Skip to main content

Full text of "The science of ethics"

See other formats


A 


n^ 


">-..<> 


\ 


THE 

Science  of  Ethics 


BY 

RT.  REV.  MGR.   MICHAEL  CRONIN,  M.A.,  D.D.,  P.P. 

Formerly  Professor  of  Ethics  and  Politics 

University  College,  Dublin 

National  University  of  Ireland 


VOLUME   I 
GENERAL    ETHICS 


THIRD   IMPRESSION 


/<5<V 


DUBLIN 

U.    H  .    GILL     AND     SON.    LTD 

50   UPPER   O'CONNELL  STREET 
1930 


&3 
(on 

V.I 

f 


c^^M 


First  Edition 1909 

Second       ,,         Revised   and    Enlarged   ...     1920 
Third  Impression  ...  ...  ...     1930 


Printed  and  Hound  in  IreUtud  al  the  I'rcss  of  the  I'lihlishers. 


PREFACE 

The  main  purpose  of  this  work  on  Ethics  is  to  present 
to  students  of  Moral  Science  a  full  and  connected 
account  of  the  ethical  system  of  Aristotle  and  St. 
Thomas  Aquinas.  To  this  system  the  author  gives 
his  fullest  assent  and  adherence,  an  adherence  which 
is  no  mere  blind  acceptance  of  a  tradition,  but  comes 
of  a  conviction  which  has  grown  stronger  and  clearer 
with  time  and  study,  that  the  general  principles  on 
which  Aristotle  builds  furnish  a  thoroughly  sound  basis 
of  moral  enquiry,  and  that  his  method  is  such  as  to 
ensure  continued  development  in  accordance  with  the 
most  rigid  requirements  of  science.  For  Ethics  is 
nothing  more  than  a  study  of  natural  law,  i.e.  the 
natural  needs  of  man  and  the  means  of  satisfying 
them,  and  the  method  emplo3ed  by  Aristotle  is 
the  direct  determination  of  those  needs  by  an 
empirical  examination  of  our  human  constitution,  our 
faculties  and  their  essential  functions  and  objects. 
Every  natural  normative  science  proceeds  in  this 
manner.  Physiology  determines  the  needs  of  the  body 
by  an  examination  of  the  organs,  their  functions  and 
ends.  Medicine  supplies  the  means  necessary  for 
meeting  these  needs.  And  not  only  the  determination 
of  our  personal,  but  of  our  social  necessities  also, 
depends  upon  the  same  method.  The  'natural  welfare 
of  the  human  race  is  found  always  in  development 
within  the  range  of  our  natural  capacities  and  their 
essential  objects. 

Nor  does  Aristotle  omit  the  study  of  what  are  called 
the  facts  of  our  moral  life,  i.e.  human  beliefs,  customs, 


iv  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

institutions,  and  laws,  a  study  which  writers  of  the 
historical  school  are  wont  to  place  in  opposition  to  what 
they  caU  the  a  'Priori  systems  of  the  older  theorists. 
These  facts  Aristotle  regards  as  of  the  highest  importance, 
because  they  are  an  indication  of  the  essential  and  per- 
manent needs  of  human  life  as  distinct  from  men's 
passing  fancies  and  desires  ;  and  therefore  the  historical 
method  is  used  by  Aristotle  to  supplement  what  can  be 
learned  by  a  direct  examination  of  our  human  con- 
stitution. There  is  no  large  requirement  or  principle  of 
the  modern  scientific  method  in  the  domain  of  morals 
that  is  not  to  be  found,  at  least  in  embryo,  in  Aristotle. 

But,  as  was  suggested  before,  the  science  of  Ethics 
has  been  enormously  developed  since  Aristotle's  day. 
This  is  especially  the  case  in  the  region  of  Applied  Ethics 
where  Morals  proper  is  now  brought  into  contact  with 
innumerable  other  spheres  of  enquiry  such  as  Ancient 
History,  Sociology,  Economics,  and  Political  Science. 
The  Appendices  to  the  chapters  in  the  second  volume 
dealing  with  Natural  Religion,  Marriage,  and  Socialism, 
will  give  some  idea  of  how  this  science  has  grown  with 
expansion  of  allied  subjects,  during  the  last  twenty-five 
years. 

A  large  part  of  the  first  volume  is  devoted  to  the  study 
of  other  sj'stems  than  that  of  Aristotle.  It  may  be 
stated  here  that  there  is  hardly  any  system  of  Ethics 
whicli  has  had  to  be  rejected  wholly,  the  author's  critic- 
isms being  directed  only  to  specific  points  in  the  opposed 
theories.  After  all,  no  sensible  or  honest  writer  is  going 
to  sit  down  and  present  the  world  with  a  theory  of  life 
and  human  conduct  in  which  there  is  not  some  truth, 
even  tliough  there  be  much  error.  For  that  reason  the 
writer  has  been  most. careful  in  the  exposition  of  these 
different  systems  to  call  the  reader's  attention  to  the 
points  where  agreement  is  possible  as  well  as  to  matters 
which  he  is  asked  to  regard  as  erroneous.  In  all  this  it 
has  been  the  author's  best  endeavour  to  be  just  to  his 
opponents.     He  hopes  that  he  has  not  misrepi  esented 


PREFACE  V 

their  views  in  an}^  way  or  stated  them  inaccurately. 
Where  possible  he  has  always  had  recourse  to  the  original 
sources  in  describing  systems,  or  stating  the  arguments 
used  in  their  defence  ;  and  when,  through  want  of  space, 
it  was  necessary  to  omit  some  of  these  arguments,  he 
has  invariably  omitted  just  those  on  which  his  opponents 
appeared  to  lay  least  stress  in  their  expositions. 

Of  modern  scholastic  writers  the  author  is  most  in- 
debted to  Professors  Meyer  and  Cathrein,  to  Rev.  Joseph 
Rickaby,  Taparelh,  Scliiffmi,  Castelein,  and  Rev.  Dr. 
Walter  McDonald,  Maynooth  College,  whose  treatises  on 
Ethics  have  been  of  immense  help  to  him  in  the  prepara- 
tion of  his  work.  His  most  grateful  thanks  are  due  to 
the  Rev.  Canon  Waters,  of  Clonliffe  College,  for  his 
kindness  in  reading  this  book  and  for  many  valuable 
criticisms  and  suggestions.  Canon  Waters'  wide  and 
minute  acquaintance  with  the  writings  of  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas  was  always  at  the  author's  disposal  in  the  task 
of  discovering  and  comparing  scattered  references, 
which,  without  such  aid,  it  would  have  been  difficult 
to  collate.  Thanks  are  also  due  to  those  gentlemen  who 
so  kindly  undertook  the  tedious  and  uninteresting  task 
of  proof-reading,  and  to  many  others  also  for  help  given 
of  various  kinds. 

It  is  the  present  writer's  earnest  hope  that  others  more 
competent  than  he  will  take  up  this  work  of  making 
known  to  the  world  the  secret  treasures  of  a  great 
philosophy — a  philosophy  which  moderns  have  too  much 
and  too  long  neglected.  Already,  of  course,  there  are 
many  labourers  in  the  field.  But  there  is  room  for 
many  more.  It  is  in  the  hope  of  helping  a  little  towards 
the  accomplishment  of  this  great  task  that  the  author 
ventures  to  publish  this  work  on  Ethics — not  without 
consciousness  of  its  many  defects.  , 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2009  with  funding  from 

Ontario  Council  of  University  Libraries 


http://www.archive.org/details/scienceofethics01cron 


/  • 


II 


CONTENTS 


CIL\PTER  I 


< 


Definition  and  Scope  of  Ethics  (pp. 

1-27)— 

PAGE 

Definition 

I 

Scope     ..... 

4 

Ethics  and  some  other  Sciences — 

Psychology 

8 

Pohtical  Philosophy  . 

10 

Moral  Theology 

.     13 

Method  of  Ethics — 

The  various  possible  methods 

.     14 

The  true  method 

20 

Possibility  of  the  Science  of  Ethics 

21 

Objections 

21 

CHAPTER  II   ^ 

Of  Human  Acts  (pp.  28-45)— 

Division  of  human  acts 28 

Of  what  makes  an  act  human  . 

31 

Of  voluntariness  in  particular     . 

33 

'               Kinds  of  voluntariness 

34 

Of  indirect  voluntariness    . 

36 

Of  what  makes  an 'act  less  human 

40 

Ignorance         .... 

40 

Violence  ..... 

42 

Passion 

.      42 

viii  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


CHAPTER  IlK 

Of  the  Ends  of  Human  Action  (pp.  46-88) —  page 

/•  Of  ends  in  general 46 

The  ultimate  end 53 

2,  The  objective  ultimate  end 54 

That  it  can  be  determined  by  Reason           .         .  54 
It  does  not  consist  in  finite  external  goods  .         .  56 
„            „             bodily  health  or  life    .         .  57 
„            ,,             pleasure  (sensuous  or  intel- 
lectual)       .         •         •  57 
„            ,,             a  state  of  the  soul,  e.g. — 

self-realisation       .  62 
holiness  or  perfec- 
tion      .         .  66 
knowledge    .         .  67 
culture          .         .  68 
„            ,,             adjustment  to  environment  69 
It  consists  in  the  Infinite  Uncreated  Good   .         .  69 
The  objective  final  end  a  reality.         .         .         -7^ 

3'  The  subjective  final  end 79 

It  consists  in  an  act 79 

of  intellect  ....  79 
Consideration  of  rival  theories  on  this  point 

(Paulsen) 81 

(Simmel) 82 

(Schopenhauer) 83 

It  does  not  require  the  exercise  of  all  the  faculties  84 

The  subjective  end  of  man  really  attainable         .  85 


CHAPTER  IV 

Of  '  Good  '  and  '  Evil  '  (pp.  89-123)— 

Meaning  of '  good  ' 89 

'  Good  '  is  object  of  appetite       .         .         .         .      8() 
'  Good  '  and  being  are  one  .        .        .         -91 


CONTENTS  ix 

Of  '  Good  '  and  '  Evil  ' — continued 

Meaning  of '  good  ' — continued  page 

'  Good  '  is  an  attribute  of  reality        ...       93 
'  Good  '  is  fulness  of  being  .         .         .         -93 

Human  '  Good  '  is  fulness  of  human  being       .       94 
'  Good '  or  fulness  of  being  of  the  human  act 

depends  upon  the  end  ....       95 

'  Good  '  is  determined  by  final  end      ...      97 
Of  the  determinants  of  Goodness       ....       97 

Are  aU  acts  good  or  bad,  or  are  there  any  indifferent 

acts  ?       .         .         .         .  ....     100 

That  there  is  a  natural  distinction  of  '  good  '  and  '  evil '    104 
I      Consideration  of  Positivist   theories,   or  of  theories 
J  which  deny  natural  distinctions — Hobbes,  Rous- 

^  seau,  Camcades,  Nietzsche,  Paulsen,  Occam  and 

Fuffcndorff 114 

Theory  of  extrinsic  morality      .         .         .         .         .120 
„        independent  morality         .         .         .         .122 


CHAPTER  V 


y 


The  Moral  Criteria  (pp.  124-174) — 

Meaning  of  Criterion         ......  124 

Division  of  Criteria           ......  125 

Need  of  a  Criterion  in  Ethics    .....  126 

The  primary  or  fundamental  Ethical  Criterion    .         ,  127 

Conditions  of    ......         .  127 

The  criterion  determined   .....  129 

applied 133 

Range  of  application  of  this  criterion        .         .  135 
The  secondary  or  derivative  criteria — 

General  injury  with  general  observance        .         .  140 

(Note  on  Ethical  Optimism) 

Common  human  convictions       ....  153 

The  moral  feelings .         .         .         .         -155 

Some  general  remarks  on  the  criteria          .         .         .  157 
Some  difficulties  against  the  system  of  Natural  Morals 

considered        .......  160 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


CHAPTER  VI 

EEDOM  AND  MORALITY   (j^p.  I75-I95) — 

PAGE 

Meaning  of  freedom          ..... 

175 

View  of  Wiindt          .         .         .         .         . 

179 

„       Caldervvood  ..... 

180 

„      Hamilton  and  Kant 

180 

„      Reid 

180 

Wundt's  view  of  the  Scholastic  definition     . 

180 

Ed.  von  Hartmann's  view  of  freedom 

180 

Ground  of  freedom  ...... 

181 

Extent  of  freedom 

185 

Freedom  and  the  law  of  Conservation  of  Energy 

187 

Consequence  of  freedom  ..... 

189 

Kantian  theory  of  freedom        .... 

190 

Hegelian  theory  of  freedom       .... 

192 

CHAPTER  VII 

Freedom  and  Morality  (pp.  196-210) — 

Necessity  of  freedom  for  morality      ....  196 

for  moral  distinctions 197 

„       obligation  ......  198 

for  imputability  and  punisliment         .         .         .  201 

Leslie  Stephen's  view  of  freedom  and  punishment  203 

Butler's  view  of  freedom  and  punishment          .  204 

The  practical  bearing  of  this  question  of  the  relation 

of  freedom  to  morals    ......  206 

Kant's  theory  tiiat  freedom  and  morality  are  one        .  209 


CHAPTER  VIII 

y  Of  Duty  (pp.  211-255)— 

The  prol)lcm  c.vplained     . 

Pr(K)f  of  duty  .         .         .         . 

The  ;il)s()lti(c  charadcr  of  (lul\ . 


211 
214 

210 


CONTENTS  ki 

Of  Duty — continued  page 

Some  statements  of  philosophers  confirmatory  of  our 
proof  of  duty  (Taparelli,  Kickaby,  Simmel, 

Sidgwick,  Ed,  von  Hartmann,  Fouillee)        .  222 

A  difficulty  (duty  and  freedom)          .         .         .'         .  224 
/    Two  Corollaries — 

/            Concerning  a  view  of  Sidgwick  on  duty       .         .  228 

the  theory  of  independent  duty         .  229 
Other  theories  of  Duty — 

Duty  a  willing  of  the  totality  of  ends  (Lipps)        .  231 

I                      „      disjunctive  necessity  (Meyer)  .         .         .  234 

-Theory  of  Intuitionism  (Butler,  &c.)    .         .         .  234 

r-Positivist  theory       ......  240 

Associationist  form  of  (Mill)    ....  241 

Evolutionist  form  of  (Spencer)          .         .         .  242 

Ethics  without  duty  (Guyau)      ....  247 

Appendix-^Kant's  deduction  of  liberty  from  duty       .  254 


CHAPTER  IX 

On  Kantian  Formalism  (pp.  256-274) — 

Explanation  of  theory  as  formulated  by  Kant     .         .  256 

Disproof  of  theory  .......  257 

Argiunents  of  the  formalists  discussed        .         .         .  2C6 


CHAPTER  X 

On  Hedonism  (pp.  275-317) — 

Explanation  and  history  of  theory  of  Hedonism.         .     275 
Aquinas'  arguments  against  the  Hedonistic  principle 

that  pleasure  is  our  final  end        .         .         .     280— 
Arguments  of  Psychological  Hedonists  (Mill)      .         .     289 
„  Ethical  Hedonists  (Sidgsvick)         .         .     300 

Empirical  (Mill)  and  Scientific  (Spencer)  Hedonism — 

their  criterion     ......     302 

Mill's  theory  of  qualitative  distinctions  in  jiieasurcs 

examined  .......     311 


xii  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

CHAPTER  XI    y 

Of  Utilitarianism  (pp.  318-37^) —  page 

Definition        .         .         .  s  '    .         .         .         .         .  318 

Utilitarianism — how  far  true 319 

Disproof  of  the  Utilitarian  principle  that  the  well- 
being  of  Society  is  man's  final  end        .         .321 

The  Utilitarian  criterion  examined    ....  325 

Examination    of    the    arguments    for   Utihtarianism 
drawn  from  the  following  : — 

"  The  Benevolent  Impulses "      .         .                  .  331 

"  Hedonism "  .         .         .         .         .         .         .  339 

"  Moral  good  as  categorical  and  universal "           .  348 

"  Ccmimon  conception  of  morals "       .         .         .  350 

"Pragmatism"                  353 

"  Theory  of  solidarity  of  Society  "       .         .         .  356 
"  The  moral  intuitions "             .         .         .         .  365 
Appefidix— Theory  of  Moral  Values  considered   .         .  367 
„          Hedonism  and  Utilitarianism,  their  recon- 
ciliation    369 


CHAPTER  XII 

Evolution  and  Ethics  (pp.  372-441) — 

Theory  of  Biological  Evolution  (Spencer)  . 

Note  on  Leslie  Stephen's  theory 
Criticism  of  Spencer's  theory — 

Whether  the  moral  law  evolves  . 
Spencer's  assumptions  examined 

„       argument  depending  on  development  in 

structure  and  function  examined  . 

Theory  that  life  is  man's  final  end  disproved 

Spencer's  two  criteria — viz.,  "  Adjustment  to  en 

vironinent  "  and  "  Health  "  examined  . 

Theory  of  Psychological  Evolution — 

Statement  of  theory  .... 


373 
383 

387 
393 

408 
•III 

413 
424 


CONTENTS  xiii 

Evolution  and  Eimcs— continued 

Criticism —  page 

Moral  beliefs  sho\\n  to  be  derived  from  reasoning  428 
Associations  of  pleasure  and  pain  not  the  source 

of  moral  beliefs 430 

A   special   form   of   this   theory   depending   on 

principle  of  "  Natural  Selection  "  examined  .  434 

Question  of  origin  and  validity — how  they  are  related  440 


(CHAPTER  XIII 

Evolution  {con.).    Ethics  of  Transcendental  Evolu- 
tion (pp.  442-471)— 

Statement  of  theory 442 

Hegel's  form  of  theory 445 

Green's  form  of  theory 448 

Criticism  of  the  theory  of  Transcendental  Evolution    .  451 

Note  on  Self-realisation    ......  461 

Appendix — Spinoza's  system     .....  466 

Fichte's  system 468 


CHAPTER  XIV 

The  Moral  Faculty  (pp.  472-505) — 

^he  faculty  defined 472 

ConsicJ^ation  of  erroneous  views  : — 

Conscience  a  distinct  faculty  (Hume)  . 

„         a  feeling  (Leslie  Stephen,  Fichte) 
„         a  sense  (Hutcheson)  . 
„  the  Universal  Reason  (Hegel) 

,,         the  Voice  of  God  (Butlor)  . 
*^ Appendix — Of  Probabilism       .... 


CHAPTER  XV 


475 
480 
486 
491 
497 
504 


Of  Intuitionism  (pp.  506-536) — 

Statement  of  question 506 


XIV 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


Of  Intuitionism — continued.  page 

Exposition  of  author's  view      .....     507 

Other  views  examined — 

Perceptive  Intuitionism  (Mansell,  McCosh)  .         .518 
Common  Sense  Intuitionism  (Reid)      .         .         .     522 
iEsthetic  Morals  (Schiller,  Herbart,  Shaftesbury, 

Hutcheson)         ......     525 

Moral  Impulse  theory  (Martineau)       .         .         .     530 


CHAPTER  XVI 


Of  Synderesis  (pp.  537-572) — 

Statement  of  doctrine 

On  the  origin  of  a  child's  moral  beliefs 

Can  Conscience  develop  and  decay  ? 

Unethical  man         .... 

Of  the  moral  beliefs  of  savages   . 

Of  the  "  homo  sapiens  ferus  "     . 

Appendix — ^Theories  concerning  differences  in  moral 

codes  of  different  natidns  (Kittel,  Elsenlians) . 


537 
539 
547 
550 
551 
568 

571 


CHAPTER  XVII 


The  Consequences  of  Morality  (pp.  573-592) — 

Of  Rectitude ^        •  573 

Of  Imputability 574 

Of  Merit,  Its  kinds 574 

Its  conditions  .......  577 

Witli  whom  can  we  merit  ?         .         .         .         .  578 

Erroneous  views  on  merit — 

Merit  implies  effort  (Leslie  Stephen)      .         .  578 
„     attaclics  only  to  works  of  supereroga- 
tion (Leslie  Stephen)     ....  579 

Inverse  ratio  of  merit  and  virtue  (Martineau 

and  Shaftesbuiy)  .         .         .  580 

Theory  that  virtue  implies  struggle  (Royce)  .  581 


CONTENTS 


X'/ 


The  Consequences  of  Moraluy— continued  page 

Of  Demerit 5^4 

Punishment  as  retributive  ....     586 

„  emendatory  and  deterrent    .         .     589 


CHAEIgRJ^n  ^ 


Of  Habits  and  Virtues  (pp.  593-632)- 

- 

Of  Habits 593 

Virtue  and  Vice  in  general 

.    595 

The  Intellectual  Virtues  . 

.    596 

PiTiduic^,. 

.    598 

The  Moral  Virtues  . 

.    604 

The  Cardinal  Virtues 

.    613 

Of  Temperance 

.    616 

Of  Fortitude  . 

.    618 

Of  Justice 

.     621 

Just;ice  a  natural  virtue 

.    625 

Hume's  objections 

.    626 

Justice  an  objective  virtue 

.    628 

Opposed  theory  of  Hume 

.    630 

.)             )> 

Sid 

gwick 

.    630 

CHAPTER  XIX 


Of  Law  (pp.  633-659)— 

General  Conception  of  Law 

. 

•     633 

Note  on  Natural  Selection  and  Law 

.     635 

The  Various  kinds  of  Law 

•     639 

The  Eternal  Law 

. 

.    639 

The  Natural  Law 

.     643 

Jus  gentium 

. 

.     648 

Human  Law     . 

. 

.     650 

Theory  of  Autonomy — 

Autonomy  of  Reason  (Kant) 

. 

.     652 

Will  (Lipps) 

•     657 

Immanent  Heteronomy  (Ed. 

von  Hartmann) 

.     658 

\^ 


xvi  •  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


On  Rights  (pp.  660-686) —  page 

—Notion  of  Right       ....                  .         .  660 

Properties  of  Right — 

Inviolability 662 

Limitation        .......  662 

Coaction 663 

Erroneous  theories  on  relation  of  Right  to 

Coaction  (Ihering,  Hegel,  Thomasius)     .  663 

Division  of  Rights 666 

Perfect  and  Impsrfect  Rights           .         .         .  667 

That  some  Rights  are  natural 669 

Objections  of  Historical  School  (Neukamp,  &c.)  .  670 

Relation  of  Right  to  Morality 673 

Erroneous  theories  on  origin  and  principle  of  Right — 
Theory  that   all  Rights  come   from  the   State 

(Hobbes,  &c.)     ......  676 

Theory   that   all   Rights   originate   in   Contract 

(Fichte,&c.) 678 

Theory  of  Historical  School  that  all  Rights  origi- 
nate in  Custom  (Savigny,  Neukamp,  &c.)     .  679 
"  Mechanical "  theory  of  principle  of  Right  (Kant)  683 


APPENDIX 
Kant's  Criterion  of  Goodness.  The  Categorical  Imperative  687 


THE 

SCIENCE    OF    ETHICS 

CHAPTER    I 
DEFINITION   AND   SCOPE  OF  ETHICS 

{a)  Definition 

Ethics  may  be  defined  as  "  the  science  of  human  con- 
duct as  according  with  human  Reason  and  as  directed 
by  Reason  towards  man's  final  natural  end,"  or,  it  is 
"  the  science  of  moral  good  and  evil  in  human  acts." 
The  former  of  these  two  definitions  we  expound  as 
follows : — • 

(i)  Ethics  is  a  science  and  not  merely  an  art. 

An  art  and  a  science  differ  mainly  in  their  object  or 
purpose.  The  end  of  an  art  is  to  facilitate  action — that 
of  a  science  is  to  discover  truth.  Now,  the  end  of 
Ethics  is  to  discover  moral  truths — to  establish,  in  the 
first  place,  the  general  moral  principles,  and  then  to 
deduce  from  these  the  laws  which  govern  human  action 
in  particular  cases.  Ethics  is  therefore  a  science — a 
practical  science  of  course,  not  a  theoretic  science,  since 
its  end  is  to  direct  action. 

Besides  the  science  of  Ethics  there  exists  also  an 
art  that  has  to  do  with  the  regulation  of  conduct,  and 
which  is  named  the  art  of  good  conduct.  But  these 
two  disciplines  are  quite  distinct.  The  end  of  Ethics 
is,  as  we  said,  to  tell  us  what  is  good  and  what  is  evil 
— the  art  of  good  conduct  tells  us  how  we  may  do  the 
Vol.  I.— I  I 


2  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

good  and  avoid  evil  with  greater  ease  and  security. 
For  instance,  the  art  of  good  conduct  tells  a  man  when 
and  in  what  circumstances  he  should  fly  temptations  to 
evil,  and  when  and  how  he  ought  to  face  temptation  ; 
also,  how  a  man  should  set  about  the  acquiring  of  a 
virtue,  and  how  he  may  best  retain  it  when  acquired. 
Counsels  of  this  kind  may,  indeed,  sometimes  be  found 
in  works  on  Ethics,  but  they  are  not  essential  to  the 
science  of  Ethics,  nor  are  they  in  strictness  included  in 
its  object.  Ethics  does  not  aim  at  telling  a  man  how 
!  to  do  good  or  how  to  strengthen  his  will  against  evil, 
but  only  tells  him  what  is  good  and  what  is  evil.  In 
this  sense  we  find  it  said  that  Ethics  supplies  no  moral 
dynamics — that  is,  its  aim  is,  at  least  primarily,  not  to 
purify  and  strengthen  the  will,  but  to  inform  the  Reason 
— that  is,  to  enable  the  Reason  to  form  correct  moral 
judgments  about  the  right  order  of  conduct. 

(2)  It  is  the  science  of  conduct  as  directed  by  Reason. 

Human  Reason  bears  a  two-fold  relation  to  the  order 

of   objects  in  the  Universe.     First,   there  is   an  order 

which   human    Reason   merely   considers   but    does   not 

make,   like   the   order   of   the   heavenly   bodies   or   the 

order  exhibited  in  the  growing  plant.     Secondly,  there 

is   an   order  which   Reason   not   merely   considers,   but 

also  constitutes — an  order  which  Reason  sets  up  in  things 

like   the   order   of   a   well-arranged   house.    Now,   the 

order  which  is  considered  in  Ethics  is  of  the  second 

kind.*    The  ethical  or  moral  order  is  an  order  which 

I  the  human   Reason  itself  introduces  into  conduct — an 

order  which  belongs  to  conduct  in  so  far  as  it  is  under 

the  control  of  Reason. 

•  This  doctrine  of  St.  Thoma.s,  that  the  moral  order  of  the  human 
act  is  set  up  in  the  act  by  human  Reason,  is  to  be  carefully  distinguished 
from  IIk-  Kantian  theory  of  th<'  autonomy  of  Keason-  Ihc  theory, 
namely,  that  the  moral  law  springs  from  our  own  Koason.  Accord- 
ing to  St.  Thomas,  Reason  .sets  up  in  the  human  act  the  right  order, 
but,  in  doing  so,  it  follows  laws  that  spring  not  from  Reason  itsell 
but  from  nature.  According  to  Kant,  Reason  not  only  directs  the 
act,  but  also  creates  the  laws  according  to  which  the  actshculd  be 
directed. 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS  3 

This  order  which  Reason  sets  up  in  human  action  is 
not  an  arbitrary  order,  but  depends  on  certain  fixed 
and  necessary  laws,  and  it  is  the  business  of  Ethics  to  /^ 
formulate  these  laws,  to  say  when  conduct  accords  with'' 
them  or  is  good  and  rational  and  when  it  does  not  ac- 
cord with  them  or  is  evil  and  irrational.  In  this  sense 
we  define  Ethics  as  the  science  of  conduct  as  directed  or 
controlled  by  Reason. 

(3)  It  is  the  science  of  "  human  conduct." 

Ethics  has  to  do  with  conduct  or  with  human  actions 
only.  This  implies  three  things.  Jit&t,  it  has  to  do 
with  man  only.  Animal  conduct  is  subject  to  certain 
laws.  The  acts  of  angels  are  also  subject  to  law.  But 
Ethics  takes  cognisance  onl}^  of  one  kind  of  act  and  one 
kind  of  law.  It  has  to  do  with  human  actions  only. 
Secondly,  when  we  say  that  Ethics  relates  to  conduct, 
we  mean  that  it  has  to  do  with  deliberate  acts  only  , 
{actus  humani),  with  acts  that  proceed  from  and  are 
controlled  by  Reason  [qui  a  voluntate  deliberaia  proced- 
tint)  ;*  it  has  nothing  to  do  with  indeliberate  acts, 
which  are  in  no  sense  from  Reason  [cicius  hominis). 
TMrdl}^  the  science  of  Ethics  has  to  do  with  actions, 
not  ^ith  states  or  permanent  conditions  of  mind,  for 
instance,,  our  character,!  except  indeed  in  so  far  as  our 
acts  affect  our  character.  It  is  only  our  actions  that 
fall  directly  under  our  control  or  are  deliberate,  and  as 
we  saw,  Ethics  has  to  do  only  with  what  is  deliberate. 

*  "  Sic  ergo  moralis  philosophiae  proprium  est  considerare  opera- 
tiones  humanas  secundum  quod  sunt  ordinatae  ad  invicem  et  ad  finem. 
Dico  autem  operationes  humanas  quae  procedunt  a  voluntate  hominis 
secundum  ordinem  rationis.  Nam  si  quae  operationes  in  homine 
inveniuntur  quae  non  subjacent  voluntati  et  rationi,  non  dicuntur 
proprie  humariae,  sed  naturales,  sicut  patet  de  operationibus  animae 
vegetativae,  quae  nullo  modo  cadunt  sub  consideratione  moralis 
philosophiae.  Sicut  autem  subjectum  philosophiae  naturalis  est 
motus  vel  res  mobilis  ita  subjectum  moralis  philosophiae  est  operatio 
humana  ordinata  ad  finem  vel  etiam  homo  prout  est  voluntarie  agens 
propter  finem  "  (Aquinas,  "  Commentaries  on  Aristotle,"  Ethicorum, 
Lib.  I.,  Lect.  I.). 

f  According  to  Hume,  Schopenhauer,  and  most  evolutionists, 
"  character  "  and  not  action  is  the  proper  subject-matter  of  Ethics 


4  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(4)  "  As  directed  to  tnan's  final  natural  end." 

Other  sciences,  like  Ph3^sics,  treat  of  the  efficient 
causes  of  human  action.  Ethics  treats  of  the  final 
causes  or  the  ends  of  conduct.  It  treats  in  particular 
of  the  final  end  and  of  other  ends  as  leading  to  the 
final  end.  Ethics  tells  us  what  acts  will  lead  us  to  our 
final  end  or  are  morally  good,  and  what  will  lead  us 
away  from  it  or  are  bad,  that  apt  being  morally  good 
which  is  directed  by  Reason  to  the  final  end,  its  opposite 
being  morally  evil.  In  Ethics  the  final  end  holds  the 
same  place  and  exercises  the  same  function  that  the 
first  principles  do  in  the  speculative  sciences.  For  as 
reasoning  begins  with  principles  so  action  depends  on 
and  begins  with  "  end."  The  last  end  will  be  the  first 
ground  of  action,  since  it  is  that  which  moves  to  the 
attainment  of  all  other  intermediate  ends. 


(&)  Scope  of  the  Science  of  Ethics 

In  our  definition  of  Ethics  we  have  already  im- 
plicitly indicated  its  scope.  The  scope  of  Ethics  is  the 
formulation  and  establishment  of  the  laws  of  human 
conduct — those  laws  following  which  conduct  tends  to 
man's  ultimate  end  and  is  good,  violating  which  conduct 
is  bad. 

Ethics  is  thus  a  normative  science — it  prescribes  norms 
or  rules  of  action.  In  this  it  resembles  many  other 
sciences,  like  Medicine,  which  also  is  normative,  since  it 
prescribes  laws  of  health,  laws  following  which  we  shall 
be  healthy,  neglecting  which  we  cannot  be  healthy. 

Now,  many  modern  ethicians  take  quite  another 
view — a  very  erroneous  view — of  the  scope  and  subject- 
matter  of  Ethics.  They  maintain  that  the  proper 
subject-matter  of  Ethics  is  not  the  laws  of  morals,  the 
laws  to  which  conduct  ought  to  conform,  but  what  they 
call  tlu'  fads  of  Ethics — by  which  thoy  moan  the  moral 
cubtouis  and  beliefs  of  various  peoples  in  diifercnt  ages 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS  5 

and  under  different  conditions,  the  scope  of  Ethics 
being,  according  to  these  ethicians,  to  describe  and 
correlate  these  facts  (without  reference  to  their  being 
right  or  wrong) — to  give  their  origin  and  the  law  of  their 
development. 

The  difference  between  what  moderns  call  laws  and 
facts  can  best  be  illustrated  from  architecture.  We 
assign  the  laws  of  architecture  when  we  say  how  build- 
ings oiight  to  be  constructed.  The  facts  of  architecture 
would  be  the  history  of  men's  views  on  architecture  or 
an  account  of  the  fashions  that  have  prevailed  in  archi- 
tecture at  different  periods  and  in  different  places.  But 
whereas  we  do  not  find  that  any  architect  has  ever 
described  his  science  as  a  history  of  men's  views  on,  or 
of  fashions  in  architecture  (this  he  would  call  the  history 
not  the  science  of  architecture),  we  do,  as  we  have  said, 
find  ethicians  who  claim  that  the  business  of  moral 
science  is  merely  to  explain  and  correlate  men's  views 
on  morals  *  and  the  customs  to  which  these  views  have 
given  rise. 

We  are  indebted  to  Professor  Sorley  for  an  interest- 
ing account  and  a  valuable  criticism  of  this  theory, 
from  which  we  may  be  permitted  to  quote  the  following  : 
"  The  enquiries,"  he  writes,t  "  commonly  described  as 
ethical  comprise  two  kinds  of  questions  which  differ 
fundamentall}^  from  one  another  in  scope,  and  require 
the  employment  of  distinct  methods  for  their  solution. 
On  the  one  hand,  there  are  the  fads  of  human  conduct, 
the  customs  and  institutions  to  which  it  gives  rise  and 
the  sentiments  and  ideas  by  which  it  is  accompanied. 
All  these  are  facts  in  time  whose  genesis  and  history 
may  be  investigated  by  appropriate  historical  methods. 
On  the  other  hand,  there  is  a  question  of  different  scope 
which  no  amount   of  history  could  solve.     This  is  the 


*  Amongst  the  most  prominent  members  of  this  School  is  M. 
Levy-Bruhl.  His  views  are  to  be  foimd  in  a  remarkable  work, 
entitled  "  La  Morale  et  La  Science  des  Mocurs." 

f  "  Ethics  of  Naturalism,"  page  310. 


6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

question  of  the  value  or  worth  of  conduct  and  the  truth 
of  the  judgments  which  men  pass  upon  it.  The  ques- 
tion is  no  longer  how  the  action  came  to  be  performed 
or  the  judgments  passed  upon  it  arose,  but  whether  the 
action  was  right  and  whether  our  moral  judgments  are 
true  judgments." 

And  again  * — "  It  is  an  irrelevant  answer  to  the  ques- 
tion, '  what  is  the  good,'  when  we  are  given  a  mere 
record  of  men's  ideas  about  what  is  good  and  of  the 
way  in  which  these  opinions  arose.  We  ask  about  the 
validity  of  moral  judgments,  and  are  put  off  by  specu- 
lations concerning  their  history.  The  strictly  ethical 
question  is  thus  disregarded." 

According,  then,  to  Professor  Sorley  the  strictly 
ethical  question  is  not  what  men  have  thought  about 
the  laws  of  conduct  or  how  our  moral  ideals  have 
originated,  but  "  wiiat  are  the  laws  of  right  conduct — 
what  should  conduct  be  .-^  "  This,  of  course,  is  also  the 
view  taken  by  Aristotle  and  by  St.  Thomas  Aquinas. 

The  view  taken  by  our  opponents  on  this  point — for 
instance,  by  M.  Levy-Bruhl — is,  we  maintain,  opposed 
to  the  whole  conception  of  the  scope  and  subject-matter 
of  a  science.  As  well  might  we  confine  the  science  of 
Physics  to  the  description  and  correlation  of  the  various 
views  of  physicists  at  different  periods  as  to  say  that 
the  exclusive  purpose  of  Ethics  is  to  describe  the  history 
of  men's  views  on  good  and  evil,  and  the  practices  to 
which  these  views  have  given  rise.  Of  course,  if  it 
could  be  shown  that  conduct  has  no  laws,  that  it  is  all 
the  same  to  a  man  whether  he  is  drunk  or  sober,  honest 
or  dishonest,  that  the  supposition  of  laws  for  conduct 
is  purely  a  figment  of  our  imaginations,  then  certainly 
we  should  admit  that  the  study  of  morals  could  mean 
no  more  than  the  study  of  opinions  on  matters  of  con- 
duct. But,  apart  altogether  from  the  scientific  proof  of 
morality  wliich  we  hope  to  give  in  the  present  work,  it 
should  be  evident  even  from  common  sense  that  human 

*  "  EthicK  (A  NuluruliHiii,"  patiP  ^20. 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS  7 

conduct  is  not  without  its  laws.  We  have  only  to  open 
our  eyes  and  see  what  men  come  to  through  intem- 
perance, and  to  consider  what  society  would  come  to 
were  there,  for  instance,  no  such  thing  as  marriage  con- 
tracts, in  order  to  know  that  human  conduct  is  subject 
to  laws  of  some  kind,  that  it  has  requirements  just  as  a 
tree  has  requirements,  that  it  is  not  the  same  to  a  man 
and  society  whether  we  follow  one  set  of  courses  or  the 
opposite  set — in  other  words,  whether  we  do  good  or 
evil.  At  present  we  do  not  say  what  is  the  nature  of 
the  laws  of  conduct,  what  the  "good  "  is  and  what 
evil  is,  or  to  what  end  the  laws  of  conduct  should  guide 
us.  We  only  insist  that  there  are  courses  that  are 
necessary  for  us  and  courses  that  are  ruinous,  and 
therefore  that  human  conduct  is  really  subject  to  laws 
of  some  kind.  That  being  the  case,  it  is  evident  that 
the  science  of  Ethics,  which  is  the  science  of  human 
conduct,  deals  not  with  the  growth  of  ethical  views  and 
customs,  but  with  the  laws  of  conduct,  just  as  Physics 
deals  not  only  with  opinions  about  the  phenomena  of 
nature,  but  with  the  objective  phenomena  themselves. 
The  purpose  of  Physics  is  the  establishment  of  the  laws 
of  physical  nature.  The  purpose  or  scope  of  Ethics  is 
the  establishment  of  the  laws  of  human  conduct.  The^ 
correlation  or  history  of  the  views  and  customs  of 
different  peoples  at  different  periods  may,  indeed,  be 
interesting  on  its  own  account,  and  we  might  even  find 
a  place  for  such  questions  in  Ethics,  as  leading  indirectly 
to  a  right  view  of  the  good  and  evil  of  certain  acts. 
But  these  views  and  customs  are  no  part  of  the  direct 
object  of  Ethics. 

(c)  Ethics  and  some  other  Sciences 

Having  defined  absolutely  the  science  of  Ethics,  we 
turn  now  to  define  it  relatively — in  other  words,  to 
determine  its  boundaries  and  to  show  where  it  differs 
from  the  other  sciences,  or  at  least  from  those  that  are 
more  or  less  closely  connected  with  it. 


8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

ETHICS  AND  PSYCHOLOGY 

We  shall  draw  out  the  distinction  between  these  two 
sciences  step  by  step.  In  the  first  place,  Ethics  has  a 
narrower  object  than  Psychology,  for  Psychology  treats 
of  every  act  of  man,  whereas  Ethics  treats  of  deliberate 
acts  only.  Second^,  even  deliberate  human  actions 
are  considered  very  differently  by  the  psychologist  and 
the  ethician.  For  whereas  Ps3xhology  treats  of  these 
actions  in  every  aspect — as  regards  their  origin,  the 
conditions  of  their  existence,  their  relations  to  one 
another,  and  their  relations  to  the  various  faculties 
and  to  the  natural  ends  of  the  faculties — Ethics  treats 
of  them  in  this  latter  way  onlj-,  that  is,  in  their  relation 
to  natural  ends.  Hence,  whilst  the  psychologist  is  like 
the  geographer,  who  tells  us  everything  about  a  road — 
its  length,  its  position  in  respect  to  other  roads,  &;c. — 
the  ethician  is  like  the  traveller  who  is  interested  in  one 
question  only — namely,  whether  a  particular  road  leads 
to  the  town  he  is  seeking,  and  how. 

So  far,  however.  Psychology  is  but  the  wider  science 
and  not  specifically  distinct  from  Ethics.  Some  ethi- 
cians  have  stopped  here,  and  been  content  to  draw 
this  mere  quantitative  distinction  between  the  two 
sciences.  They  sometimes  formulate  it  thus — whereas 
Psychology  treats  of  the  origin  and  nature  and  ends  of 
our  acts.  Ethics  treats  of  their  end  only,  and,  therefore, 
of  their  goodness  or  badness.  But  it  is  evident  that  if 
Ethics  is  not  to  be  accounted  a  chapter  of  Psychology 
it  must  differ  from  that  science  qualitatively  as  well  as 
quantitatively — that  is,  it  must  concern  the  human  act 
under  a  separate  aspect,  an  aspect  which  the  psycholo- 
gist does  not  consider. 

The  existence  of  a  qualitative  distinction  between 
Ethics  and  Psychology  is  clearly  shown  by  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas  in  his  "  Commentaries  on  Aristotle."  * 
"Order,"  he  writes,  "bears  a  fourfold  relation  to 
Reason.     There  is  first,   the  order  which   Reason   does 

•  I.ilier  primus  FJhicorum.     Lectio  I, 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS         g 

not  establish,  but  merely  considers  *  {quern  ratio  non 
jacit  sed  solum  considcrat),  as  is  the  case  with  natural 
things  {i.e.,  physical  nature).  There  is  also  an  order 
which  Reason  itself  by  considering  sets  up  (or  estab- 
lishes) in  its  own  act — for  instance,  the  proper  order- 
ing of  the  concepts  to  one  another.  ...  A  third  '  order  ' 
is  that  which  Reason  sets  up  in  the  operations  of  the 
will.  A  fourth  is  that  which  Reason  sets  up  or  estab- 
lishes in  external  things  in  so  far  as  they  are  made  by 
Reason.  (Now)  .  .  ,  these  different  kinds  of  order  give 
rise  to  different  sciences.  Natural  Philosophy,  includ- 
ing Metaphysics  (under  Natural  Philosophy  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas  also  includes  Psychology),  regards  that  order 
which  Reason  discovers  but  does  not  itself  establish. 
Rational  Philosophy  {i.e.,  Logic)  regards  the  order 
which  Reason  itself  sets  up  in  its  own  act,  for  Logic 
regards  the  order  of  terms  in  a  judgment  and  of  pre- 
misses to  conclusions.  Moral  Philosoph}'^  has  to  do 
with  the  order  of  our  voluntary  actions  (an  order  which 
Reason  sets  up  or  establishes  in  the  human  will). 
Finally,  there  is  the  order  of  the  mechanical  arts,  an 
order  which  Reason  sets  up  in  external  objects  in  so 
far  as  external  objects  are  subject  to  or  constituted  by 
Reason."  j 

We  see,  then,  that  the  order  which  is  contemplated 
in  Ethics  is  not  one  (to  use  a  modern  expression)  which 
is  given  to  Reason,  but  rather  an  order  which  Reason 
itself  sets  up  in  the  acts  of  the  will.  Its  specific  object 
is  "an  order  in  human  acts  to  be  established  by  Reason." 
In  Psychology,  on  the  other  hand.  Reason  merely  plays 
the  part  of  knower.  It  tells  us  what  are  the  objects  of 
the  faculties,  what  are  the  relations  between  the  faculties 
and  the  soul,  &c.  In  other  words,  whereas  Psychology 
treats  of  what  is.  Ethics  treats  of  an  "  order  "  in  our 
acts  which  perhaps  is  not,  but  which,  if  conduct  is  to  be 
rational,  ought  to  be,  and  which  can  only  be  set  up  in 

*  The  distinction  has  already  been  mentioned,  page  2. 
f  See  note,  page  2. 


10  ,  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  will  by  Reason  itself.  Pyscholog3%  then,  like  Mathe- 
matics and  Physics,  treats  of  mere  facts  or  actual 
happenings  of  mind.  Ethics  is,  like  Logic  and  certain 
of  the  arts,  normative.  It  lays  down  rules  of  action. 
And  even  amongst  normative  sciences  it  has  a  specific 
difference  of  its  own — namely,  that  the  order  which  it 
contemplates  is  an  order  of  acts  not  to  any  proximate 
or  intermediate  end,  but  to  the  final  end  of  our  whole 
being — the  summum  bonum. 

But  though  Ethics  is  a  distinct  science  from  Psycho- 
logy, it  is  yet  in  many  points  dependent  on  Psychology. 
For,  first,  it  is  from  Psychology  that  we  learn  the 
freedom  of  the  will  or  the  fact  that  Reason  is  able  to 
control  our  actions.  Again,  it  is  from  Psychology  we 
learn  what  are  the  ends  and  objects  of  the  various 
faculties,  and  it  is  through  the  information  thus  ob- 
tained that  Reason  is  enabled  to  set  up  in  our  wills  the 
necessary  ethical  order,  the  order  of  act  to  final  end. 
In  this  way,  just  as  the  traveller  gets  his  information 
from  the  geographer,  so  does  the  ethician  from  the 
psychologist.  But  still  Ethics  is  not  to  be  identified 
with  Psychology,  nor  with  any  chapter  in  Psychology. 
It  is  a  distinct  science,  since  the  aspect  under  which 
conduct  is  related  to  our  human  Reason  is  different  in 
the  two  sciences. 


ETHICS  AND  POLITICAL  PHILOSOPHY 

We  meet  in  recent  ethical  literature  with  two  remark- 
able and  quite  opposed  accounts  of  the  relation  in  which 
Ethics  stands  to  Politics.  One  tends  to  separate  the 
two  sciences  altogether  ;  the  other  tends  to  make  Ethics 
a  part  of  Political  Science.  The  first  view  is  advo- 
cated by  Kant  and  his  many  disciples.  The  second 
by  the  modern  utilitarians.  In  the  first  view,  whereas 
Moral  Philosophy  concerns  itself  with  the  individual 
conscience  and  with  the  inner  act  as  subject  to  con- 
science,   Political    Philosophy   concerns   itself   with    the 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        ii 

laws  and  interests  of  the  State  and  with  external  acts. 
In  the  second  view,  morality  is  regarded  as  identical 
with  the  good  of  the  race,  and  the  science  of  Ethics  as 
identical  with  the  science  of  the  racial  interest  in  so 
far  at  least  as  the  racial  interest  can  be  promoted  by 
individual  effort,  and  gives  rise  to  individual  responsi- 
bility. Ethics  is  thus,  in  the  utilitarian  system,  identi- 
fied with  Politics  regarded  as  the  science  of  the  social 
good,  whereas  in  the  first  or  Kantian  system  the  two 
sciences  stand  completely  apart. 

Now,  the  view  taken  in  the  present  work  is  that 
Ethics  is  neither  distinct  from  Political  Philosophy  nor 
identical  with  it  ;  that,  on  the  contrary,  Political 
Philosophy  is  merely  a  branch  of  Ethics,  that  as  Ethics 
considers  the  actions  of  men  in  regard  to  our  last  end, 
both  in  our  character  as  individuals  and  as  members 
of  society.  Political  Philosophy  considers  the  acts  of 
men  as  citizens  or  as  members  of  society  only,  and 
directs  the  lawgiver  as  to  the  best  way  to  rule  the 
citizens  so  as  to  obtain  the  ends  of  society. 

On  this  question  of  the  relation  of  Ethics  to  Political 
Philosophy,  it  may  be  well  to  quote  the  argument  of 
St.  Thomas.  Having  determined  the  general  subject- 
matter  of  Ethics— that  is,  human  operations  as  directed 
by  Reason  to  the  last  end — he  writes  : — "  It  should, 
however,  be  mentioned  that  man  is  a  social  animal 
inasmuch  as  many  things  are  necessary  for  his  life 
which  he  himself  as  an  individual  could  not  procure  : 
from  which  it  follows  that  according  to  the  design  of 
nature  man  is  to  be  considered  a  member  of  a  multitude 
which  is  (nature's)  means  for  affording  him  the  neces- 
sary help  in  the  proper  ordering  of  his  life.  This  neces- 
sary help  extends  to  two  classes  of  requirements.  First, 
it  extends  to  things  necessary  for  life,  without  which 
the  present  life  could  not  continue  ;  and  in  this  respect 
man  is  a  member  of  the  domestic  multitude  (or  of  the 
family),  since  it  is  from  our  parents  that  we  receive 
life,  support,  and  education.  .  .  .  Secondly,  as  members 


12  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of  another  multitude  we  receive  those  things  that  are 
required  for  complete  sufficiency  of  hfe,  things  necessary 
not  for  Hfe,  but  for  the  perfect  hfe,  and  on  this  account 
man  is  a  member  of  the  multitude  of  civil  society,  and 
that,  not  merely  in  regard  to  "  (such  things  as)  "  bodily 
necessities  which  only  a  number  of  artificers  living 
together  can  fully  supply,  but  also  in  regard  to  the 
moral  necessities  like  that  of  public  punishment,  whereby 
youths  are  coerced  into  good  behaviour  when  they 
cease  to  give  heed  to  mere  paternal  admonition.  .  .  . 
Hence  moral  philosophy  is  divided  into  three  parts. 
The  first  regards  the  acts  of  a  man  in  his  individual  or 
personal  relation  to  the  final  end — which  is  '  Monastica  ' 
(or  personal  Ethics).  The  second  considers  the  actions 
of  the  family — which  is  '  Oeconomica.'  The  third  con- 
siders the  political  organisation  and  its  action — which 
is  '  Politica.'  "  * 

There  is,  however,  one  difficulty  in  the  way  of  regard- 
ing Political  Philosophy  as  a  branch  of  Ethics — namely, 
that  Political  Philosophy  considers  many  questions 
which  apparently  have  nothing  to  do  with  the  moral 
good  or  with  duty — for  instance,  the  question  of  the 
best  form  of  "  electoral  system  "  or  the  best  methods  of 
taxation.  Our  view  of  these  questions  is  that,  though 
they  are  not  concerned  directly  with  what  is  of  strict 
moral  obligation,  they  are  concerned  remotely  and 
indirectly  with  what  is  of  obligation,  because  they  are 
concerned  with  the  means  whereby  ends  which  arc  of 
strict  moral  obligation  are  to  be  attained.  For  instance, 
it  is  of  strict  moral  obligation  that  government  should 
exist  and  tliat  the  State  should  be  maintained.  But 
there  are  many  possible  forms  of  government  and  many 
systems  of  maintenance.     The  form  of  government  may 

•  "  Commentaries  on  Aristotle."  Liber  primus  Ethicorutn,  Lectio  I 
We  may  note  that  Aristotle  in  one  place  speaks  of  Ethics  as  a  sort  of 
Politics  (iroKiTinr)  T(t),  and  speaks  of  Politics  as  li\e  siiiiicnir  science 
(Nich.  Kth.  I.  2).  His  meaninK,  however,  evidently  is  that  Politics 
\H  the  hinhest  part  of  Ethics,  and  it  is  usual  to  denominate  any  .science 
fniiii  uliat  i»  highest  in  it. 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        13 

be  monarchical  or  representative,  and  the  system  of 
maintenance  may  be  that  of  direct  taxation  or  of  in- 
direct. In  other  words  the  means  to  the  end  are  many. 
The  moral  law  is  indifferent  what  form  or  system 
is  adopted,  but  it  is  of  obligation  to  choose  some  one 
form  or  system,  just  as  the  laws  of  health  are  indifferent 
as  to  what  kind  of  food  one  eats  (provided  it  is  whole- 
some) but  requires  that  one  eats  some  kind.  Now  in  all 
its  departments  Political  Philosophy  is  concerned  either 
with  the  ends  of  the  State  or  with  the  means  by  which 
these  ends  are  reached.  And  since  the  ends  of  the 
State  are  obligatory  and  ethical,  the  means  also  which 
this  science  considers  are  obligatory  and  ethical. 

Political  Philosophy  therefore  is  Ethical  in  character, 
not  only  in  regard  to  the  fundamental  problems  like 
the  necessity  and  function  of  government,  but  also  in 
regard  to  the  derived  problems  like  those  others  which 
we  have  mentioned. 


ETHICS  AND  MORAL  THEOLOGY 

Ethics  treats  of  the  moral  law  from  the  standpoint  of 
natural  Reason  alone — Moral  Theology  from  the  point 
of  view  of  revelation.  The  relation  of  Ethics  to  revealed 
Theology  is  very  clearly  drawn  by  the  scholastic  writers. 
Ethics  is  a  natural  science  in  the  sense  of  a  science  con- 
ducted by  our  natural  Reason,  and  therefore  the  ethi- 
cian  does  not  in  the  construction  of  his  science  use  the 
Revealed  Word  as  a  proof  of  ethical  truth  or  as  a  pre- 
miss from  which  to  draw  ethical  conclusions.  Revealed 
morality  stands  to  Ethics  in  the  same  relation  exactly 
that  the  biblical  account  of  the  origin  of  the  material 
world  stands  to  the  natural  science  of  Geology.  In 
other  words,  no  proposition  can  be  regarded  as  a  genuine 
conclusion  of  the  science  of  Ethics  unless  it  can  be 
established  on  giounds  of  natural  Reason  alone  without 
revelation.  If  revelation  is  necessary  in  order  to  estab- 
lish a  particular  proposition  this  proposition  is  a  con- 


14  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

cliuion  of  Moral  Theology,  not  of  Ethics.  There  are  a 
great  number  even  of  moral  truths  that  can  be  estab- 
lished only  through  revelation — truths  that  unaided 
natural  Reason  could  not  possibly  discover.  These 
truths  are  not  ethical  truths,  and  are  not  the  premisses 
of  ethical  conclusions,  nor  are  they  used  as  such  by 
the  scholastic  writers.  Ethics  and  Geology  are  natural 
sciences,  Theology  is  a  revealed  science.  The  stand- 
points, or  what  are  called  the  formal  objects  of  the 
natural  and  the  revealed  sciences,  are  not  indeed  op- 
posed, but  they  are  distinct.  The  science  of  the  re- 
vealed moral  law  is  Moral  Theology.  Ethics  is  the 
science  of  natural  morals  only,  and  its  standpoint  is 
that  of  natural  Reason. 

(d)  Method  of  Ethics 

The  methods  *  employed  by  various  ethicians  in  the 
development   of  this   science  may  be  conveniently  re- 

*  By  "  method  "  here  we  mean,  not  a  system  of  Ethics,  but  the 
method  of  study  adopted  in  discovering  moral  truths.  It  is  perfectly 
possible  that  two  men  following  the  same  method  (for  instance  the 
inductive)  should  arrive  at  very  different  ethical  systems.  The 
reader  will  easily  understand  that  it  would  be  no  easy  matter  to  classify 
all  the  methods  adopted  by  ethicians,  or  even  to  know  in  every  case 
the  precise  method  adopted  by  individual  ethicians.  Many  ethicians 
adopt  a  plurality  of  methods,  which  is,  indeed,  quite  logical  and  often 
necessary.  But  many  who  lay  claim  to  using  a  single  method  arc 
often  so  vague  in  their  account  of  it,  that  it  becomes  impossible  at 
times  to  know  under  what  heading  to  classify  it.  Thus  it  is  ex- 
ceedingly difficult  to  know  how  far  many  "  moral  sense  "  ethicians 
acknowledge  intellect,  or  whether  they  regard  the  testimony  of  the 
moral  sense  as  given  by  inner  reflection  or  by  outward  perception 
Thus  they  speak  of  the  moral  sense  as  a  "  sentiment  of  judgment," 
which  would  suggest  .some  kind  of  intellectual  faculty.  Yet  such 
prominence  is  given  to  "  feeling  "  in  these  theories  that  the  moral 
faculty  would  seem  to  be  regarded  as  predominantly  sensuous.  In  the 
main  we  say  that  the  moral-sense  writers  regard  conscience  not  as  an 
intellectual  but  as  a  sensuous  faculty  with  higlier  .sentiments  attached. 
Agam,  the  moral  sense  is  sometimes  represented  as  extra-regarding,  in 
so  far  as  by  it  wc  become  aware  of  the  moral  qualities  of  other  men's 
act*,  and  Bometimcs  as  reflective  or  intra-regarding,  in  so  far  as  it  is 
a  reflective  liking  for  certain  affections  in  our.selves. 

Again,  with  the  exception  of  a  few,  intuitionists  generally  fight 
»hy  of  the  question  whether  our  moral  intuitions  concern  thtr  general 
moral  fjrinciples  only,  or  whether  they  extend  to  particular  acts. 
They  speak  generally  of  intuitions  (not  of  moral  principle,  and  not  of 
individual  act  but)  of  morality  simply 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        15 

duced  to  three.  First,  methods  are  either  intuitive  * 
or  inferential — that  is,  moral  truths  are  either  repre- 
sented as  known  directly  and  immediately  without 
reasoning,  or  they  are  represented  as  knowable  through 
reasoning  alone.  Secondly,  the  inferential  method  is 
either  one  of  induction  or  of  deduction — that  is,  the 
ethician  either  starts  from  experience  and  builds  up  the 
general  moral  proposition  from  particular  truths,  or  he 
represents  particular  moral  truths  as  deducible  from 
the  more  general  self-evident  moral  principles.  Speak- 
ing broadly  then,  the  methods  recognised  by  different 
ethicians  are  the  intuitive,  the  inductive  or  a  posteriori, 
and  the  deductive  or  a  -priori. 

The  intuitive  method  represents  moral  truths  as  know- 
able  immediately  by  direct  perception.  Now,  in  general, 
there  are  possible  two  modes  of  intuition — intuition  by 
sense  and  intuition  by  intellect.  Accordingly,  intui- 
tional moralists  may  be  divided  broadly  into  two  classes 
— those  who  attribute  the  knowledge  of  moral  truths 
to  a  sense  which  they  call  the  moral  sense,  f  and  those 
who  attribute  it  to  intellect.  To  the  former  class  belong 
Reid,J  Shaftesbury  and  Hutcheson,  to  the  latter,  the 
Intellectual  moralists  Cudworth  and  Clarke.  Again, 
the   "  moral    sense "    theory   is   a   theory   either   of   an 


*  Speaking  strictly,  "  intuition  "  is  not  a  method.  Common  usage 
and  convenience,  however,  are  our  justification  for  speaking  of  it  as 
a  method. 

t  So  far  as  method  is  concerned,  the  moral  sense  theory  may  be 
classed  as  one  with  the  theory  of  moral  feeling,  with,  e.g.,  Adam 
Smith's  theory  of  "  Conscience — a  feeling  of  sympathy,"  and  Brown's 
theorv  of  "  Conscience — a  feeling  of  approvableness." 

{  ^jidgwick  distinguishes  two  intuitional  methods,  (i)  The  strict 
a  priori  method,  in  which  a  man's  duty  is  clearly  stated  on  general 
principles,  and  no  room  is  left  for  individual  tastes  or  freedom.  (2) 
The  aesthetic  intuitional  method  which  allows  for  individual  tastes, 
puts  virtue  above  strict  duty,  and  allows  for  its  not  being  always 
realisable  at  will.  The  moral  code  resulting  from  this  latter  method 
is  necessarily  very  indefinite.  We  need  not  say  that  in  the  following 
treatise  we  shall  take  no  notice  whatever  of  aesthetic  intuitionism  in 
Sidgwick's  sense.  Of  .(Esthetic  Ethics,  in  another  sense,  we  shall 
have  something  to  say,  but  ajsthetic  intuitionism  in  Sidgwick's  sense 
is  not  a  science,  and  it  is  therefore  disproved  by  everything  we  can 
bring  forward  in  favour  of  the  scientific  method. 


i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

"  inner  "  sense  or  of  an  "  outer."  An  "  inner  "  sense, 
it  is  claimed,  discovers  the  moral  law  within  a  man 
himself  by  introspection.  In  this  way  Hume  may  be 
regarded  as  a  sense  intuitionist.  The  moral  sense  as 
"  outer  "  is  represented  as  sensible  to  the  morality  of 
other  men's  acts  as  weU  as  of  our  own,  and  as  such  its 
action  is  said  to  be  akin  to  that  of  our  other  ordinary 
outer  senses. 

It  is  not  so  easy  to  mark  off  the  various  methods  of 
"  intellectual  "  Intuitionism.  In  one  way  even  the  de- 
fenders of  the  inferential  method  are  all,  to  some  extent, 
intellectual  intuitionists,  for  they  insist  that  the  process 
of  reasoning  must  begin  with  intuition  of  some  kind, 
that  we  cannot  reason  back  m  infinitum.  Indeed,  every 
moralist  recognises  the  need  of  intuition  at  some  stage 
or  other  in  the  determination  of  moral  truths.  But 
between  the  inferential  theory  and  the  theory  of  the 
"  intellectual  intuitionists  "  we  may  at  least  draw  a  dis- 
tinction of  degree,  as  regards  the  number  of  intuitions 
they  each  admit.  Intuitional  moralists  as  a  rule  regard 
aU  the  general  moral  principles,  or  at  least  those  simpler 
truths  which  all  civilised  men  know  of,  like  "  justice  is 
to  be  done,"  "  drunkenness  to  be  avoided,"  "  the  truth 
to  be  told,"  "  superiors  are  to  be  obeyed,"  as  judgments 
of  intuition.  Those  who  follow  the  inferential  method 
insist  that  the  great  body  of  these  same  moral  principles, 
including  many  principles  which  are  generally  accepted 
by  civilised  men,  need  to  be  proved  ;  but  they  admit 
that  we  must  fall  back  somewhere  in  our  reasoning  on 
self-evident  truths.  This  second  class  of  writers  are 
not  usually  described  as  intuitionists,  and  in  this  work 
we  shall  speak  of  Intellectual  Intuitionism  in  the  lirst 
sense  only.  We  shall  not  at  present  discuss  the  in- 
tuitional method.  Our  view  of  intuition  and  of  the 
other  methods  will  be  given  in  a  special  chapter  on 
intuitioniHui  and  other  chapters  dealing  with  different 
moral  theories. 

The  a  posteriori  or  inductive  method  may  be  defined 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        17 

in  a  general  way  as  that  method  which  bases  the  general 
principles  of  moral  science,  if  not  exclusively,  at  least 
mainly  on  experience.  The  form  of  the  method  varies 
with  the  different  schools  of  ethicians  employing  it. 
Thus  hedonists  and  utilitarians  use  it  to  determine  the 
moral  principles  by  a  calculus  of  the  pleasurable  and 
painful  consequences  of  action,  pleasure  and  pain  being 
evidently  matters  of  experience.  The  historical  school 
of  moralists  employ  this  method  (in  their  hands  it  is 
known  as  the  historical  method)  to  investigate  the 
customs  and  beliefs  of  different  peoples  at  different 
periods  of  the  world's  history.  According  to  these 
moralists  there  are  no  natural,  permanent,  or  necessary 
moral  principles.  Our  moral  beliefs  cannot  even  be 
divided  into  true  and  false.*  At  different  ages  different 
customs  arose  under  the  influence  of  environment, 
physical  and  social.  These  customs  came  gradually 
to  be  viewed  as  necessary,  obligatory,  and  right,  and 
their  opposites  as  wrong,  and  the  essential  business  of 
the  Ethician  is  to  tabulate  these  various  beliefs  and 
customs,  to  discover  their  causes,  and  if  possible  to 
lay  down  a  formula  which  will  explain  their  develop- 
ment. 

These  various  forms  of  the  inductive  method  it  would 
be  impossible  for  us  to  criticise  at  this  point  in  our 
work.  Their  consideration  and  refutation  will  be  much 
more  easily  undertaken  when  we  come  to  examine  the 
moral  systems  of  which  they  form  a  part,  e.g.,  the 
hedonistic  and  evolutionist  systems,  to  which  therefore 
we  refer  our  reader. 

However,  there  is  one  form  of  the  inductive  method 
to  which  we  should  like  to  make  some  critical  reference 
here,  a  form  of  it  to  which,  we  may  say  at  once,  we 
shall  rigorously  refuse  a  place  in  this  science — namely, 
the  method  of  "  induction  through  moral  instances,"  or 
the  establishment  of  general  moral  truths  through 
particular  cases  of  the  general  truth.     An  example  of 

*  One  noted  exponent  of  this  theory  is  M.  Levy-Bruhl. 
Vol.  I — 2 


i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

this  method  would  be  the  establishment  of  the  general 
proposition  "  all  lies  are  bad "  by  finding  that  this, 
that,  and  the  other  lie  were  bad,  or  that  "  murder  is 
bad  "  because  the  murder  of  this,  that,  and  the  other 
man  was  bad.  This  method,  as  we  have  said,  cannot 
be  admitted  into  Ethics,  We  do  not  know  that  the 
lie  in  general  is  bad  on  the  ground  that  many  particular 
lies  are  bad.  On  the  contrar}-,  we  can  only  know  that 
a  particular  lie  is  bad  through  knowing  that  the  lie  of 
its  nature,  and  therefore  of  itself  and  in  general,  is  bad. 
Induction  through  instances  has  an  undoubted  value  in 
the  physical  sciences,  for  the  physical  sciences  are  con- 
cerned solely  with  objects  and  qualities  that  fall  under 
the  senses.  We  see,  for  instance,  with  our  e3'es  that 
this  and  that  piece  of  gold  are  yellow,  and  thus  we  can 
argue  from  many  single  instances  to  the  general  pro- 
position that  "  gold  is  yellow."  But  such  a  form  of 
argument  is  quite  inapplicable  in  morals.  For,  indi- 
vidual lies  are  not  labelled  "  good "  or  "  bad."  We 
have  to  discover  their  moral  quality  by  the  use  of 
reasoning,  and  in  establishing  their  moral  quality  we 
argue  on  the  strength  of  premisses  that  are  quite  of 
general  application.* 

The    a    priori    method. — The    deductive    or    a    priori 

*  Some  have  adopted  the  a  posteriori  method  as  cqui-primary  with 
the  deductive,  and  as  the  exclusive  method  of  certain  branches  of 
Ethics.  Thus  John  Grote,  in  his  work,  "  A  Treatise  on  the  Moral 
Ideals,"  divides  Ethics  into  two  parts — "  Aretaics  "  and  "  Eudae- 
monics."     The  method  of  the  second  part  is  a  posteriori. 

A  method  akin  to  that  of  induction,  and  sometimes  adopted  in 
Ethics — e.g.,  by  Sigwart — is  that  which  some  writers  call  the  reductive 
method,  correspomling  in  great  measure  to  what  Mill  calls  induction 
by  parity  of  reason.  It  is  the  case  of  a  law  revealed  fully  and  neces- 
sarily in  one  particular  instance.  Thus,  the  fifth  proposition  of  the 
first  book  of  Euclid  is  not  only  exemplified  but  proved  from  any 
isosceles  triangle  which  one  may  draw. 

To  this  metliod  all  that  we  have  said  about  induction  by  instances 
may  be  applied  without  excepli(m.  Even  Sigwart  implicitly  admits 
its  impossible  character  when  he  says — "  Ethics  can  only  come  down 
from  above  •  it  cannot  be  built  up  from  below  " — that  is,  the  general 
moral  truth.s  can  Ik*  established  from  general  principles  only,  and  not 
from  particular  empirical  facts.  The  expression  "  reductive  method  " 
huanother  meaning  also — namely,  the  establishing  of  the  jiremisses  of 
&n  argument  given  the  concluHion  that  has  come  from  them. 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        19 

method  is  that  which  deduces  all  moral  truths  from 
certain  broad  general  principles  that  have  either  the 
force  of  analytic  *  judgments  themselves  or  may  b^ 
reduced  to  judgments  that  are  analytic.  As  there  are 
schools  of  Ethics  that  adopt  the  a  posteriori  method 
only,  so  there  are  ethical  schools  that  adopt  the  a 
priori  method  exclusively,  and  make  no  appeal,  or  at 
least  aim  at  making  no  appeal,  whatsoever  to  experience 
in  the  building  up  of  their  science. 

The  following  are  instances  of  the  a  priori  ethical 
method : — (a)  The  geometric  method  of  Spinoza,  in 
which  proposition  is  drawn  from  proposition  exactly  as 
in  Euclid,  without  any  appeal  to  experience,  or  any 
admixture  of  probable  reasoning — the  last  conclusions 
being,  it  is  contended,  quite  as  certain  as  the  axioms 
from  which  they  are  drawn,  whatever  be  the  number  of 
intervening  propositions  ;  (6)  the  transcendental  or  ab- 
stract a  priori  method,  in  which  all  moral  truths  are 
deduced  from  some  one  original  speculative  truth,  such 
as  "  I  find  myself  willing"  (Fichte),  or  "I  am  free" 
((Hegel),  which  one  proposition,  it  is  contended  in  each 
<case,  is  just  the  abstract  expression  of  the  whole  moral 
order,  the  manifold  laws  of  which  are  derived  from  the 
first  principle  by  pure  a  priori  reason  alone  :  j  (c)  the 
Ideal  a  priori  method  of  Plato  in  the  "  Republic,"  and 
of  More  in  his  "  Utopia,"  in  which  conduct  is  regulated 
not  by  what  is  good  and  obligatory  for  real  men,  but  by 
an  abstract  ideal  of  what  is  best  or  might  be  best  for  us 
under  conditions  that  are  superhuman. 

What  value  attaches  to  a  priori  reasoning  in  Ethics 
will  be  seen  in  the  following  section,  which  will  contain 
our  view  on  the  function  both  of  deduction  and  of  in- 
duction in  the  science  of  Ethics. 


*  By  an  analytic  judgment  is  meant  a  judgment  of  which  the 
predicate  is  a  part  of  the  meaning  of  the  subject. 

t  Hegel  recognises  the  a  priori  method  as  primary  and  fundamental. 
But  he  is  finally  led  to  the  adoption  of  the  historic  method  as  the 
practical  and  proximate  method  of  Ethics 


20  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

THE  TRUE  METHOD  OF  ETHICS 

As  the  present  work  proceeds  and  the  moral  laws  and 
their  many  applications  come  before  us  for  consideration, 
it  ought  to  become  plain  to  the  reader  that  the  method 
of  Ethics  is  a  mixed  one,  that  it  is  partly  a  priori  or 
deductive,  and  partly  empirical.  Ethics  is  primarily 
and  in  the  main  a  deductive  science — that  is,  it  is 
science  in  which  the  morality  of  particular  acts  is 
deduced  from  general  moral  propositions.  For  Ethics 
is  a  practical  science,  and,  therefore,  its  aim  is  to  direct 
men  aright  in  the  concrete  circumstances  of  real  life. 
Hence  the  primary  and  essential  method  of  Ethics  will 
be  that  by  which  our  Reason  determines  the  individual 
duty  in  individual  circumstances.  We  know,  however, 
from  experience  that  in  order  to  do  this,  it  is  neces- 
sary to  bring  together  certain  general  moral  principles 
such  as  will  suit  the  circumstances  of  the  act  in  question, 
and  from  a  consideration  cf  those  principles  we  are  able 
to  determine  deductively  the  individual  duty.  Hence 
the  method  of  Ethics  is  primarily  and  in  the  main  de- 
ductive. 

But  it  is  in  the  establishment  of  the  general  principles 
themselves  that  Reason  has  to  fall  back  to  a  large  extent 
on  experience.  There  are  indeed  a  number  of  prin- 
ciples that  are  known  to  us  intuitively,  so  evidently 
are  certain  actions  requirements  of  our  natural  con- 
stitution, and  others  violations  of  it.  In  other  cases 
agreement  or  disagreement  with  our  human  nature  can 
only  be  recognised  by  the  aid  of  investigation  and 
reasoning.  But  whether  the  natural  requirements  are 
known  intuitively  or  not,  it  is  certain  that  the  deter- 
mination of  morality  involves  in  every  case  the  study 
of  our  natural  constitution,  and  this  can  only  become 
known  to  us  through  experience.* 

•  Wc  refrain  from  calliriR  this  oxporimrntal  t;utor  in  l-lthics  "in- 
ductive," becanw  of  the  nicaninf,'  usually  attachinji;  to  "  induction  " 
an  reasoning  built  on  instances  in  the  way  wc  liavc  ilcscribed.  To  say 
that  there  is  in  Ethics  an  clement  of  experience  expresses  our  whole 
meaning  here. 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        21 

We  should  mention,  however,  that  this  experimental 
factor  which  plays  so  important  a  part  in  the  deter- 
mination of  the  general  moral  principles  is  no  bar  to 
the  certitude  required  of  the  science  of  Ethics.  For  the 
experience  that  we  presuppose  in  Ethics  is  no  narrow 
experience,  but  one  so  broad  and  universal  that  there 
can  be  no  error  nor  risk  of  error  in  following  it.  The 
method,  therefore,  of  Ethics  is  in  the  main  deductive. 
But  it  presupposes  experience,  for  in  the  establishment 
of  its  general  principles  it  must  rely  upon  experience.* 

(e)  Possibility  of  the  Science  of  Ethics 

Is  a  science  of  Ethics  really  possible  ?  A  full  dis- 
cussion of  this  question  would  anticipate  what  we  hope 
to  prove  regarding  the  reality  of  the  distinction  between 
moral  good  and  evil,  and  the  validity  of  the  first  prin- 
ciples of  Ethics.  But  the  question  may  be  partly 
answered  here  by  meeting  the  more  important  of  the 
arguments  that  have  been  advanced  against  the  possi- 
bility of  a  Moral  Science. 

(i)  It  has  been  said  that  if  there  is  a  science  of  Ethics 
at  all  it  must  be  a  science  of  the  most  inexact  type, 
so  inexact  as  scarcely  to  merit  the  title  of  science. 
Opinions,  it  is  contended,  are  so  varied  on  moral  matters 
that  no  certain  convictions  can  be  entertained  about 
them.  Savages,  for  instance,  have  only  the  rudest 
morality.  Their  highest  code  of  morals  is  immorality 
to  civilised  men.  Nor  can  it  be  argued  that  a  savage's 
opinions  are  only  savage,  and  are  consequently  negligible. 
Valueless  as  his  opinions  may  be  on  purely  speculative 
scientific  questions,  like  astronomy  or  electricity,  they 
certainly,  it  is  insisted,  have  a  value  all  their  own  on 
matters   that    concern   human   life   and    existence.     We 

*  The  reader  must  not  complain  that  we  give  no  convincing  proof 
here  that  the  method  of  Ethics  is  such  as  we  have  described.  At  this 
stage  of  our  work  it  would  be  irrational  to  expect  us  to  prove  these 
things.  The  requirements  of  Ethics  in  regard  to  method  can  only 
appear  when  we  come  to  treat  of  particular  moral  problems. 


22  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

■\ 
have  not,  therefore,  in  morals  a  sufficient  consensus  of 

opinion  to  constitute  a  genuine  science  of  Ethics. 

Reply — It  is  untrue  to  sa}^  that  Ethics  is  either  not  a 
genuine  science  or  is  an  uncertain  science.  Ethics,  in 
the  first  place,  possesses  all  the  elements  that  are  re- 
quired for  a  genuine  science — namely,  indisputable 
principles  and  a  definite  method ;  and  it  is  certain 
because  the  conclusions  to  which  it  leads  us  are  certain. 
This,  of  course,  we  can  only  make  clear  to  the  reader 
as  we  proceed.  We  admit,  indeed,  that  there  are 
problems  in  Ethics,  not  of  a  primary  character  and  re- 
mote from  our  first  principles,  which  cannot  be  solved 
with  certainty.  Also,  the  practical  application  of  the 
complex  rules  about  circumstances,  &c.,  is  not  in  many 
cases  without  difficulty.  But  yet  we  shall  be  able  to 
show  that  a  very  large  number  of  our  moral  conclusions 
are  certain — a  number  quite  large  enough  to  cover  all 
the  important  duties  of  a  man's  life. 

The  argument  drawn  from  the  difference  in  existing 
codes,  between  that  of  the  savages  and  that  of  civilised 
men,  is,  we  maintain,  no  disproof  of  the  validity  of  our 
science,  just  as  differences  of  view  on  the  physical  world 
are  no  disproof  of  the  validity  or  reality  of  Physical 
Science.  We  admit,  however,  that  it  would  be  a  serious 
thing  for  our  Moral  Science  if  men  did  not  agree  on  at 
least  the  first  principles  of  Ethics,  for  these  principles 
are  represented  by  us  as  intuitions,  and  it  is  supposed 
that  all  minds  agree  about  intuitions.  But  there  can 
be  no  doubt  whatsoever,  as  we  shall  see  later  on  in  this 
volume,  that  savages  and  civilised  men  are  quite  in 
agreement  about  the  first  principles  of  morals,*  and  that 
all  differences  between  our  codes  fall  under  one  or  other 
of  the  following  heads,  none  of  which  have  reference 

•  Profcs.Hor  Wundt,  though  an  ardent  evolutionist,  writes  ("  Etliik," 
Engl,  transl.,  pa^c  40) — "  No  unpicjiuliccd  observer  can  avoid  the 
conviction  that  in  the  last  resort  tin:  dilU'rcnccs  here  (that  is,  on  points 
of  practical  morals),  are  no  (greater  than  in  the  intellectual  realm, 
where,  in  spite  of  all  the  multiplicity  of  views  and  schools,  the  universal 
validity  of  the  laws  of  thought  remains  unquestioned," 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        23 

to  primary  Ethical  principles — {a)  remote  and  difficult 
ethical  conclusions  which  only  the  developed  Reason 
can  successfully  determine  ;  (&)  the  secondary  laws  of 
morality — that  is,  laws  that  appertain,  not  to  absolute 
moral  necessities,  but  to  the  higher  necessities  or  the 
necessities  of  the  more  perfect  human  existence  ;  (c) 
positive  laws  that  are  above  nature. 

For  instance,  (a)  it  is  not  to  be  expected  that  savages 
will  have  right  and  proper  views  of  the  details  of  justice, 
since  "  justice  "  cases  require  reasoning — reasoning  of 
which  even  civilised  men  are  often  quite  incapable ; 
(6)  savages  practise  polygamy,  civilised  men  as  a  rule 
do  not.  But  then  this  difference  appertains,  not  to 
the  strictly  necessary  or  primary  laws  of  natural  Ethics, 
but  to  the  secondary  laws — the  laws  of  greater  human 
perfection.  Now,  of  these  secondary  laws  the  savage 
has  either  no  care  (for  he  does  not  desire  the  greater 
human  perfection)  or  no  knowledge  (since  what  is 
necessary  for  the  greater  perfection  is  never  so  obvious 
as  that  which  is  required  for  existence  or  life  itself)  : 
but  the  primary  laws  are  fully  known  to  him,  as  will 
be  proved ;  (c)  differences  sometimes  concern  mere 
positive  laws  which  are  above  nature,  and  which  savages 
know  nothing  about.  For  instance,  we  have  the  law  of 
Christian  charity.  But  such  differences  of  moral  idea 
are  not  ethical,  since  Ethics  is  the  study  of  natural 
morals,  and  hence  these  differences  are  outside  the 
question  which  we  are  discussing. 

(2)  Secondly — It  is  contended  that  many  weighty 
authorities  have  not  regarded  this  science  as  demons 
strative — e.g.,  Aristotle.* 

Reply — We  can  only  answer  briefly  that  Aristotle 
merely  meant  to  indicate  that  Ethics  could  not  give  us 
certainty  in  every  case,  and  that  the  science  has  its 
difficulties  like  other  genuine  sciences  that  in  part  de- 
pend on  experience. 

(3)  Again,    it    is    objected    that    "  the    philosophical 

*  Nich.  Eth.,  I.  3,  4. 


24  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

explanation  of  morality  always  lags  behind  the  fullness 
of  real  life  "  * — that  the  principles  of  a  science  of  Ethics 
must  be  purel}^  general,  whereas  the  object  of  Ethics — 
viz.,  human  life — is  concrete  and  real.  You  cannot,  it 
is  contended,  frame  a  bod}^  of  laws  which  will  reach 
into  all  the  crevices  of  a  man's  life  or  regulate  all  his 
motives. 

Reply — On  the  question  of  the  relation  between 
general  law  and  individual  fact  we  shall  speak  at  some 
length  later,  f  Here  we  may  say  that,  in  regard  to  this 
relation,  Ethics  stands  on  exactly  the  same  footing  ag 
Mathematics  and  Physics.  Let  us  confine  our  com- 
parison to  the  case  of  Ethics  and  the  Physical  sciences. 
The  function  and  aim  of  the  Physcial  sciences  is  the 
discovery  of  general  laws  of  nature  and  the  deduction 
of  facts  from  general  laws.  Yet  the  general  laws  of 
Physics  do  not  of  themselves  account  for  the  individual 
facts,  but  have  to  be  supplemented  by  considerations  of 
the  circumstances  in  which  these  facts  exist  and  under 
which  they  are  produced.  Thus,  from  the  general  laws 
of  Dj^namics  no  man  could  deduce  the  actual  course  of 
a  falling  body  because  so  much  depends  on  the  sur- 
rounding circumstances.  So  also  in  Ethics  the  general 
moral  laws  could  not  of  themselves  meet  all  the  require- 
ments of  the  individual  life.  But,  given  a  full  state- 
ment of  the  circumstances  and  given  the  general  laws, 
the  ethician  will  determine  our  individual  duty,  if  not 
in  every  case,  at  least  in  every  important  case. 

(4)  Any  genuine  science,  it  is  argued,  should  fulfil  two 
important  conditions — it  should  verify  and  it  should 
predict.  Now  Ethics  cannot  predict,  i.e.,  cannot  pre- 
dict what  will  happen,  because  it  is  solely  concerned 
with  what  ought  to  be  ;  and,  secondly,  its  laws  cannot 
be  verified,  because,  since  they  concern  what  ou\;ht  to 
be,  they  might  still  be  true  and  valid  even  though  they 
were  at  variance  with  the  facts,  that  is,  with  actual 

•  BusBcl  in  "  Personal  Idealism,"  page  345. 
t  page  98. 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        25 

conduct.  If,  therefore,  Ethics  is  a  science,  it  is  a  science 
in  a  very  imperfect  sense  only. 

Reply — This  difficulty  we  shall  dispose  of  in  very  few 
words.  Since  Ethics  proposes  to  tell,  not  what  one 
will  do  but  what  one  ought  to  do,  prediction  is  not  a 
function  of  Ethics.  But  prediction  is  not  required  for 
a  genuine  science.  Mathematics,  e.g.,  is  incapable  of 
predicting  in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word.  It  cannot 
tell  us  where  a  body  will  fall,  but  only  what  it  would 
do  if  allowed  to  fall  freely.  Mathematics  is  a  study  of 
laws  not  of  facts.  It  is  so  also  with  Ethics.  Ethics  is 
a  study  of  the  laws  of  right  conduct.  It  is  no  part  of 
its  business  to  tell  us  what  will  happen,  but  only  what 
ought  to  happen  if  men  are  to  act  morally. 

Neither  is  verification  a  necessary  requirement  of 
science.  The  conclusions  of  Trigonometry,  for  instance, 
are  never  strictly  verified  by  fact.  Nor  does  Trigono- 
metry require  verification  in  this  sense.  It  is  essentially 
like  Ethics  a  study  of  laws  not  of  facte. 

(5)  Again,  we  have  Mr.  Balfour's  objection  that 
ethicians  simply  falsify  their  ethical  conclusions  for  the 
sake  of  coming  into  line  with  the  code  of  morals  that 
obtains  de  facto  in  the  world,*  since,  while  they  disagree 
concerning  their  moral  principkiS,  they  agree  about  the 
code  of  morals  which  these  principles  yield. 

Reply — This  is  a  serious  charge  to  make  against 
intellectual  men,  and  we  do  not  think  it  can  be  sub- 
stantiated. No  doubt  ethicians  do  agree  about  their 
conclusions  and  their  codes,  and  differ  very  widely 
about  their  principles  ;  but  from  this  it  does  not  follow 
that  ethicians  deal  dishonestly  with  their  principles  or 
force  them  to  unwarranted  conclusions.  De  facto,  many 
ethicians  hold  fast  to  principles  which  they  find  it  ex- 
ceedingly difficult,  if  not  impossible,  to  bring  into 
harmony  with  the  accepted  code.     But  it  is  strange  that 

*  Prof.  Busscl  in  "  Personal  Idealism  "  expressly  impugns  the 
candour  of  ethicians  in  admitting,  as  part  of  their  stock-in-trade, 
principles  which  we  "  blush  to  examine,  and  for  which  we  find  it 
impossible  to  account  "  (page  344). 


26  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

it  never  occurred  to  Mr.  Balfour  that  possibly  these  so 
divergent  principles  really  supplement  one  another — 
that  they  are,  to  a  large  extent,  genuine  truths,  if  only 
partial  truths,  and  that,  consequently,  the  codes  they 
make  possible  must  in  the  main  be  one  ;  in  other  words, 
that  they  are  all  partial  views  of  the  same  central  fact — 
human  nature  and  its  needs.  As  a  matter  of  fact  we 
are  persuaded  that  this  is  the  true  explanation,  and  we 
shall  in  the  course  of  the  following  inquiry  rarely  find 
ourselves  obliged  to  discard  any  ethical  theory  wholly. 
In  practically  all  of  them  there  is  a  great  deal  of  truth 
mixed  up  with  some  error.  We  do  not,  however,  wish 
it  to  be  understood  that  the  theorj^  we  are  going  to  offer 
is  one  qf  eclecticism.  Eclecticism  means  weakness,  com- 
promise, insecurity.  But  to  recognise  the  "  true "  in 
what  is  in  part  false  is  not  eclecticism  but  common  sense. 

(6)  There  is,  then,  the  much  repeated  difficulty  about 
the  "  is "  and  the  "  ought."  Science,  we  are  told, 
deals  with  the  real,  with  what  is,  whereas  Ethics  deals 
only  with  the  ideal  or  with  what  "  ought  "  to  be. 

Reply — The  obvious  answer  to  such  a  difficulty  is 
that  Ethics  is  a  normative  science — that  is,  it  offers  us 
norms  or  rules  of  conduct.  Surely  it  is  no  drawback 
to  any  science  that  it  has  a  difjercntia,  which  distin- 
guishes it  from  other  sciences.  Ethics,  like  Logic,  treats 
of  what  ought  to  be  and  not  of  mere  facts  or  happenings. 
Again,  we  do  not  recognise  any  very  marked  and  essen- 
tial distinction  between  the  real  and  the  ideal,  between 
what  is  and  what  ought  to  be,  such  as  is  here  postulated. 
Surely  the  necessity  or  "  oughtness,"  of  taking  the  one 
road  that  leads  to  a  town  if  a  man  would  get  to  a  town, 
is  a  real  necessity,  and  yet  it  is  also  ideal  or  a  thing  that 
ought  to  be  just  in  so  far  as  a  man  may  or  may  not  take 
the  road.  Now,  as  we  shall  see  later,  Ethics  has  just  to 
do  with  these  teleological  necessities,  with  the  necessities 
of  certain  ends  of  human  appetite.  These  necessities 
are  real  necessities  and  the  means  by  which  they  are 
pupplie4  are  really  "  pieans."    There  \%,  then,  no  absor 


DEFINITION  AND  SCOPE  OF  ETHICS        27 

lute  cleavage  between  the  ought  and  the  is  in  Ethics, 
any  more  than  there  is  in  "  Medicine."  The  needs  of 
the  body  are  as  real  as  the  body  itself,  and  so  are  the 
means  to  its  development  and  maintenance.  "  Medi- 
cine," therefore,  is  a  real  science.  But  it  is  also  ideal 
in  the  sense  that,  like  Ethics,  it  tells  what  ought  to  be 
done.  The  only  distinction  of  "  ought "  and  "  is " 
which  we  recognise  in  Ethics  is  that  of  the  laws  of  con- 
duct and  the  actual  practices  of  conduct.  These  two 
may  not  coincide,  but  it  is  the  business  of  Ethics  to 
assign  these  laws  of  conduct  not  to  tabulate  the  courses 
of  conduct  which  men  will  actually  follow. 

(7)  And  this  leads  us  to  another  objection  of  Pro- 
fessor Bussel  * — that  the  end  contemplated  in  Ethics  is 
always  an  ideal  which  the  individual  can  never  realise, 
an  ideal  which  belongs  to  a  world  beN'ond  the  present, 
and  is  out  of  space  and  time,  and  so  can  give  rise,  not 
to  rational  judgments,  but  to  vague  sentimentalities 
and  unreal  yearnings  which  never  can  be  satisfied. 

Reply — Now,  we  admit  that  some  ethical  sj'stema 
may  be  so  described,  particularly  those  which  we  shall 
afterwards  discuss  under  the  heading  of  "  Elpistic " 
theories — theories,  viz.,  which  place  the  good  of  man  in 
what  has  been  described  as  "  asymptotical  desire,"  or  in 
the  working  of  the  will  towards  an  end  which  we  may 
always  approach,  but  which  we  can  never  realise.  But 
Ethics,  as  we  shall  see  later,  has  to  do  with  a  real  end — 
an  end  which  we  can  prove  real,  as  real  as  man  himself, 
an  end,  too,  which  man  can  reach — quern  homo  conseqtd 
possit.  It  has  to  do  also  with  the  means  which  lead 
thereto  necessarily  and  infallibly.  Then,  in  the  matter 
of  the  criterion,  Ethics  deals  with  our  human  nature — 
a  real  principle,  from  which  spring  all  the  real  properties 
and  perfections,  relations  and  needs  of  man.  In  the 
fullest  sense  of  the  word,  therefore,  Ethics  deals  not 
with  sentimentalities  but  with  realities,  and  with  rational 
judgments  concerning  them. 

*  "  Personal  Idealism,"  pages  359  and  361. 


CHAPTER  II 
ON  HUMAN  ACTS 

In  our  last  chapter  we  defined  Ethics  as  the  science  of 
human  action  in  relation  to  our  last  end,  and  we  gave  a 
brief  account  of  what  is  meant  by  a  human  act.  It  will 
be  our  duty  in  the  present  chapter,  first,  to  enumerate 
very  generall}'  the  various  kinds  of  human  action,  and 
thus  to  determine  in  a  rough  way  the  subject-matter  or 
range  of  application  of  the  science  of  Ethics ;  then, 
secondly,  by  a  fuller  investigation  of  the  "  elements  " 
or  "  principles  "  of  the  human  act,  or  of  what  makes 
an  act  human,  to  determine  this  subject-matter  still 
more  closely  and  scientifically. 

(a)  Division  of  Human  Acts 

The  human  act  we  defined  as  an  act  which  is  done 
under  the  control  of  Reason  and  will ;  and  as  Ethics  is 
the  science  of  human  action  or  conduct  we  may  regard 
any  act  that  is  controlled  by  the  rational  will  as  falling 
within  the  compass  of  this  science  and  as  governed  by 
ethical  law.  Now,  roughly  speaking,  the  rational  will 
controls  two  classes  of  acts — its  own  acts  and  the  acts  of 
certain  other  powers — or  those  acts  which  are  done  by 
and  completed  within  the  will  itself,  and  which  we  call 
elicited  acts  of  will,  and  those  acts  which,  though  done 
by  other  powers,  are-  yet  done  at  the  command  of  the 
will,  and  are  therefore  called  commanded  acts.  Both  of 
these  two  classes  of  acts,  and  not  the  second  merely  (it 
will  not  be  necessary  to  remind  the  reader),  are  com- 
manded by  the  will,  but  it  is  usual  and  convenient  to 
apply  the  expression  "  commanded  acts  "  to  the  second 

38 


ON  HUMAN  ACTS  29 

class  alone^ — that  is,  to  acts  that  proceed  from  other 
powers  but  at  the  command  of  will.  Examples  of  these 
two  classes  will  readily  suggest  themselves.  "  Wishing  " 
is  an  elicited  act  of  will,  because  it  involves  the  exercise 
of  no  other  human  faculty  but  that  of  will.  It  begins 
and  is  completed  within  the  will  itself.  On  the  other 
hand,  walking  and  speaking  are  "  commanded  "  acts  of 
will,  because  they  belong  to  and  proceed  from  other 
powers,  but  are  done  at  the  command  of  and  under  the 
control  of  will. 

The  following  is  a  complete  enumeration  of  the 
various  kinds  of  "  elicited  act  " — wish,  intention,  con- 
sent, election,  use,  and  fruition.* 

Wish  (vclle)  means  simply  the  love  of,  or  inclination 
of  the  will  to,  anything.  It  precedes  all  other  acts  of  ijji>'*'^ 
will.  Intention  f  is  a  movement  of  the  will  actually  to 
gain  the  end  wished.  Formally  this  act  appertains  to 
the  end  not  to  the  means,  though,  of  course,  actually 
gaining  really  invoh'es  the  taking  of  means.  Now, 
having  determined  to  gain  the  end,  the  will  must  move 
to  embrace  whatever  means  may  be  found  necessary. 
This  is  consent.  One  of  the  many  possible  means  must 
then  be  chosen  and  adhered  to  by  the  will.  This  will- 
act  is  called  election.  It  is  preceded  by  the  intellectual 
act  of  "  counsel."  Use  is  that  act  by  which  the  will 
directs  and  moves  the  other  faculties  to  realise  the 
particular  means  chosen  by  the  will.  Fruition  is  the 
enjoyment  of  the  end  attained.     Of  these  elicited  acts 

*  These  are  translations  of  the  scholastic  expressions — telle,  in- 
tendere,  consensus,  electio,  usus,  fruitio. 

t  "  Intention  "  is  sometimes  used  to  signify  the  object  of  desire. 
Mill  defines  "  intention  "  as  what  one  wills  to  do,  as  distinguished 
from  "  motive,"  or  the  feeling  prompting  to  the  act.  With  Bentham 
"  intention  "  means  that  on  account  of  which,  or  in  spile  of  which, 
any  thing  is  done.  It  includes,  therefore,  the  pleasant  and  the  un- 
pleasant consequences,  whilst  "  motive  "  means  that  on  account  of 
which  a  thing  is  done.  This  is  also  MacKenzie's  meaning.  Hegel 
distinguishes  "  purpose  "  and  "  intention."  Purpose  is  the  end  de- 
sired with  its  concrete  circumstances.  Intention  is  the  essential 
element  in  desire.  Thus,  to  bum  a  house  is  the  intention  ;  to  burn 
this  man's  house  and  in  such  a  way  is  the  pui-pose. 


30  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

three  appertain  to  the  end — namel}^  wish,  intention  and 
fruition.     The  other  three  appertain  to  the  means. 

Commanded  acts  it  would  not  be  possible  to  enumerate 
with  any  such  precision  because  they  belong  to  so  many^ 
powers,  and  are  often  very  complex.     At  present  we  can)' 
only   divide   them   under   the   two   broad   categories   o0 
internal  and  external  act — that  is,  ^he  will  can  command' 
the  actions  of  the  internal  powers  and  of  external  powers) 
An  INTERNAL  human  act  is  one  that  involves  the  use  of 
internal    mental    powers    only,    like    remembering    and' 
reasoning  ;    an  external  act  is  one  that  involves  the; 
use  of  bodily  powers  also,  for  instance,  the  acts  of  th& 
external    senses    and    the    various    bodily    movements^) 
And  though  in  the  case  of  these  outward  actions  the> 
external  element  is  neither  prior  in  order  of  time  nor  the? 
more  important  ethicall}'',  still  it  is  customary  to  speak 
of  the  whole  human  act  as  external,   and  not  merely 
that  part  of  it  which  is  material  and  can  be  seen  or  felt 
by   others.     Thus   the   purposeful   killing   of   a   man   is 
accounted  an  external  human  act. 

Now,  it  may  be  considered  that  in  giving  prominence 
here  to  the  external  element  in  human  action  we  are 
extending  the  range  of  application  of  this  science  beyond 
its  proper  limit,  since  morality  is  a  quality  of  the  free 
and  deliberate  act  onl3^  whereas  the  movements  of  the 
body  are  material  and  determined,  and  subject  rather 
to  physical  laws  and  conditions  than  to  moral  laws. 
But  it  should  be  remembered  that  though  the  external 
act  is  in  part  physical  and  material,  the  whole  actf  and 
not  merely  that  part  of  it  which  is  internal  is  caused  by 
and  done  under  the  control  of  the  human  will,  and  that 
therefore  both  "  external  "  and  "  internal  "  make  up 
between  them  one  act,  which,  as  human  and  con- 
trolled by  will,  has  a  right  to  be  considered  in  this 
science. 

It  is  well  also  to  point  out  in  this  connection  that  it 
is  exactly  in  the  kciihc  just  explained  that  our  internal 
will-acts  arc  intjral.     For  it  is  not  because  our  internal 


ON  HUMAN  ACTS  31 

will-acts  reside  in  the  will  as  their  subject  that  they  are 
free  and  moral  (there  is  one  such  act  that  is  not  free 
and  moral — namely,  the  desire  for  happiness),  but 
because  they  are  controlled  by  will.  And  since  the 
external  act  is  also  controlled  by  will,  it  also  is  free  and 
rr  oral. 

The  division  of  human  acts  into  elicited  and  com- 
manded acts  of  will,  and  into  internal  and  external,  gives 
us  some  rough  idea  of  the  range  of  application  of  this 
science  of  Ethics.  Qt  is  the  science  which  prescribes 
laws  for  all  human  action,  whether  elicited  or  com- 
manded, internal  or  external,  in  relation  to  our  last 
end.^ 

We  must  now  go  on  to  a  fuller  and  closer  investiga- 
gation  of  the  nature  of  the  human  act. 

{h)  Of  What  makes  an  Act  Human 

^he  human  act  is  characterised  by  three  essenti^ 
qualities — (i)  knowledge,  (2)  voluntariness,  (3)  freedony 
All  three  are  necessar}^  to  it,  and,  as  necessary,  they  are 
called  "  principles  "  of  the  human  act.  Some  acts  fail 
to  be  human  from  ignorance,  because  a  man  does  not 
know  what  he  does,  as  when  a  person  shoots  at  a  bird 
and  kills  a  man  whom  he  had  not  seen  ;  some  because 
they  are  not  voluntary — that  is,  they  do  not  proceed 
from  will,  for  instance,  purely  reflex  acts,  also,  move- 
ments to  which  we  are  compelled  under  stress  of  vio- 
lence ;  some,  because  they  are  not  free,  like  the  acts  of 
madmen  or  acts  done  in  sleep.  But  all  three  "  prin- 
ciples "  must  be  present  in  an  act  before  we  can  speak 
of  it  as  Imman. 

For,  as  we  saw,  a  human  act  is  one  that  is  controlled 
by  will.  But  (i)  will  depends  on  intellect — it  is  a 
psychic  appetite.  It  desires,  therefore,  onl\^  what  is 
known,  and  v,hat  the  intellect  presents  to  it  as  desir- 
able. Hence  knowledge  is  necessary  to  the  human  act. 
{2.)  That   the   human   act   must   be   voluntary — that   is. 


32  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

must  proceed  from  the  will  either  as  elicited  by  the 
will  or  as  commanded  by  it— follows  from  our  very 
definition  of  the  human  act  as  an  act  done  under  the 
control  of  the  rational  will.  (3)  Again,  the  human  act 
must  be  free.  This  also  follows  from  the  definition  of 
a  human  act.  For,  as  we  shall  see  in  a  later  chapter,* 
a  free  act  is  any  self-determined  act  of  will,  any  act 
which  the  will  causes  in  itself.  But  an  act  of  wiU  which 
the  will  does  not  itself  produce,  which  is  necessitated  in 
the  will  by  inner  nature,  or  forced  upon  it  by  violence 
from  outside  (if  that  were  possible),  is  plainly  not  under 
the  control  of  the  will,  and  therefore  such  an  act  is  not 
a  human  act.     Consequently,  a  human  act  must  be  free. 

Now,  though  each  of  these  principles  is  necessary  to 
a  human  act,  still  it  is  not  unusual  to  speak  of  a  human 
and  a  volunta}'y  act  as  one,  and  to  include  ajl  three  con- 
ditions under  the  second  condition,  or  voluntariness,  the 
reason  being  that  vohmtariness,  whcM  perfect,  includes 
all  three.  For,  first,  a  voluntary  act  is  one  that  proceeds 
from  the  will,  and  every  will-act,  as  we  have  already 
explained,  depends  on  knowledge.  Again,  an  act  could 
not  be  said  to  proceed,  in  the  full  sense  of  the  word,  from 
the  will,  or  to  be  voluntary,  when  it  is  caused  "within  the 
will  either  by  nature  or  by  some  external  influence.  An 
act  proceeds  from  the  will  or  is  voluntary,  in  the  fullest 
and  most  perfect  sense  of  that  word,  only  when  it  is 
caused  by  the  will,  and  such  an  act  is,  according  to  our 
definition,  a  free  act. 

A  voluntary  action,  then,  understood  in  its  most 
perfect  sense,  is  always  free,  and  any  act  that  is  not 
free  is  voluntary  in  a  qualified  and  imperfect  sense 
only.t 

•pago  178. 

t  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  defines  a  vohinlary  act  as  one  that  proceeds 
from  will,  with  (in  sense  fif  through)  a  knowledge  of  the  end.  When 
free,  such  acts,  he  says,  Iwlong  to  the  will  as  will.  When  not  free 
thoy  belong  to  will  a?  nature. 

Wc  sliuuid  notice,  also,  that  of  all  the  acts  that  proceed  from  will, 
only  one  is  not  a  free  act — namely,  the  desire  for  happiness.  Sec 
Chapter  on  Freedom  a«d  Morality. 


ON  HUMAN  ACTS  33 

But  though  voluntary  acts  and  free  acts  may  be 
regarded  under  certain  technical  conditions  as  co- 
extensive in  their  range,  still  it  is  necessary  to  insist 
that  freedom  is  no  part  of  the  direct  connotation  of 
voluntariness,  which  latter  term  means  simply  that  an 
action  proceeds  from  will  or  that  the  will  is  directed 
or  inclined  to  some  object.  And  it  is  in  this  sense  that 
we  speak  of  voluntariness  in  the  discussions  that 
follow,  u 

(c)  On  Voluntariness 

The  human  act  as  we  have  already  seen,  involves 
three  conditions — knowledge,  voluntariness,  and  free- 
dom. Now,  of  two  of  these  conditions  it  will  not  be 
necessary  to  speak  at  any  length  here — namely,  of  know- 
ledge and  of  freedom.  For  knowledge  is  a  necessary 
part  of  every  will-act,  and  it  will  be  sufficiently  dealt 
with  in  our  discussion  on  voluntariness.  Besides,  we 
shall  in  the  present  chapter  consider  the  impediments 
to  voluntariness,  one  of  which  is  ignorance,  and  from 
our  discussion  on  ignorance  we  shall  be  able  to  see  how 
far  knowledge  is  necessary  to  the  human  act.  Con- 
cerning freedom,  it  is  only  necessary  to  remember  at 
this  point  that  any  act  is  free  which  the  will  has  power 
to  do  or  not  to  do,  and  that  in  this  sense  freedom  is 
necessary  for  every  human  act.  An  exacter  and  fuller 
account  of  freedom  and  of  its  relation  to  Ethics  will  be 
given  in  a  later  chapter. 

But  we  must  here  enter  upon  a  formal  discussion  of 
the  various  kinds  of  voluntariness,  or  the  various  ways 
in  which  an  agent  can  be  said  to  will  aiv^^thing,  for  it  is 
not  always  easy  to  say  what  kinds  of  acts  are  voluntary, 
or  how  far  voluntariness  or  involuntariness  may  attach 
to  the  same  action,  and,  in  that  way,  it  is  possible  to 
mistake  the  range  of  application  of  our  science  which 
it  will  be  remembered  extends  to  voluntary  acts 
only. 

Vol.  1—3 


34  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

The  following  are  some  of  the  kinds  of  voluntariness 
which  are  of  most  importance  in  ethical  science  : — 


KINDS  OF  VOLUNTARINESS 

(I.)  Perfect  and  imperfect  voluntariness,  according  as 
we  know  clearly  and  full}^  intend  what  we  do,  or  know 
it  only  obscurely  and  consent  to  it  only  imperfectly. 

(11.)  Simple  voluntariness  [vohmtarium  simpliciter) 
and  conditional  voluntariness  [voluntarhmi  secundum 
quid).  The  former  means  that  the  will  either  has  no 
repugnance  to  the  thing  done  or  that  it  has  momentarily 
put  aside  its  repugnance  in  order  to  do  the  act  ;  the 
latter,  that  we  do  a  thing,  but  with  a  certain  measure  of 
repugnance.  That  this  second  kind,  however — the  so- 
called  conditional  voluntariness — has  reference  to  in- 
voluntariness  rather  than  to  voluntariness  will  be  seen 
from  the  following  example,  which  also  makes  clear 
the  distinction  between  simple  and  conditional  volun- 
tariness. When  the  captain  of  a  ship  throws  valuable 
goods  overboard  in  order  to  keep  his  ship  afloat  in 
rough  weather  his  act  is  sitfiply  *  or  absolutely  voluntary 
because  his  act  is  done  with  full  knowledge  and  consent, 
but  it  is  conditionally  {secundum  quid)  involuntary, 
which  means  that  he  would  not  have  thrown  the  goods 
overboard  if  there  were  no  storm.  In  other  words,  he 
throws  them  overboard  with  repugnance.  His  act  in 
this  case  is  said  to  be  voluntary  simply  [simpliciter)  but 
involuntary  conditionally  {secundum  quid), 

(III.)  Direct  and  indirect,  or  in  se  and  in  causa.  We 
will  a  thing  directly  when  we  will  it  in  itself  either  as 
means  or  as  end  (when  wished  directly  as  end  it  is 
wished  not  only  in  but  for  itself).     Thus,  the  man  who 

•  Examining  this  act  from  anotlior  point  of  view  Aristotlo  speaks 
of  It  as  .simply  (AirXiDt)  involuntary  ;  that  is,  if  you  abstract  from  the 
special  circumstances  of  the  case  aiid  consider  the  act  itself  of  throwing 
goods  overboard,  such  an  act  is  opposed  to  the  person's  will  (oi'SfU 
7A/1  Af  IXoiTO  KaOai'tb  ruiv  rotoOruv  oM^c).  Nich.  Eth.  HI.,  i,  (>.  liut, 
under  the  circumstances,  the  act  is  willed — it  is,  therefore,  con- 
dilion;""'^'  vi,|ihi1:ii v. 


ON  HUMAN  ACTS  35 

shoots  in  order  to  kill  a  bird  wills  both  ends  directly. 
We  will  a  thing  indirectly  when  we  will  not  the  thing 
in  itself,  but  something  of  which  it  is  a  consequence. 
Thus  the  man  who  fires  a  bomb-shell  at  a  monarch, 
knowing  that  it  will  kill  the  attendants  also,  wills  in- 
directly the  death  of  the  attendants,  and  consequently 
the  killing  of  them  is  voluntary,  even  though  their 
death  is  by  no  means  a  pleasure  to  the  assassin. 

(IV.)  Positive  and  negative.  Positive  willing  is  the 
willing  to  do.  Negative  *  willing  is  the  willing  not  to 
do.  The  man  who  voluntarily  neglects  his  business  is 
properly  regarded  as  responsible  for  its  decline  as  well 
as  the  man  who  injures  it  by  positive  bad  management. 

(V.)  Actual,  virtual,  habitual,  interpretative.]  Volun- 
tariness or  intention  is  actual  when  we  consent  to  what 
we  do  at  the  time  of  doing  the  act.  It  is  virtual  when 
the  thing  done  is  the  result  not  of  a  present  but  of  a 
former  intention.  It  is  habitual  when  the  act  done  is 
not  the  result  of  any  intention  present  or  past,  but 
nevertheless  corresponds  to  an  intention  formerly  made 
and  never  retracted.  An  example  will  bring  out  this 
distinction  of  virtual  and  habitual  intention.  The  man 
who  sets  out  to  walk  along  a  road,  and  then  in  conversa- 
tion with  a  friend  ceases  to  attend  to  the  fact  that  he  is 
walking,  virtually  intends  every  step  he  takes,  for  each 
step  is  a  result  of  the  intention  he  has  already  formed. 
But  the  man  who,  at  some  time  during  his  life,  made 
up  his  mind  to  kill  an  enemy,  and  has  not  as  yet  re- 
tracted that  resolution,  and  afterwards,  having  quite 
forgotten  about  his  resolution,  kills  him  for  some  other 
independent  reason,  is  said  to  have  had  the  habitual 
intention  of  killing  his  enemy.  Intention  is  interpretative 
when  we  have  never  actually  willed  a  certain  act  but 
would  will  it  if  we  knew  of  it  or  of  its  necessity. 


*  In  negative  willing  the  attitude  of  the  will  is  not  one  of  pure 
negation.     The  will  must  consciously  refuse  to  act. 

\  These  qualifying  expressions  are  more  often  used  with  the  word 
"  intention  "  than  with  "  voluntariness." 


36  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

These  two  latter  kinds  of  intention — habitual  and 
interpretative — though  not  so  important  as  the  first 
two  kinds,  are  not  without  their  effects  in  morals  and 
in  civil  law. 

Of  the  distinction  drawn  in  the  third  place  between 
direct  and  indirect  will  we  must  now  offer  some  further 
explanation. 


OF  INDIRECT  VOLUNTARINlgS  OR  WILL  IN  CAUS. 

In  determining  the  various  kinds  of  acts  that 
within  the  ethical  sphere,  and  may  be  gocxl  or  bad,  it 
is  easy  to  see  that  at  least  all  such  actions  lie  within 
the  moral  sphere  and  are  good  or  bad  which  a  man 
consciously  and  deliberately  elects  to  do.  But  some- 
times, attached  to  those  actions  which  please  us  and 
which  we  wish  to  do,  there  are  consequences  which  do 
not  interest  us  or  which,  perhaps,  displease  us,  and  it 
is  not  always  easy  to  say  whether  in  willing  the  act 
we  may  be  justly  said  to  will  or  be  justly  held  account- 
able for  these  consequences,  and  more  particularly 
whether,  if  these  consequences  are  bad,  we  are  bound 
always  to  refrain  from  the  action  to  which  they  attach. 

Now,  the  first  of  these  two  qijestions  may  be  answered 
very  briefly  by  saying  that  if  a  man  knows  that  attach- 
ing to  his  act  there  will  be  certain  evil  consequences, 
then,  whether  he  likes  these  consequences  or  does  not 
like  them,  we  must  regard  their  production  as  a  vt)lun- 
tary  act ;  for  the  will  in  causing  an  act  from  which 
these  consequences  spring  is  indirectly  also  the  cause  of 
the  consequences  of  this  act  {causa  causa  est  causa 
causati).  And  this  is  none  the  less  true  because  the 
consequences  may  sometimes  be  displeasing  to  us. 
For  when  we  do  an  act  we  do  the  whole  act,  just  as 
when  we  buy  a  house  we  buy  the  whole  house  ;  and 
80  a  man  is  said  to  will  and  be  the  cause  of  consequences 
which,  tak(!n  in  themHi^lves,  he  would  not  wish  to  pro- 
duce, just  as  in  buying  u  house  we  really  will  to  own  the 


ON   HUMAN  ACTS  37 

whole  house  though  some  features  of  it  may  displease 
us,  and  even  though  it  gives  us  no  pleasure  to  own  some 
parts  of  it.  The  will,  therefore,  is  the  true,  though  the 
indirect,  cause  of  all  the  known  consequences  of  our 
action,  and  if  the  act  that  we  do  is  a  free  act  and  the 
consequences  be  foreseen  then  we  are  rightl}'  held  to 
be  responsible  for  them. 

But  a  more  difficult  question  arises  concerning  a 
man's  moral  obligations  in  regard  to  these  consequences, 
whether,  namely,  in  the  case  of  evil  consequences,  he 
is  always  bound  to  refrain  from  the  action  to  which 
they  belong.  And  though  we  have  not  yet  given  any 
principles  of  conduct  which  might  guide  us  to  the  solu- 
tion of  this  problem,  still  it  arises  so  naturally  out  of 
the  question  of  indirect  voluntariness  now  under  con- 
sideration that  we  shall  be  pardoned  for  making  reference 
to  it  at  this  early  stage  of  our  work. 

Acts  that  are  in  themselves  good  or  indifferent  are 
not  always  forbidden  because  of  the  evil  consequences 
to  which  they  lead.  For  though  the  person  who  does 
these  acts  is  the  cause  of  the  consequences  to  which 
they  lead,  still  he  is  not  their  direct  cause,  nor  does  his 
will  rest  in  them  as  an  object.  It  is  always  wrong  to 
wish  evil  directly,  for  acts  are  morally  bad  or  good 
according  as  the  objects  of  our  wills  are  bad  or  good. 
But  such  a  rule  cannot  be  applied  to  cases  in  which 
the  will  is  not  fixed  on  an  evil  thing,  but  is  fixed  rather 
on  some  good  thing  from  which  certain  evil  consequences 
follow.  It  would,  for  instance,  be  an  absurd  thing  to 
charge  a  ruler  with  evil-doing  for  engaging  in  a  war 
which  is  otherwise  just  because  he  knows  that  many 
injustices  will  occur  through  means  of  it,  or  to  prevent 
a  man  from  saving  his  own  honour  even  though  some 
people  might  suffer  from  the  disclosures  that  have  to 
be  made  in  his  defence.  ^ 

The  question  then  arises — when  may  an  act  be  done 
in  spite  of  the  foreseen  evil  consequences  ?  and  when 
is  it  forbidden  on  account  of  these  consequences  ? 


1/ 


38  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Plainly,  if  the  consequences  are  all  evil  the  act  cannot 
be  done.  For  an  act  that  has  no  good  consequence  is 
bad  intrinsically^  since  if  it  were  either  good  or  in- 
different it  should  have  some  good  effect.  It  would 
be  at  least  an  exercise  of  liberty.  But  our  question 
gains  point  in  the  case  of  an  act  with  mixed  effects, 
some  good,  some  bad,  and  concerning  such  acts  we  must 
determine  when  they  are  allowed  and  when  the}'  are 
disallowed. 

Before,  however,  we  answer  this  question  it  is  neces- 
sary to  remark  that  causes  of  action  may  be  very 
different  in  kind  and  that  they  may  bear  very  different 
relations  to  the  effects  that  flow  from  them.  The  causes 
may  be  either  physical  or  moral  according  as  a  man  does 
an  act  himself  or  persuades  another  to  do  it.  Also 
they  are  proximate  or  remote  according  as  very  few  or 
many  secondary  intervening  causes  are  necessary  to  the 
^effect.  Again,  some  causes  are  natural,  others  are 
accidental.  Taking  poison  is  a  natural  cause  of  death. 
A  passing  locomotive  engine  is  often  the  accidental 
cause  of  fires  in  the  vicinity  of  railways.  These  dis- 
tinctions have  a  bearing  on  our  question  in  some  of  its 
applications,  but  it  is  only  the  general  question  that 
shall  here  be  answered. 

Our  answer  is  that  acts,  good  or  indifferent  in  them- 
selves, but  yet  productive  of  evil  consequences,  are 
allowed  under  the  following  three  conditions,  all  of 
which  must  be  fulfilled  : — (i)  The  bad  effect  must  be 
merely  permitted — it  must  not  be  desired  in  itself.  For 
if  the  bad  effect  be  desired  in  itself,  evil  is  desired 
directly,  and  it  is  never  lawful  jto<j  will  evil  directly. 
(2)  The  bad  effect  must  be  co-onTuiate  with  the  good. 
In  other  words,  the  good  effect  must  not  be  itself  a 
consequence  of  the  bad  effect,  for  in  that  case  the  bad 
^effect  would  be  willed  as  a  means  to  the  good  effect. 
But  to  will  a  bad  effect  as  means  is  to  will  it  directly, 
for  means  are  always  willed  directly — that  is,  they  are 
willed,   as   we   have   already   explained,   in   themselves 


ON  HUMAN  ACTS  39 

though  not  for  themselves  or  for  their  own  sake,  and, 
therefore,  the  will  that  is  directed  to  them  is  necessarily 
bad.  (3)  There  must  be  a  sufficient  cause  for  per- 
mitting the  evil  effect.  A  sufficient  excuse  is  always 
required  for  the  doing  of  an  act  from  which  an  evil  effect 
follows.  And  since  the  good,  effect  is,  our  excuse  in  the 
present  case,  the  present  condition  amounts  to  saying 
that  between  the  good  and  the  evil  effect  there  is  to 
be  a  due  proportion.  No  man  could  for  the  sake  of  a 
very  small  good  do  an  act  from  which  follows  a  very 
great  evil. 

If  these  three  conditions  are  fulfilled,  an  act,  which  in 
itself  is  either  good  or  indifferent,  is  allowable,  in  §pite 
of  the  evil  consequences  to  which  it  leads.  But  if  even 
one  of  these  conditions  be  unfulfilled,  then  the  act  is 
forbidden.* 

Following  these  rules  we  shall  be  able  to  compute 
when  an  act  may  lawfully  be  performed,  which,  though 
good  or  indifferent  in  itself,  involves  the  occurrence  of 
consequences  that  are  morally  evil.  But  of  the  two 
questions  proposed  by  us,  the  first — namely,  how  far 
the  effects  of  our  actions  may  be  regarded  as  voluntary 
— is  the  more  important  for  our  present  purpose,  for 
we  are  at  present  attempting  to  give  a  general  account 

*  These  conditions  sometimes  offer  difficulty  in  practice.  It  is  not 
easy  to  know  when  the  fjjood  effect  is  proportional  to  the  bad.  In 
estimating  the  proportion  there  are  certain  common-sense  maxims  to 
be  followed  —for  instance,  that  the  more  remote  our  act  is  from  the 
effect  (considering  the  number  of  intervening  causes  necessary  to  the 
production  of  the  evil  effect)  and  the  less  the  likelihood  of  the  effect 
following  from  our  act,  the  less  is  the  excuse  required.  We  should 
also  remember  that  if  we  decide  on  a  course  of  action  in  one  case — for 
instance,  if  we  decide  that  there  being  no  proportion  between  the 
good  and  the  bad  effect,  the  act  is  not  lawful  for  us^ — then  we  must  be* 
prepared  to  forego  this  act  every  time  the  same  circumstances  are  re- 
peated. This  of  itself  increases  the  awkwardness  and  evil  of  omitting 
the  act,  and  hence  a  less  amount  of  good  is  required  in  the  case  of  acts 
which  we  often  have  occasion  to  do  than  in  the  case  of  uncommon  acts. 
Again,  if  a  man  is  bound  from  his  position  to  guard  generally  against 
this  .precise  evil  effect,  then  a  greater  excuse  is  required  for  the  per- 
mitting of  the  effect  than  is  required  in  the  case  of  a  man  who  has  no 
special  duties  in  regard  to  this  effect.  Thus  a  soldier  on  guard  should 
suffer  almost  any  evil  rather  than  do  anything  from  which  the  betrayal 
of  his  comrades  might  possibly  follow  as  an  effect. 


40  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of  what  acts  are  voluntary  and  human,  and,  therefore, 
are  subject  to  ethical  rule. 


[d)  Of  what  makes  an  Act  less  Human 

Having  now  determined  what  it  is  that  makes  an 
action  human  and  thus  brings  it  within  the  sphere  of 
ethical  science,  we  turn  next  to  consider  a  kindred  and 
not  less  practical  question  which  also  appertains  to  the 
nature  of  the  human  act — namely,  what  are  those  things 
that  make  an  act  less  human,  that  diminish  the  moral 
character  of  our  acts  ?  In  this,  as  in  the  preceding 
question,  we  shall  do  very  little  more  than  explain  the 
teaching  of  the  scholastic  writers,  and  in  particular  the 
teaching  of  St.  Thomas  Aquinas. 

The  perfectly  human  act  is,  as  we  saw,  one  of  which 
we  have  perfect  knowledge,  and  which  is  perfectly  under 
the  control  of  will.  But  opposed  to  knowledge  is 
ignorance  ;  and  the  control  of  the  will  is  impaired  from 
two  causes — namely,  violence  from  without  and  passion 
from  within.  And,  therefore,  we  shall  in  the  following 
sections  consider  these  three  things-Zignorance,  violence, 
and  passion — in  relation  to  voluntarmess  and  freedoni^ 


^F  IGNORANCE 

Qgnorance  means  absence  of  knowledge  in  one  who 
has  naturally  the  faculty  of  knowledge^  In  reference  to 
action  it  may  be  either  antecedent,  concomitant,  or 
consequent.  Ignorance  is^  antecedent  when  the  act  that 
we  do  is  done  through  ignorance,  and  would  not  have 
been  done  but  for  ignorance — on  the  contrary,  would 
have  been  avoided  had  we  had  any  knowledge  of  our 
action.  It  is  concomitant  when  it  is  done  merely  in 
ignorance,  but  not  on  account  of  ignorance,  and  there- 
fore would  have  been  done  even  if  ignorance  had  been 
replaced  by  knowledge.     Ignorance  is  consequent  wlion 


ON  HUMAN  ACTS  41 

it   is   itself   consciously   and   voluntarily   procured   and 
maintained  by  the  agent. 

When  ignorance  is  antecedent,  the  resultant  act-  is 
not  only  involuntary,*  but  is  actually  opposed  to  our 
inner  will,  and  therefore  we  are  not  responsible  for  it. 
Thus  a  man  who  fir-es  at  an  animal,  not  knowing  that  a 
child  is  near,  could  not  be  said  to  kill  the  child  volun- 
tarily. Where  ignorance  is  concomitant  our  act  is  simply 
involuntary,  in  the  sense  of  not  willed  (it  is  not  neces- 
sarily opposed  to  our  wills),  and  we  are  not  responsible 
for  its  performance.  When  ignorance  is  consequent  the 
act  is  neither  involuntary  nor  opposed  to  our  will,  but 
is  simply  voluntary,  and  we  are  responsible  for  its  per- 
formance. Of  consequent  ignorance  there  are  two  kinds 
— ignorance  which  is  directly  willed  and  ignorance 
which  is  willed  only  indirectly.  Qt  is  directly  willed 
when  we  actually  strive  to  remain  in  ignorance — that 
is,  when  we  take  care  not  to  know  ;  indirectly  when  we 
simply  neglect  to  learn,  but  do  not  actually  desire  to  be 
ignorant.  vThe  first  kind  of  ignorance  is  called  affected 
ignorance.  The  second  when  gravely  culpable  is  called 
crass,  ignorances  and  it  is  gravely  culpable  when  we 
negleqt  to  use  what,  humanly  speaking,  are  ordinary 
means  for  its  removal.  Sometimes  the  removal  of 
ignorance  is  possible  by  the  use  of  extraordinary  means 
only,  and  then  our  ignorance  is  not  accounted  con- 
sequent, but  concomitant.  Now,  neither  of  these  two 
kinds  of  consequent  ignorance — affected  or  crass — makes 
an  act  involuntary,  for  the  simple  reason  that  the  act 
done  under  their  influence  is  due  to  that  of  which  we 
are  ourselves  the  cause.  But  though  affected  and  crass 
ignorance  do  not  wholly  destroy  the  voluntariness  of  an 
act,  yet  they  do  impair  its  voluntariness  to  some  extent, 
and  if  the  act  is  bad  they  diminish  the  evil  of  it ;  for  it 
is  better  to  refuse  to  know  the  law,  so  as  not  knowingly 

*  The  scholastics  use  the  word  "  involuntarium  "  to  denoto  what 
is  opposed  to  a  man's  will.  The  English  word  cannot  be  so  used.  It 
simply  means  "  not  voluntary  "  or  "  not  willed." 


42  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

jto  break  it,  than  to  break  the  law  with  a  fun  conscious- 
/ness  that  we  are  violating  it.     In  the  forn^er  case  the 
violation  of  law  is  accompanied  by  some  respect,  i'ii  the 
latter  there  is  violation  and  no  respect 


ON   VIOLENCE 

Violence  destroys  voluntariness  and  freedom  in  him 
who  suffers  violence,  for  an  act  done  through  violence 
is  caused  not  by  the  agent  who  suffers  the  violence,  but 
by  him  who  inflicts  it,  whereas  voluntariness  implies 
that  an  act  is  done  by  the  agent  himself  as  cause. 

However,  it  is  sometimes  hard  to  determine  how  far 
an  agent  who  is  violently  compelled  to  an  act  is  to  be 
held  responsible  for  the  same.  And  this  difficulty 
arises  from  two  causes — first,  because  an  act  may  be 
not  wholly  due  to  violence.  A  man  may  resist  violence 
and  yet  to  some  extent  co-operate  with  it.  Secondly, 
even  when  the  violence  is  such  as  cannot  be  resisted, 
still  ^he  wiU  retains  always  the  power  of  determining 
itself  independently  of  the  external  violence  used,  for 
violence  cannot  affect  the  willj  Questions,  therefore, 
arise  concerning  the  duty  of  external  resistance  and 
also  concerning  the  internal  consent  which  may  be 
given.  But  these  questions  we  shall  not  consider  here, 
since  we  are  here  merely  considering  what  things  can 
affect  voluntariness  and  freedom — violence  being  one 
of  them. 


THE   PASSIONS 

The  effect  of  passion  on  the  voluntariness  of  acts  is 
set  forth  by  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  in  a  number  of  pro- 
[H,  iiiMiiH  whirl^  have  now  come  to  be  looked  upon  as 
ii<<<  s.iiy  formuhe  for  the  solution  of  practical  (luestions 
on  voluntariness  and  responsibility.  We  give  them  here 
witii  the  briefpHt  possible  explanation  : — 

(i)  Concupmentia    antecedens    auget    voluntariion    sed 


ON  HUMAN   ACTS  43 

minuit  liberum — that  is,  where  passion  is  not  itself  con- 
sciously worked  up,  where  it  precedes  our  act,  it  increases 
voluntariness  in  the  sense  of  increasing  the  onward 
movement  of  the  will,  but  it  lessens  liberty  since  it 
lessens  one's  control  over  his  act. 

(2)  Concupiscentia  consequens  auget  voluntarium — that 
is,  where  passion  is  consciously  worked  up  it  increases 
voluntariness,  for  it  increases  the  onward  movement  of 
the  will.  It  also  increases  liberty  in  sense  of  increasing 
the  amount  of  free  action. 

(3)  Concupiscentia  consequens  ei  totaliter  tollens  usum 
rationis  non  tollit  voluntarium.  Passion,  when  directly 
worked  up,  may  completely  take  away  the  use  of 
Reason,  and  still  the  act  is  voluntary  and  free. 

(4)  Concupiscentia  antecedens  totaliter  tollens  usum 
rationis  tollit  voluntarium.  Passion  which  we  do  not 
ourselves  cause,  and  which  completely  takes  away  the 
use  of  Reason,  completely  destroys  voluntariness  and 
freedom. 

(5)  Concupiscentia  non  totaliter  tollens  usum  rationis, 
et  antecedens.  minuit  liberum.  Passion  which  we  do  not 
ourselves  cause,  if  it  should  interfere  with  the  use  of 
Reason,  lessens  freedom  for  the  reason  given  before. 

These  five  propositions,  in  so  far  as  they  relate  to 
voluntariness,  yield  the  following  resultant  which  St. 
Thomas  Aquinas  gives  as  expressing  the  general  relation 
subsisting  between  passion  and  voluntariness — concupi- 
scentia magis  facit  voluntarium  quam  involupiarium — 
the  general  effect  of  passion  is  to  increase  voluntariness 
in  the  sense  of  intensifying  the  onward  movement  of 
the  will  to  any  object. 

It  is  usual  in  works  on  moral  science  to  pay  some 
special  attention  to  the  passion  of  fear.*  Fear  is  the 
recoiling  of  the  mind  from  impending  evil.  It  h^sthis 
distinctive  characteristic,  that  it  induces  the  will  to  do 


*  The  full  enumeration  and  classification  of  the  passions  can  be 
found  in  any  standard  work  on  Psychology — for  instance,  in  Maher's 
"  Psychology." 


44  THE  SCIENCE  OE  ETHICS 

an  act  which  the  will  of  itself  would  not  do — that  is, 
which  it  would  not  do  were  it  not  under  the  influence  of 
fear.  Thus  the  captain  of  a  ship  will,  in  order  to  save 
his  vessel,  throw  out  even  valuable  goods  which  it  is  no 
pleasure  to  him  to  lose.  And  though  the  throwing  out 
of  these  goods  is  secundum  quid  involuntary — that  is, 
would  not  be  willed,  did  ordinary  circumstances  prevail, 
yet  absolutely  [simpliciter]  the  loss  of  them  is  voluntary 
since  de  facto  these  circumstances  do  prevail  and  the 
goods  are  thrown  over.     When  an  act  is  done  jrom  fear 

bits  voluntariness  is  lessened,  but  not  when  done  merely 

\iDith  fear. 

Fear,  like  the  other  passions,  may  be  so  strong  as 
totally  to  destroy  one's  liberty,  and  an  act  so  done  is 
hot  a  human  act.  It  is  an  actus  hominis,  not  an  actus 
humanus.  But  if  fear  be  not  so  strong  as  to  destroy 
freedom,  the  act  done  under  its  influence  is  free  and 
human,  in  the  degree  in  which  Reason  is  allowed  to 
play  its  part.  If  the  evil  feared  be  grave,  then  the  fear 
is  grave  ;  if  the  evil  be  light,  then  the  fear  is  light. 
But  these  terms  must  be  understood  as  relative  to  the 
person  affected,  for  what  would  be  grave  fear  for  one 
person  may  be  light  for  another. 

But  the  positive  law  often  invalidates  an  act  which  is 
done  from  fear,  not  because  the  act  which  a  person  does 
from  fear  is  not  voluntary  in  itself,  but  because  it  is  for 
the  common  good  that  an  act  so  done  should  be  invali- 
dated in  certain  cases.  The  conditions  -generally  re- 
quired for  such  "  invalidation  "  depend  upon  particular 
forms  of  legislation  and  the  kind  of  act  that  is  being 
legislated  for.  There  is,  however,  one  condition  that  is 
pretty  generally  regarded  as  necessary  ifi  all  such  cases — 
namely,  that  the  fear  which  invalidates  an  act  must  be 
excited  by  someone  directly  and  wrongfully,' and  for  the 
express  purpose  of  obtaining  consent  to  the  act  in  ques- 
tion— **  directe  et  injuste  incussus  ad  exiorquendiim  con- 
sensum." 
These  are  the  principal  elements  that  lessen  Ihc  human 


ON  HUMAN  ACTS  45 

character  of  acts — ignorance,  violence  and  passion  * — 
and  it  is  for  the  morahst  to  compute  in  individual  cases 
how  far  an  act  done  under  their  influence  is  voluntary 
and  human  and  falls  within  the  range  of  Ethical  Science. 

*  Some  ethicians  give  prominence  also  to  habit  as  a  fourth  factor. 
The  consideration  of  it  here  would  bring  us  too  far  afield  in  a  work 
like  the  present. 


CHAPTER  III 

OF  THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  * 

Having  in  the  preceding  chapter  treated  of  the  human 
act  considered  in  itself,  we  must  now  treat  of  the  ends 
of  human  action,  for,  as  we  shall  prove,  every  human 
act  derives  its  specific  quality  from  the  end  to  which  it 
is  directed,  and  moral  quality  belongs  to  action  in  so 
far  as  it  is  directed  by  Reason  to  the  final  end. 
We  shall,  therefore,  treat  of  three  questions  : — 

(a)  Of  ends  of  human  action,  and  in  particular  of 
the  last  end. 

(b)  Of   the   objective   last   end,   or   of   the   object   in 
which  our  supreme  happiness  consists. 

(c)  Of  the  subjective  last  end,  or  of  happiness  as  a 
subjective  state. 


(a)  Of  Ends  in  General 
(i)  All  human  action  is  done  for  some  end. 

We  have  already  distinguished  between  hunmn  acts 
{actus  humani)  and  acts  of  men  {actus  hominis).  Qiuman 
acts,   we  showed,   are  acts  that  proceed  from  men  as 

♦  With  the  spread  of  the  Kantian  philosophy  it  became  customary 
to  regard  all  systems  of  Ethics  which  based  morality  on  distinctions 
of  "  end  "  or  "  purpose  "  as  spurious  systems.  The  most  recent 
writers,  however,  have  returned  to  the  older  Aristotelian  theory  and 
regard  Ethics  as  a  teleological  science. 

We  should  mention  that  Kant  himself  saw  no  a  priori  difliculty 
in  the  conception  of  a  teleological  Ethics,  for  he  actually  began  his 
exposition  with  an  enquiry  into  the  ends  of  human  action,  and  it  was 
only  l)ccausc  he  could  not,  amongst  i\w  various  ends  of  action,  iind  a 
final  end  or  an  end  that  was  not  a  means  to  j)leasure  (an  assumption 
which  we  shall  disprove  in  the  pre.sent  chai)lei)  that  he  rejected  the 
theory  of  teleological  Ethics  and  adopted  the  theory  of  autonomy,  to 
be  discussed  later — p.  O52. 

46 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  47 

such — that  is,  from  the  will  under  the  influence  of 
Reason^  An  act  of  a  man  {actus  hominis)  is  one  which 
belongs  to  a  man  in  some  way,  but  yet  does  not  proceed 
from  will,  and  is  not  under  the  control  of  Reason.  Now, 
these  latter  acts  may,  indeed,  be  directed  to  an  end,  but 
he  to  whom  they  belong  does  not  direct  them  to  their 
end.  The  beating  of  the  heart  has  a  purpose,  but  that 
purpose  is  of  nature's  making,  not  of  man's.  These 
indeliberate  acts  we  now  put  completely  out  of  our 
purview,  for  Ethics  has  nothing  to  do  with  them.  We 
have  to  treat  of  human  acts  only,  and  concerning  these 
human  acts  our  first  thesis  is  that  they  are  all  done  for 
some  end.  We  take  exercise  for  health's  sake,  or  to 
test  our  powers,  or  for  mere  amusement.  We  read  for 
information's  sake,  or  to  pass  the  time.  All  these  are 
acts  of  the  will,  and  the  will  must  wish  "  end,"  as  is 
evident  from  ordinary  experience.* 

•  (2)  Besides  human  agents  other  things  also  act  for  ends. 

(Everything  that  moves  tends  to  the  attainment  of 
an  end.  But  all  action  is  movement.  Therefore,  every- 
thing that  acts  tends  to  attain  an  end.y 

Now,  things  move  to  ends  in  various  ways  and  under 
the  influence  of  different  appetites.  Human  movements 
are  self-directed — that  is,  they  are  the  result  of  choice, 
and  are  done  under  the  control  of  the  rational  appetite 
of  will.  Animals  are  moved  by  a  sense  appetite,  and 
their  acts  are  not  self-directed,  because  they  neither 
choose  the  end  nor  the  means,  nor  do  they  formally 
realise  the  relation  between  means  and  end.  Aguntur 
potius  qiiam  agunt,  as  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  says.  Plants 
and  the  inorganic  substances  are  moved  to  their  ends 
by  what  is  sometimes  called  "  natural  "  appetite,  in  the 
sense  of  an  appetite  which  has  no  dependence  on  know- 

*  Many  modern  ethicians  are  not  sufficiently  careful  to  distinguish 
"  end  "  from  "  consequence."  End  is  nothing  more  than  the  object 
which  is  desired.     Consequences  are  not  always  desired. 


48  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

ledge,  whether  intellectual  or  sensile,*  but  springs  un- 
consciously out  of  the  very  nature  of  the  body,  and  is 
inseparable  from  this  nature.  Animals  and  men  are 
also  moved  by  "  natural  "  appetites  in  so  far  as  they 
are  substances  merely,  not  conscious  beings.  But 
whether  the  principle  of  action  be  intellectual  appetite 
or  sensile  appetite,  or  the  mere  natural  appetite  of  un- 
conscious life,  all  action,  all  change,  is  a  movement  to 
the  attainment  of  or  the  continued  possession  of  some 
end. 

^(3)  Human  acts  derive  all  their  character  from  the  end 
to  which  they  are  directed. 

(y\.ll  movement  is  denominated  by,  and  receives  its 
direction  from,  the  endy  And  as  acts  are  movements 
they  also  receive  their  character  from  the  end  which 
they  subserve.  Acts  in  general  are  distinguished  ac- 
cording to  their  objects.  For  when  a  thing  is  wholly 
for  another  then  what  it  is  depends  on  that  other. 
Now,  faculties  are  wholly  for  acts,  and  acts  for  their 
formal  objects.  Hence  it  is  from  the  object  that  we 
determine  the  specific  character  both  of  the  faculty  and 
the  act.  Thus  we  distinguish  the  various  acts  of  mind 
in  Psychology  by  the  objects  which  they  concern.  The 
sensitive  act  concerns  a  particular  material  object  ; 
the  act  of  intellect  a  universal  object.  But  the  object 
of  will  is  the  end  ;  and,  therefore,  the  character  of  our 
will-acts  is  determined  by  end.  Nor  should  we,  gifl  St. 
Thomas  Aquinas  remarks,  regard  the  end  of  the  act  of 
the  will  as  something  quite  extrinsic  to  the  act.  The 
end  is  the  term  and  principle  of  the  act,  and  therefore 
is  part  of  its  nature.  It  is  because  all  will-acts  are 
specified  through  the  end  to  which  they  lead  that  the 

•  The  word  "  natural  "  has  many  meanings.  Here  it  is  used  as 
oppoHcd  to  "  con.scious."  It  is  sometimes  also  used  to  signify  that 
which  is  not  the  resull  of  free  choice.  Hut  it  is  most  generally  used  to 
lignify  that  which  accords  with  the  requirements  of  tlic  law  of  nature. 
TniH  third  will  be  our  meaning  in  the  present  work,  except  where  we 
•ay  cxprcsyly  tu  the  contrary. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  49 

science  of  Ethics  begins  with  the  study  of  ends,  or  that 
it  is  teleological. 

V|4)  There  must  he  a  final  end  to  which  all  human  acts 
are  directed. 

This  proposition  is  simply  an  application  of  the 
general  formula  that  a  dependent  series  cannot  extend 
to  infinity.  It  must  have  a  beginning  somewhere.  A 
dependent  series  is  a  series  in  which  each  member 
depends  for  its  existence  on  some  other  member,  that 
again  on  another,  and  so  on.  Now,  a  series  of  which 
all  the  members  are  dependent,  is  intrinsically  impos- 
sible. For  a  number  of  dependent  members  implies 
the  existence  of  one  independent  member  on  which  the 
others  depend.  If  there  be  no  such  independent  member 
the  others  could  not  have  come  into  existence.  Granted 
their  existence,  therefore,  the  existence  of  the  indepen- 
dent unit  is  necessarily  conceded.  That  independent 
unit  will  form  the  beginning  of  the  whole  series,  and 
from  it  the  rest  will  proceed  in  due  order. 

Now,  the  series  considered  in  Ethics — the  series  of 
means  and  ends — is  a  dependent  series.  For  it  is  be- 
cause the  end  is  desired  that  we  desire  the  means. 
We  desire  a,  because  we  desire  b  to  which  it  leads, 
h  because  we  desire  c,  and  so  on.  Being  a  dependent 
series,  this  extending  line  of  means  and  ends  must  finish 
(and  in  another  sense  must  begin)  somewhere  with  an 
end  which  is  desired  for  its  own  sake  only,  ^hat  end 
with  which  the  whole  series  of_means  and  ends  terminates 
is  our  supreme  and  final  good.j 

'■*  (5)  All  that  a  man  desires  is  desired  on  account  of  the 
ultimate  end. 

St.  Thomas'  proof  of  this  very  important  proposition 
is  two-fold  : — 

First,  the  final  end  is  related  to  movements  of  appetite 

*  Et  Sri  Ti  WXos  iffrl  tCiv  vpaKrQv  6  SI  airrd  ^ovXSfieOa  r^XXa  5^  Siii  tovto, 
Kai  fj.T)  rrtt'ira  Si  'inpov  alpovfitda  {vpdeKTi  yap  oOtu  y  els  &ireipov  uxtt  elvai 
Kevi]v  Kai  /jLaraiav  T7]f  6pe^ii>),  S^Xov  wj  i-oi>r'  &v  fft)  rdyadbv  Kal  rb  tpuTTOv. 
— (Nich.  Eth.,  Book  \  ,  ch.  U.) 

Vol.  1—4 


50  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

as  the  first  mover  is  related  to  other  movements.  But, 
in  other  movements,  the  secondary  or  subordinate 
movers  act  by  virtue  of  and  in  so  far  as  they  are  moved 
by  the  prime  mover.  Therefore,  also,  it  is  by  virtue 
of  the  ultimate  end  that  subordinate  ends  are  able  to 
move  our  wills  ;  consequently  whatever  else  a  man  may 
desire  he  desires  it  on  account  of  the  ultimate  end — that 
is,  as  leading  to  the  ultimate  end,  or  as  seeming  to  lead 
to  it. 

Secondly,  that  which  a  man  desires  he  desires  under 
the  aspect  of  good,  which  if  it  be  not  itself  the  perfect 
good,  which  is  our  ultimate  end,  is  sought  as  tending  to 
the  perfect  good.  "  For  the  beginning  of  anything  is 
ordained  to  its  perfect  accomplishment,  not  only  in  the 
case  of  things  which  are  of  nature's  making,  but  also  in 
the  case  of  products  of  art.  Hence  an  imperfect  good  is 
always  looked  for  as  an  instalment  of  the  perfect,  which 
is  our  ultimate  end."  This  principle,  on  which  St. 
Thomas  lays  so  much  stress  [omnis  vnchoatio  perfcctionis 
ordinatur  in  perfectionem  consummatam) ,  will  come  before 
us  again  in  other  connections,  and  it  is  well  we  should 
have  a  clear  idea  of  what  it  means.  We  shall  illustrate 
it  by  example.  It  does  not  mean  that  if  a  man  puts 
a  pound  into  his  pocket  he  puts  it  there  necessarily  as 
leading  on  to  more.  It  means  that  if  a  man  wishes  to 
put  a  pound  into  his  pocket,  then  each  shilling  that  he 
puts  in  his  pocket  is  placed  there  as  leading  up  to  the 
pound.  So  also,  if  the  ultimate  end  of  any  series  be 
already  determined  upon  and  desired,  then  each  member 
of  the  series  is  desired  as  leading  to,  and  by  virtue  of 
our  desire  for,  the  last  end.  But  we  shall  show  *  that  the 
final  end  is  necessarily  desired,  and  therefore  all  other 
ends  are  desired  as  leading  to  it. 

Again,  the  principle  that  everything  is  done  with  a 
view  to  the  ultimate  end  does  not  mean  that  in  each  act 
that  we  do  we  must  think  actually  of  the  ultimate  end. 
For  a  man  does  not  think  of  the  end  of  his  journey  at 

*  pago  ax6. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  51 

each  step.  It  means  simply  that  each  end  is  sought  in 
virtue  of  our  ultimate  end,  as  each  step  in  walking  is 
taken  in  virtue  of  the  end  we  desire  to  reach  in  walking. 

^(i)  To  any  9ne  individuMl  there  cannot  he  many  ulti- 
mate ends.* 

The  reason  of  this  proposition  is  contained  in  the  very 
notion  of  ultimate  end.  The  ultimate  end  of  anj^lhing 
is  that  which  fills  up  the  measure  of  its  capacities,  and 
includes  everything  which  that  thing  may  achieve  or 
tend  to  achieve.  Thus  the  ultimate  end  of  a  plant  is 
flowering  and  bearing  seed,  because  these  acts  fill  up  its 
highest  capacity,  and  to  them  all  the  other  capacities 
are  directed.  So  the  end  of  each  man  will  be  found  to 
consist  in  that  act  or  object  which  leaves  him  nothing 
to  be  desired.  Now,  if  for  each  individual  man  there 
were  many  final  ends  no  one  of  them  could  fulfil  the 
.  conditions  of  a  final  end  ;  for  no  one  of  them  could 
satisfy  our  appetites.  Having  attained  any  one  of 
them  it  would  still  be  possible  to  desire  the  others. 
Hence  no  man  can  have  many  final  ends. 

Again,  the  final  end  must  be  natural.  But  the  nature 
of  each  thing  is  determined  to  one  end  only :  the  eye 
can  see  only,  the  ear  hear  only.  So  also  the  final  end, 
being  natural,  will  be  one  only. 

We  may  be  permitted  to  ask  here  whether  the  final 
end,  besides  being  one,  is  also  a  single  thing.  If  an 
animal  were  possessed  of  only  two  perfectly  co-ordinate 
appetites,  with  objects  quite  distinct  from  each  other, 
its  end  would  be  one  but  complex — it  would  be  the  sum 
of  those  two  dbjects,  and,  if  possible,  their  simultaneous 
attainment.  But  in  organisms  generally,  the  appetites 
are  not  co-ordinate.  One  faculty  is  built  on  another 
and  includes  the  object  of  that  other,  and  therefore 
their  final  end  will  not  be  complex  but  single.     It  will 

♦This  does  not  mean  that  the  ultimate  end  must  be  one  thing  or 
simple.  It  means  that  there  cannot  be  many  objects  each  of  which  is 
our  ultimate  end. 


52  THE  SCIENCE  OE  ETHICS 

be  the  highest  end  of  the  highest  faculty.  In  man 
the  will  includes  in  its  object  the  object  of  every  faculty. 
Man's  final  end  therefore  will  be  what  satisfies  the  will, 
and  as  each  faculty  has  a  single  natural  object  this  end 
will  be  single.* 

V  (7)   The  ultimate  end  is  the  same  for  all  men. 

That  men  often  mistake  their  last  end  is  true  ;  and 
so  far  men  certainly  are  not  in  agreement  about  what 
it  consists  in.  Some  men  place  it  in  riches,  some  in 
honour,  some  in  bodily  pleasure.  Even  about  these 
things,  however,  there  is  this  much  unity — that  they 
are  all  looked  upon  and  desired  as  a  perfection  of  some 
kind,  and  so  far  men  are  in  agreement  concerning  the 

'  ultimate  end.  But  apart  from  subjective  views  of  the 
matter,  and  speaking  of  objective  truth  alone,  we  affirm 
that  all  men  have  a  common  ultimate  end.  For  nature, 
as  we  observed  in  our  last  paragraph,  is  determined  to 
one  end  always.     Things,  therefore,  that  have  the  same 

I  nature  must  in  so  far  have  also  the  same  ultimate  natural 
end,  which  is  merely  the  perfect  fulfilment  of  the  common 

'nature.  The  end  of  the  eye  is  the  same  in  all  men.  The 
end  of  the  ear  is  the  same  for  all ;  and  so  for  every 
natural  organ  or  function.     The  last  end  of  our  whole 

•  Dr.  Simmel  remarks  in  his  "  Einleitung  "  that  "  the  assumption 
of  a  single  last  end  is  one  of  the  most  widespread  errors  of  teleological 
thinking."  We  quite  agree  with  Dr.  Simmel  that  we  have  no  right  to 
take  the  existence  of  a  single  ultimate  end  for  granted.  With  us,  how- 
ever, it  is  not  an  assumption,  but  an  established  fact.  What  the 
single  end  is  will  be  shown  presently,  and  the  proof  of  it  will  rest 
upon  the  natural  content  of  our  appetites. 

To  the  same  effect  we  have  the  contention  of  modem  evolutionist 
philosophers,  that  since  man  is  possessed  of  many  appetites  he  cannot 
have  a  single  ultimate  end.  "  The  happiness  which  all  men  desire," 
writes  Ix-slic  Stephen,  "  is  not  a  single  end,  but  a  name  for  many  and 
radically  different  forms  of  gratification.  The  description  just  given 
(that  of  the  ultimate  end  as  single)  would  hold  in  strictness  of  notliing 
but  a  polyp — an  organism  swayed  by  a  single  desire."  We  reply  that 
every  organism  must  move  to  a  single  end,  else  it  is  not  an  organism. 
The  end  of  a  locomotive  is  one.  The  end  of  man  with  his  faculties 
and  apiK'titcs  will  l)c  one  also.  In  the  ca.sc  of  man  the  separate 
faculfie.s  have  each,  no  doubt,  their  own  end  ;  but  they  will  W  all 
contained  nccc.s.sarily  in  the  object  of  the  master  appetite — the  will. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  53 

nature  as  men,  the  last  natural  end  of  our  supreme 
appetite — -.that  is  to  say,  the  appetite  which  includes  the 
objects  of  all  the  others — must  be  one  and  the  same  in 
all.     Hence  the  final  end  is  the  same  for  all  men. 


(b)  The  Ultimate  End 

Our  ultimate  end  is  twofold — objective  and  subjective] 
By  objective  *  end  we  mean  the  end  or  object  which  we 
desire  ultimately  to  attain,  whether  that  object  be 
within  us  or  without  us.  By  subjective  end  we  mean 
the  attainment  and  possession  of  the  thing  desired,  or 
what  is  called  beatitude.  There  can  be  no  doubt  about 
there  being  two  ends  of  human  action — a  subjective  and  an 
objective  end — as  experience  and  Reason  both  prove,  and 
they  are  certainly  correlated,  each  being  for  the  other. 
We  must,  therefore,  enquire  in  what  each  of  those  ends 
respectively  consists.  The  objective  final  end,  or  that 
thing  which  we  finally  aim  at  attaining,  is  evidently  that 
object  or  end  wliich  \\'ill  completely  fill  up  our  capacity 
for  desiring,  completely  satisfy  our  appetites  ;  and  as 
the  will  or  master  appetite  includes  in  its  object  the 
objects  of  all  the  other  appetites  the  final  objective  end 
will  be  that  the  attainment  of  which  satisfies  the  will. 
The  subjective  final  end  Aristotle  calls  by  the  name 
happiness  {evSai/iovia).  By  happiness,  however,  as 
subjective  end  of  action,  he  means  the  satisfaction  of 
desire,  or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  the  attainment  of  an 
end  desired.  Happiness  in  this  sense  is  to  be  carefully 
distinguished  from  that  delight  (vySony)  which  hedonists 
say,  constitutes  our  final  end,  viz.,  that  glow  of  pleasure- 
feeling  which   sometimes,   and  indeed  only   sometimes, 

*  The  reader  should  take  notice  of  the  meaning  here  given  to  the 
word  "  objective."  By  objective  end  we  do  not  here  mean  "  external 
end  "  necessarily,  but  simply  ,"  that  thing  which  is  desired."  Our 
present  question,  therefore,  is — what  is  that  thing  which  the  will 
ultimately  desires,  and  on  account  of  which  it  desires  all  other  things  ? 
Whether  this  thing  is  external  to  the  will  or  internal  will  be  discussed 
later— p    59. 


54  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

arises  in  one  when  an  end  desired  has  been  attained. 
Pleasure  or  dehght  in  this  sense,  so  far  from  being 
identical  with  that  happiness  which  Aristotle  represents 
as  our  final  subjective  end,  is  spoken  of  by  him  as  rrierely 
an  ingredient  of  happiness,  and  a  necessary  ingredient 
only  of  perfect  happiness.*  We  shall  now  discuss  the 
question  of  our  final  end,  first  the  objective,  second,  the 
subjective  end. 

Of  the  Objective  Final  End 

Concerning  the  object  of  perfect  happiness  or  our 
final  objective  end  we  ask  two  questions — (i)  Is  it 
possible  to  determine  this  end  ?     (2)  What  is  this  end  ? 

(i)  Just  as  the  final  end  of  a  tree  or  a  horse  is  that 
end  or  sum  of  ends  which  fully  satisfies  its  capacities, 
so  the  final  natural  objective  end  of  man  will  be  that 
end  which  fully  satisfies  the  range  of  his  natural  appetites 
and  capacities.  Aristotle  describes  the  final  end,  as  self- 
sufficing,  or,  all-sufficing,  that  is,  it  must  be  such  as  to 
satisfy  the  whole  range  of  our  appetites  {rh  yap  reXeiov 
dyadhv  ovTapK€s  €7vai  So/cei)  ;  and  he  himself  teUs  us  what 
is  meant  by  self-sufficing — it  means  what  makes  life 
fully  desirable  and  in  want  of  nothing  (to  8'aiVap«:€s  ridefxev 

•  olofieOa  re  Seiv  ijSovrjv  Trapafjie/iixOai  rrj  evS/xovia  (Nich.  Eth.  X.,  7). 
That  happiness  as  final  end  of  action  was  regarded  by  Aristotle 
as  distinct  from  the  glow  of  pleasure-feeling  which  Hedonists 
represent  as  constituting  our  final  end  is  obvious  from  A's  definition 
of  happiness,  which  is  the  act  of  a  faculty  about  its  object  in  accordance 
with  perfect  excellence.  The  glow  of  feeling  just  described  is  not  the 
act  of  a  faculty  about  its  object. 

It  is  highly  important  that  the  reader  should  appreciate  fully 
Aristotle's  conception  of  happiness.  The  feeling  experienced  as  a 
consequenoe  of  attaining  an  end  desired  may  indeed  accompany 
happiness,  but  there  is  a  more  fundamental  element  still,  the  essen- 
tial constitutive  element  of  happiness,  viz.,  the  attaining  of  the  end 
desired.  Happiness  and  satisfaction  are  one.  And  satisfaction,  or 
the  satisfying  of  desire,  or  the  bringing  of  a  desire  to  rest,  consists  in 
the  attaining  of  the  end.  The  glow  of  feeling  mentioned  may  or  may 
not  accompany  tiiis  act.  A  man  CJin  be  ha]>j)y  without  these  feelings. 
In  many  moments  of  intense,  and  in  practically  all  cases  of  (juiet, 
l)aj)i)iiicsH  we  are  conscious  merely  of  attaining  an  end  desired, 
Hapi»ini-sH,  therefore,  essentially  consists  in  attaining  an  end  desired. 
It  consistH  a»  Mr.  NIallock  writes  (Crit.  Exam,  of  Socialism,  p.  2J^ 
in  "  the  cquatiou  between  desire  and  attainment." 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  55 

o  /JLovovfKVOv  alperhv  Trotei   tov   /3tov  /cat  firjSevo'i  ei'Sea).      The  final 

end,  therefore,  must  include  all  that  we  can  desire. 
As  Sir  A.  Grant  finel}/  remarks,  the  last  end  must  be 
the  best  "  not  as  being  really  placed  on  a  level  with 
other  goods,  or  ranked  among  them  as  being  the  '  best 
of  the  lot,'  but  as  including  all  the  lot  in  itself  so  that 
beside  it  there  is  no  (human)  good  left  that  could  possibly 
be  added  to  it." 

Now  this  end  it  must  be  possible  to  determine,  for 
by  Psychology  we  are  able  to  determine  the  objects  of 
the  various  faculties — vision,  intellect,  the  appetites,  etc., 
and  the  final_  objective  end  is  merely  that  which  includes 
the  objects  of  all  the  appetites.  Furthermore  it  is  not 
necessary  to  determine  the  objects  of  all  the  appetites 
but  only  of  the  will :  for  the  will,  in  its  object,  includes 
the  objects  of  the  other  appetites,  it  being  possible  to 
will  any  end  which  is  desirable  in  any  way.  Hence 
the  final  end  will  be  that  object  which  satisfies  the  will : 
and  since  it  is  possible  to  determine  the  object  of  will 
as  of  any  other  capacity,  it  is  possible  to  determine  the 
final  end. 

We  cannot,  therefore,  accept  the  view  which  is  advo- 
cated by  many  recent  evolutionist  philosophers — for 
instance,  by  Green — that  though  we  may  determine  the 
kind  of  action  that  will  promote  our  final  end,  it  is 
nevertheless  not  possible  to  determine  the  end  itself  or 
to  say  in  what  it  consists.  We  may  not,  indeed,  know 
everything  about  our  final  end — its  constitution  and  the 
place  and  time  of  its  attainment — just  as,  whilst  knowing 
that  the  object  of  hunger  is  food,  we  need  not  know  the 
chemical  constitution  of  food.  But  there  is  nothing  to 
prevent  our  being  able  to  determine  the  function  and 
object  that  constitutes  our  final  end,  in  so  far,  at  least, 
as  that  end  is  necessary  to  the  full  and  adequate  satis- 
faction of  our  highest  natural  appetite  ;  for  the  highest 
natural  appetite  will  consist  of  a  psychical  tendency  to 
some  end,  and  it  is  not  possible  that  Psychology  should 
not  be  able  to  determine  that  encj. 


56  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(2)  What  is  the  final  objective  end  ? 

This  end  we  now  go  on  to  determine ;  and  first, 
negatively — that  is,  we  must  see  in  what  our  final  end 
does  not  consist  ;  second,  positively,  we  shall  inquire 
in  what  it  consists. 

(l.)    OF    THE     THINGS     THAT     DO     NOT     CONSTITUTE     THE 
FINAL  END. 

The  final  end  of  man  does  not  consist  {a)  in  certain 
finite  external  objects  with  which  some  have  identified 
it — e.g.,  money,  honour  or  power  ;  (b)  nor  in  any  good 
of  the  body,  like  bodily  health  or  strength  ;  (c)  nor  in 
pleasure  ;  {d)  nor  in  any  good  of  the  soul,  like  the  soul 
itself,  or  virtue,  or  knowledge,  or  culture  ;  {e)  nor  in  the 
adapting  of  our  inner  powers  to  outer  environment. 

{a)  It  does  not  consist  in  riches,  for  riches  are  nothing 
more  than  a  means  to  other  things,  like  knowledge,  food 
and  pleasure  ;  nor  in  honour  and  glory,  which  consist 
rather  in  a  mental  act  elicited  by  other  persons  than  an 
act  of  ourselves  ;  and,  besides,  presuppose  in  us  that 
very  excellence  and  attainment  which  is  our  last  end  ; 
nor  in  worldly  power,  since  excellence  is  the  doing  of 
good  things  or  the  attainment  of  good  ends,  not  the 
power  to  do  so,  just  as  evil  is  the  doing  of  evil  things, 
not  the  power  to  do  so. 

St.  Thomas  Aquinas  sums  up  all  such  "  goods  "  in  the 
following  general  argument  : — The  final  end  must  fill  up 
the  capacity  of  the  will  for  desiring  [quietare  appetititm). 
Now,  that  which  fully  satisfies  the  will  must,  first  of  all, 
exclude  from  the  will  the  possibility  of  unhappiness, 
whereas  finite  external  goods  can  be  possessed  along 
with  unhappiness  ;  secondly,  the  final  end  must  give  us 
all  that  we  desire,  whereas  finite  external  goods  still 
leave  much  to  be  desired — v.g.,  knowledge  ;  third,  it 
must  not  of  itself  make  us  unhappy,  whereas  money  and 
honour  are  often  themselves  the  root  of  misery  ;  finally, 
our  iiighcst  natural  end  nuist  be  a  good  to  which  we 
tend   necessarily.     But    external    finite   goods   arc    not 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  57 

necessarily  desired.  They  often  come  to  us  without 
our  desiring  them,  and  accidental!}',  and  they  are  then 
called,  not  natural  acquirements,  but  goods  of  fortune. 
Our  final  end,  therefore,  does  not  consist  in  such  goods 
as  riches  or  honour  or  power. 

(b)  The  highest  good  cannot  he  any  good  of  the  body, 
because  the  body  and  its  excellences  are  only  part  of 
the  human  good,  and  the  lesser  part.  Besides,  man's 
highest  good  must  certainly  be  a  something  in  which 
he  surpasses  the  lower  animals,  whereas  there  is  no 
bodily  good  in  which  he  is  not  surpassed  by  man}^ 
animals.  The  elephant,  as  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  remarks, 
surpasses  him  in  length  of  life,  the  lion  in  strength,  the 
stag  in  swiftness.  Spencer,  speaking  of  those  very  same 
cases  given  by  St.  Thomas,  maintains  that,  even  though 
the  lower  animals  live  longer  than  man,  our  end  may 
still  consist  in  the  maximum  of  vitality,  because,  though 
the  lower  animals  surpass  him  in  length  of  life,  they  do 
not  surpass  him  in  length  and  breadth  combined — i.e., 
in  the  amount  of  living  activity  that  the}-  put  forth. 
With  this  contention  of  Spencer  we  cannot  agree.  Man's 
acts  are,  indeed,  more  varied  than  those  of  the  lion,  but 
man  does  not  necessarily  exercise  more  living  activity 
than  the  lion,  and  experience  makes  it  clear  that  the 
total  output  of  life  is  greater  in  the  case  of  many  of  the 
lower  animals  than  in  the  case  of  man.  This  point, 
however,  will  be  discussed  more  fully  later.* 

{c)  The  final  natural  end  cannot  consist  in  pleasure.  A 
full  examination  of  this  question  is  reserved  for  our 
chapter  on  Hedonism.  We  treat  it  here,  following  St. 
Thomas  Aquinas,  simply  for  the  sake  of  completeness, 
and  we  shall,  therefore,  limit  ourselves  to  one  point  of 
ouY  proof — that,  namely,  which  is  derived  from  the 
analysis  of  "  natural  desire,"  by  which  we  mean  those 
desires  which  spring  from  nature  itself,  and  are  not  the 
result  of  previous  deliberation  and  choice.  Before, 
however,  giving  our  proof  we  may  be  allowed  to  repeat 

•  Chapter  on  Evolution. 


58  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  sense  of  the  question  which  we  are  here  discussing. 
Our  question  is  whether  pleasure  is  man's  final  objective 
end — that  is,  whether  pleasure  is  that  which  is  wished 
in  every  desire,  whether  it  is  that  on  account  of  which 
we  wish  for  all  other  things,  whether  it  is  that  whose 
attainment  and  possession  will  thoroughly  satisf}^  us.* 
We  do  not  at  present  ask  whether  pleasure  is  our  sub- 
jective last  end — that  is,  whether  the  final  act  or  state 
by  which  we  attain  and  possess  our  final  objective  end, 
and  which,  therefore,  constitutes  the  final  inner  satis- 
faction of  the  will,  is  pleasure.  This  question  we  shall 
discuss  later,  when  it  will  be  shown  that  pleasure  is  not 
even  our  final  subjective  end.  Our  present  question  is — 
Is  pleasure  that  which  the  human  will  ultimately  aims 
at  or  desires  in  all  its  acts. 

Our  proof  that  pleasure  is  not  our  final  objective  end 
is  as  follows  : — 

That  object  will  constitute  our  final  natural  end  which 
is  fundamental  and  primary  in  such  desires  as  nature 
herself  produces  in  the  will.  Now,  pleasure  is  not  the 
fundamental  and  primary  object  to  which  nature  directs 
our  wills,  for  in  the  order  of  nature  desire  for  an  object 
outside  the  will  is  prior  to  all  other  desires,  even  the  desire 
for  pleasure.  Hence  pleasure  is  not  our  final  objective 
end. 

The  principle  here  given — that  the  primary  objective 
end  of  the  natural  appetites  is  external  to  the  appetite 
^nd  not  within  it — is  a  fundamental  and  a  highly  im- 
portant proposition. t  We  know  that  we  ourselves  in 
jour  deliberate  or  artificial  acts,  as  opposed  to  those 
'movements  which  nature  itself  sets  up  in  our  appetites, 

•  It  is  evident  that  by  "  objective  "  here  we  do  not  mean  "  ex- 
ternal."    It  is  too  plain  that  pleasure  could  not  be  external. 

f  This  doctrine  was  expressly  taught  by  many  of  the  school- 
men besides  St.  Thomas  Aquinas.  In  his  account  of  Peter  Lombard's 
philosophic  teaching  ("  Die  I'hilosophie  des  IVtrus  I.ombardus  und 
ihrc  Stcllun^  im  Z\v(i!flen  Jliarlnindcrt  "),  Dr.  K.sp(•nl)er^,'c•r  writes  : — 
"  Indes  nicht  die  Lust  als  solclu;  ist  das  letzte  Ende  unseris  Handclns, 
sondcrn  cin  Etwas,  cine  SAche  die  uns  Lust  gewiihrt."  The  sam 
doctrine  i«  taught  by  many  niodern  philosophers  who  are  not  of  th<' 
Khoiastic  tradition.    See  later  p.  283. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  59 

can  wish  for  these  ends  in  any  order.  We  can  wish 
the  external  object  without  thinking  of  our  inner  state 
of  pleasure,  as  when  a  man  loves  conversation  with 
friends  ;  or  we  can  wish  the  state  of  pleasure  first  and 
then  look  about  for  an  object  which  will  make  us  happy. 
In  other  words,  whatever  be  the  order  of  nature's  desire, 
we  can  by  reflection  return  upon  it  and  take  its  ends  in 
any  order  whatsoever,  either  external  object  first  or 
pleasure  first.  With  these  artificial  acts  we  have  for 
the  moment  nothing  to  do,  but  are  interested  only  in 
what  we  have  called  the  ?iahiral  desire  of  the  will.  The 
question  is — On  which  of  these  two  ends  has  nature  fixed 
our  wills  primarily — the  inner  state  of  pleasure  or  the 
external  object  ?     We  answer — On  the  external  object. 

Our  proof  is  as  follows : — Will  and  the  appetites 
follow  cognition.  We  desire  that  which  we  know  ;  and 
we  naturally  desire  first  what  we  naturally  know  first. 
But  the  primary  *  and  natural  objects  of  our  under- 
standing are  external  things,  not  states  of  the  under- 
standing itself,  of  consciousness,  or  of  will.  All  know- 
ledge begins  in  the  external  senses,  and  the  external 
senses  know  only  external  objects.  For  example,  the 
sense  of  sight  is  not  immediately  conscious  of  any  par- 
ticular state  of  itself,  but  only  of  the  material  world 
beyond  itself.  And  as  intellect  follows  the  senses  its 
primary  object  must  be  something  in  these  external 
objects  and  not  a  state  of  consciousness  or  of  will.  All 
knowledge  begins,  therefore,  with  the  external  world, 
and  only  later,  and  by  a  reflex  act,  do  we  come  to  appre- 
hend our  own  subjective  states.  A  baby,  as  certain 
modern  philosophers  point  out,  looking  upon  the  lighted 
candle,  lives  wholly  otd  of  itself, -\  that  is,  it  has  not  yet 

♦  Primary,  both  chronologically  and  rationally.  The  natural 
foundations  are  deepest  and  first,  even  chronologically. 

t  To  the  same  effect  we  have  Prof.  Taylor's  argument  in  "  Problems 
of  Conduct "  (page  77),  that  the  object  of  knowledge  is  not  the  "  self  " 
or  subject,  neither  is  it  the  object  in  relation  to  a  self.  In  knowledge, 
he  tells  us,  we  often  are  aware  of  nothing  but  the  external  object,  and 
so  far  as  knowledge  is  concerned  we  are  at  that  moment  nothing  more 
than  these  external  objects.     "  At  these  times,"  he  writes,  "  a  man 


6o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

learned  to  reflect  upon  itself.  Its  knowledge  of  self 
comes  later.  And  as  the  knowledge  of  self  is  only 
secondary  in  the  order  of  nature,  so  also  is  the  appetition 
of  self  or  of  any  state  of  self  only  secondary  in  the  order 
of  nature.  The  will,  therefore,  is  fixed  upon  the  external 
object  primarily,  and  it  is  because  the  will  is  fixed  upon 
the  external  object  that  it  desires  the  state  of  pleasure 
or  delight  which  follows  on  the  attainment  of  its 
object. 

On  account  of  its  importance  we  will  develop  this 
point  a  little  further. 

No  natural  conscious  impulse  or  craving  is  ever 
primarily  a  movement  to  a  mere  state  of  that  in  which 
the  impulse  is  excited.  That  in  which  nature  excites 
conscious  craving  is  moved  by  nature  primarily  to  an 
outer  object  and  only  secondarily  and  consequently  to 
the  state  of  itself  which  that  object  is  to  induce — 
namely,  pleasure. 

Thus  the  first  desire  of  an  animal  or  of  children  (the 
first  tendency,  for  instance,  of  hunger  or  of  thirst) — a 
desire  which  is  undoubtedly  due  to  the  working  of  the  inner 
nature  of  the  appetite,  and  represents  its  pure  natural 
operation — is  always  a  desire  for  some  object  other  than 
pleasure.  For  the  desire  of  pleasure  can  only  arise 
when    experience    has    made    known    the    existence    of 

loses  all  consciousness  of  liinisclf  as  in  any  way  being  anything  more 
than  the  succession  of  liglits  and  scents  and  sounds,  or  of  these  as  in 
any  way  objects  other  than  himself."  And  on  page  78 — "  The 
subject -object  form  of  consciousness  "  (that  is,  the  form  in  which 
we  know  an  object  merely  as  related  to  ourselves),  "  is  not  a  primary 
and  inseparable  form  of  human  experience.  There  is  the  more 
primitive  state  whicli  was  probably  our  condition  in  our  ante-natal 
days,  as  well  as  in  our  earliest  infancy..-  At  this  earliest  stage  of  ex- 
perience wc  have  as  yet  neither  '  subjects  '  nor  '  objects  '  (in  the 
sense  of  object  as  related  to  us),  but  impersonal  psychical  contents" 
(that  is,  we  luivc  only  contents  of  which  the  self  forms  no  part). 

This  view  of  Taylor's  is,  of  course,  ;in  exaggeration.  Tiie  knowing 
8u!)jcct  never  hrcomci  tiie  object  which  it  knows.  His  view,  however, 
cniphaMses  a  truth  which  relativists  olten  forget,  that  in  common 
experience  tlie  content  of  cnir  consciousness  often  ineludes  no  reference 
to  ourselves,  and  lliat,  as  Kd,  von  llartinann  says,  the  more  primitive 
and  naive  our  consciousness  becomes  the  more  objective  it  becomes, 
and  the  less  it  tells  us  of  the  sell  or  ol  its  states.     See  p.  282. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  6i 

pleasure,  and,  since  pleasure  arises  first  on  the  attain- 
ment of  some  end  of  desire,  it  follows  that  pleasure 
becomes  known  to  us  or  is  first  experienced  on  the  ful- 
filment of  or  in  the  obtaining  of  the  object  of  one's  first 
desire.  Hence  pleasure  is  not  itself  the  object  of  the 
first  desire  of  any  appetite. 

Again,   nature   does  not   drive  the  bird   in  building- 
time  to  remove  from  the  appetite  a  certain  inner  state 
of  uneasiness  and  to  substitute  for  it  another  state  of 
pleasure  or  rest.     Nature  directs  the  bird  simply  and 
directly  to  build  a  nest,  and  as  a  result  of  the  pursuit 
and   the    attainment   of   that    object    the  inner  feeling 
of  unrest  is  removed  and  pleasure  ensues.     It  is  so  also 
even    in    the    case    of    those    conscious,    particular,    yet 
natural  desires  which  arise  in  a  man  independently  of 
free  will.     The  man  who  loves  money  or  conversation 
with  friends  thinks  primarily,   not   of  any  inner  state 
which    is    induced   by   their    possession,    but    of    these 
objects    themselves,    and    in    the    attainment    of    these 
objects  he  is  at  rest.     We  can,  indeed,  if  we  care,  wish 
directly  for  happiness  or  contentment,  and  we  often  do 
so  ;   for,  as  rational  beings  we  are  gifted  with  this  power 
of  reflection,  and  through  it,  as  already  said,  we  can 
take  all  the  steps  of  nature  singly,  and  in  any  order  we 
like,  even  in  an  order  opposed  to  that  of  nature.     In 
other  words,  we  may,  by  a  positive  act,  and  by  reflec- 
tion, first  fix  our  attention  on  our  own  inner  pleasure, 
and  then  seek  out  a  means  of  promoting  it.     But  with 
all  natural  craving  this  order  is  reversed.     The  love  of 
friends,  the  love  of  man  for  a  woman,  the  love  of  boat- 
ing,  of  hunting,   are  all   primarily  movements   of  the 
appetite   to   outer   objects — i.e.,   to   things   outside   the 
will,  and  to  pleasure  secondarily. 

We  may,  therefore,  state  our  argument  as  follows  : — 
The  fundamental  and  primary  natural  object  of  our 
will,  as  of  any  other  faculty,  represents  its  final  natural 
end.  But  pleasure  is  not  the  fundamental  and  primary 
natural  object  of  our  will,  but  some  other  object  outside 


62  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

our  wills.  Therefore,  pleasure  is  not  our  linal  natural 
end. 

{d)  Our  final  objective  *  end  cannot  be  something  within 
the  soul. 

Examples  of  things  within  the  soul  are  the  substance 
of  the  soul  itself,  holiness,  virtue,  knowledge,  culture. 
We  shall  take  these  in  order. 

First,  the  final  end  is  not  the  soul  itself  or  what  is 
called  the  self,  or  self-realisation,]  because  our  faculties 
and  appetites  as  has  been  already  shown,  tend  primarily 
to  things  outside  of  us,  and  hence  the  final  natural  end, 
which  is  in  the  order  of  ends  primary  and  fundamental, 
cannot  be  within  us.  St.  Thomas  makes  use  of  the 
apt  analogy  that  the  captain  of  a  ship  never  dreams  that 
the  end  of  the  ship  is  its  own  realisation,  continued 
existence,  or  development,  or  that  it  is  his  end  as  captain 
to  keep  the  ship  in  being,  to  realise  it,  or  to  develop  it. 
The  end  of  the  ship  is  the  attainment  of  that  definite 
object  which  it  is  fitted  to  achieve — the  carrying  of  its 
freight  safely  to  port,  and  the  end  or  aim  of  the  captain 
is  to  guide  his  ship  to  harbour.  J  So  also  man — his  own 
guide  and  the  shaper  of  his  own  destiny — cannot  have 
it  as  his  end  to  keep  himself  in  being  or  to  develop  him- 
self, but  to  attain  those  ends  which  he  is  naturally  fitted 
to  attain,  to  do  such  acts — that  is,  to  take  such  means — 
as  will  secure  him  the  final  object  of  the  whole  unity 
of  the  appetites  within  him.§     And  since  these,  as  we 

•  Our  mcaniriR  here  is,  as  has  been  already  explained,  that  that  to 
which  the  will  is  finally  directed  is  not  something  within  the  soul.  See 
note,  page  53. 

t  liradley,  "  Ethical  Studies,"  page  59.  For  further  treatment  of 
this  (jucstion  of  self-realisation,  see  Chapter  on  Evolution,  page  ^6i. 

X  "  Summa  Theol.,"  I".,  1I•^,  Q.  II.,  Art.  5. 

§  In  this  argument  from  analogy,  drawn  from  the  aim  or  purpose 
of  the  captain  in  respect  to  his  ship,  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  evidently 
reasons  on  the  assumption  which  he  has  already  proved,  that  as  the 
function  of  a  ship  is  movement,  and  movement  is  always  directed  to 
an  external  end,  so  the  human  functions  from  which  we  determine 
the  final  end — namely,  our  cognitive  appetites — have  their  jirimary 
natural  object  without  and  not  within  themselves.  In  determining 
the  end  of  anything  we  have  to  examine  its  faculties  or  potentialities. 
And  as  the  faculties  of  man  (all  except  the  very  lowest)  relate  to  outer 
objects  primarily,  so  the  end  is  without  us. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  63 

have  seen,  all  tend  naturally  and  primarily  to  an  object 
outside  of  themselves  and  outside  of  man,  so  also  the 
final  natural  end  must  lie  in  an  external  object. 
Naturally,  of  course,  the  attainment  of  any  end  involves 
development  of  the  self,  its  sustainment,  and  even  its 
increase.  But  such  development  supposes  the  end  at- 
tained, and  consequently  our  own  development  or 
realisation  is  not  our  final  end.  As  St.  Thomas  puts 
it,  the  "  adeptio  ipsa  "  (attainment)  and  the  "  usus," 
or  enjoyment  of  the  end,  belong  to  the  soul,  but  the 
end  itself  which  is  sought  is  quite  distinct  from  the  soul 
or  the  self. 

Before  passing  on  to  consider  the  other  goods  of  the 
soul,  we  shall  here  consider  two  important  objections  : — 

(a)  Evolutionists  find  some  difficulty  in  the  doctrine 
that  the  final  end  of  a  thing  can  be  something  external 
to  the  thing  itself.  Growth  or  evolution,  they  tell  us 
(and  progress  to  our  final  natural  end  they  necessarily 
regard  as  in  some  sort  an  evolution),  is  a  movement 
from  potentiality  to  act,  from  a  lower  condition  of  the 
growing  self  to  a  higher  and  better  condition  of  the  self. 
Our  final  objective  end,  therefore — the  end  to  which  our 
movements  are  all  finally  directed — will  be  that  highest 
and  most  evolved  condition  of  the  self  to  which  our 
faculties  and  our  potentiality  extend. 

Reply — Before  considering  this  objection  we  may  be 
allowed  to  repeat  what  we  have  already  explained,  that 
in  the  scholastic  doctrine  it  is  the  objective  end  alone — 
the  "  res  ipsa  quae  appetitur  ut  finis  " — which  is  re- 
garded as  external — as  "  aliquid  extra  animam."  The 
subjective  final  end,  the  act  whereby  we  attain  and 
possess  the  res  appetita,  or,  to  use  St.  Thomas's  expres- 
sion, the  "  usus  "  or  "  adeptio  "  of  the  objective  end,  is 
in  the  scholastic  philosophy  expressly  described  as  an 
inner  act  of  the  soul.  Progress  is  so  manifestly  an  act, 
habit,  or  condition  of  the  evolving  subject  itself  that  it 
would  be  absurd  to  think  that  the  scholastics  made  no 
provision  for  a  subjective  final  end,  and,  as  we  say,  they 


64  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

expressly  describe  the  attainment  of  the  final  end  as  a 
soul-act,  as  "  aliquid  animae."  But  that  thing  which 
we  finally  tend  to  attain,  and  which  serves  as  the  first 
principle  of  all  hunian  action,  is,  as  we  have  seen,  in 
scholastic  philosophy,  external.  Again,  St.  Thomas  even 
qualifies  his  assertion  of  an  external  objective  end  when 
he  writes  that  the  objective  end  is  not  wholly  extrinsic 
to,  or  divided  from,  the  human  act.  "  The  end,"  he 
says,  "is  not  altogether  extrinsic  to  the  act  because  it 
is  related  to  the  act  as  principle  or  as  term."  *  Thus 
the  objective  final  end,  though  external,  is  still  to  be 
regarded  as  standing  in  intimate  relation  to  the  agent, 
and  even  as  completing  his  act,  since  a  cognitive  and 
appetitive  act  can  only  be  completed  by  the  object 
known  or  desired. 

These  explanations  being  given,  we  may  proceed  to 
answer  the  evolutionist's  difficulty.  The  theory  of  the 
evolutionists  that  progress  towards  one's  natural  end 
must  necessarily  consist  in  movement  towards  a  higher 
or  more  complex  condition  of  the  self,  is  founded  on  a 
mistaken  analogy  between  human  progress  and  mere 
vegetative  growth  or  the  growth  of  plants.  It  is  true 
that  the  plant  in  growing  tends  directly  to  the  attain- 
ment of  some  inner  state  or  condition  of  the  plant  itself,  f 
Vegetative  powers,  as  St.  Thomas  writes,  concern  the 
corpus  proprium,  the  body  of  the  individual  ("  corpus 
animce  unitum  "),  and,  therefore,  progress  in  the  case  of 
these  faculties  means  movement  to  the  attainment  of 
some  higher  condition  of  the  growing  subject,  such  as 
greater  quantity  in  the  substance  or  greater  differentia- 
tion of  the  parts. 

But  the  cognitive  faculties,  whether  sensuous  or 
intellectual,  extend  to  other  objects  besides  the  self, 
and,  as  we  have  seen,  their  first  and  natural  act  con- 
cerns  exclusively   external   objects.    Natural   progress, 

•  "  Summa  Thcol.,"  I.,  II.,  Q.  I.,  Art.  3. 

f  This  is  true  of  at  least  two  of  IIh;  vegetative  faculties,  the 
nutritiva  and  auf<mrntativa  ("  Halxiiit,"  as  St.  Thomas  writes,  "  suum 
efiectum  in  co  in  quu  uunt  ").     It  is  aot  altogether  true  of  the  general iva 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  65 

therefore,  in  the  case  of  these  faculties  means  move- 
ment, not  to  a  higher  condition  of  the  self,  but  to  a 
fuller  and  fuller  attainment  of  objects  beyond  the  self. 
But  the  differentiating  mark  of  human  progress  is  given 
not  in  what  is  lowest  in  man  but  in  what  is  highest,  not 
in  the  vegetative  faculties  but  in  the  intellectual ;  and, 
therefore,  the  end  of  human  progress  must  be  the  at- 
tainment through  knowledge  of  some  object  beyond  the 
self,  some  object,  as  we  saw  before,  which  will  fully 
exhaust  the  capacity  of  our  cognitive  powers  and  bring 
the  appetites  to  rest.  Man's  final  objective  end,  there- 
fore— the  "  res  quae  appetitur  ut  finis  " — cannot  be  a 
condition  of  the  thinking  self,  since  our  cognitive 
faculties  reach  outside  the  self. 

But  is  not  the  self  the  end  even  of  cognition,  evolu- 
tionists may  enquire  ;  and  is  it  not  merely  as  affording 
us  increased  power  of  mind,  more  general  information, 
a  more  refined  culture,  ■  or  some  other  inner  condition 
of  the  soul  that  cognition  is  desirable  ?  and,  therefore, 
is  not  our  objective  end  (the  res  quce  appetitur)  an  inner 
state  rather  than  any  outer  object  ? 

Our  reply  is — Knowledge  means  either  the  inner 
power  and  habit  or  the  act  of  knowledge.  But  the  end 
of  thinking  cannot  be  the  inner  power  to  know  nor  the 
inner  habit  of  knowledge  (that  is,  knowledge  possessed 
but  not  actually  in  exercise).  Powers  and  habits  of 
soul  are  of  value  only  in  so  far  as  they  lead  on  to  acts. 
The  power  to  walk,  to  sing,  to  eat  is  useless  if  it  does  not 
lead  on  to  operation  ;  and  even  habitual  knowledge,  or 
knowledge  which  is  not  actually  in  exgrcise,  is  valuable 
only  in  so  far  as  it  may  at  some  future  time  be  exercised. 
The  inner  power  of  knowledge,  therefore,  or  habitual 
knowledge  cannot  be  the  end.  There  remains  the 
act. 

Now,  what,  we  ask,  is  the  end  of  the  act  of  knowing  ? 

In  other  words,  to  what  is  the  mind  directed  when  it 

knows  ?     Plainly    to    its    object.     It   is   the    object   that 

interests  the  mind  in  knowledge,  not  its  own  act.     It  is  of 

Vol.  1—5 


66  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  object  that  it  thinks.  The  object,  therefore,  and 
not  the  act  of  knowledge  will  be  our  final  objective  end 
— ^the  final  res  appetita.  But  our  final  end  is  to  be 
attained  through  knowledge.*  And  since,  as  we  have 
said,  external  things  are,  as  objects  of  cognition,  more 
fundamental  in  the  order  of  nature  than  any  internal 
state,  it  follows  that  our  final  natural  objective  end 
will  be  external. 

(/3)  Another  objection  which  has  been  practically  met 
already,  but  to  which  we  may  here  give  brief  but  formal 
mention,  is  that  in  desire  we  move,  not  strictly  speaking 
to  an  object,  but  rather  to  the  attainment  or  possession 
of  an  object,  and  the  possession  of  an  object  is  sub- 
jective, f 

We  reply  that  the  possession  or  attainment  of  a  thing 
is  our  subjective  end,  but  the  thing  attained  is  our  ob- 
jective end,  and  the  latter  is  prior  as  cause  of  our  move- 
ment. But  to  argue  that  because  in  desire  we  move  to 
possess  an  end,  we  therefore  move  to  a  subjective  state 
only,  would  be  illogical.  A  stone  in  falling  towards  the 
earth  moves  like  the  will  to  the  attainment  of  an  end, 
yet  no  one  would  say  that  its  end  was  a  subjective 
state.  The  end  or  objective  of  the  stone  is  the  point 
to  which  it  moves.  So  also  the  objective  end  of  the 
will,  the  thing  which  it  desires  to  attain,  may  be  beyond 
the  will.  But  the  attainment  of  that  object  is  our  sub- 
jective end.  We  now  go  on  to  consider  the  other  goods 
of  the  soul. 

Secondly,  the  end  of  man  is  neither  holiness,  nor  virtne, 
nor  "  peace  of  cqnscience  "  %  (Gizycki),  nor  holiness  with 
its  attendant  happiness  (Kant). 

Holiness  signifies  lightness  of  life.  But  Tightness 
means  that  we  are  moving  to  the  end,  and  so,  it  is  not 

•  Or  some  of  the  luKlifst  powers. 

t  Thi.s  is  what  liradlcy  scorns  to  mean  when,  having  denied  that 
pleasure  is  our  end,  he  insists  tliat  "  in  desire  what  we  want,  so  far 
as  wc  want  it,  is  ourselves  in  some  form,  or  is  some  state  of  ourselves  ; 
and  that  our  wanting  anything  else  would  bo  psychologically  im- 
possible "  ("  Ethical  Studies,"  jKige  ()2). 

\  "  Student*'  Manual  oi  Ethical  l^Lilosophy,"  page  84. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  67 

itself  the  end.*  And  virtue  is  only  a  means  to  good  acts, 
and  therefore  cannot  be  the  end.  Neither  is  peace  of 
conscience  our  end,  since  it  is  a  result  of  holiness,  which 
is  a  movement  to  the  end,  and,  hence,  presupposes  the 
end.  And  since  happiness  generally  is  not  the  end, 
the  happiness  of  holiness  is  not  our  end.  All  these  goods 
of  the  soul,  are  either  a  means  to,  or  a  result  of,  or 
identical  with  goodness,  and  since  goodness  means 
movement  to  the  end,  it  follows  that  they  cannot  con- 
stitute our  end. 

Thirdly,  the  final  objective  end  of  man  is  not  knowledge. 

This  thesis  we  have  already  anticipated.  We  give  it 
prominence  here  because  we  are  considering  the  claim 
of  the  various  states  of  soul  to  constitute  our  final  ob- 
jective end,  and  knowledge  is  the  principal  of  these 
states.  The  act  by  which  we  shall  attain  our  final  end 
will,  as  we  shall  show  later,  be  an  act  of  knowledge. 
But  knowledge  is  not  our  final  objective  end — the  final 
res  appetita — for,  as  we  have  seen,  where  the  act  of 
knowledge  is  natural  and  spontaneous,  the  mind  thinks 
not  of  the  act  itself  but  of  its  object ;  and,  therefore,  in 
the  case  of  these  same  natural  and  spontaneous  acts, 
our  wills  are  borne  on  to  desire  the  object  and  not  the 
act.  And  hence  the  res  appetita  is  not  knowledge,  but 
the  object  of  knowledge.  Again,  our  final  objective  end/ 
is  that  which  we  finally  tend  to  possess,  the  word  "  pos- 
sess "  being  used  in  its  broadest  significance.  Now, 
possession  is  of  many  kinds.  We  possess  money  by 
holding  it  in  our  hands  ;  we  possess  friends  by  inter- 
communion with  them.  Knowledge  is  but  a  species  of 
possession,    the    possession    of    that    which    we    know. 

"  Holiness  "  with  Kant  means  the  love  of  law  for  its  own  sake. 
Its  attainment  is  supposed  to  require  an  infinite  time  ;  for  though, 
according  to  Kant,  we  can  and  ought  to  wish  for  law  for  its  own  sake 
as  distinct  from  pleasure,  yet  we  are  always  drawn  by  pleasure  also. 
To  get  rid  of  this  natural  attendant  on  human  action  will  require,  as 
Kant  observes,  an  inlinite  time.  Also,  that  adequate  happiness  may 
I'ollow  upon  holiness,  postulates  an  infinite  power  interested  in  the 
moral  law.  These  are  Kant's  proofs  for  the  immortality  of  the  soul 
and  for  the  existence  of  God. 


68  THE   SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Hence  knowledge,   being  onl}^  possession,  is    not  itself 
that  which  we  finally  aim  at  possessing. 

Besides,  enjoyment  arises  from  the  attainment  of  our 
end.  Now,  though  knowledge  is  a  necessary  condition 
of  enjoyment,  still  the  enjoyment  that  arises  in  know- 
ledge springs  generally  not  from  the  fact  that  we  possess 
this  inner  state  of  knowledge,  a  state  which  generally 
escapes  our  attention  altogether,  but  from  the  object 
itself  which  is  known.  We  enjoy  not  our  knowledge 
of  a  thing,  but  the  thing  itself.  Knowledge,  therefore, 
is  not  the  end.  No  doubt,  we  can  by  a  reflex  act  make 
knowledge  an  object  of  our  attention  and  gain  pleasure 
from  our  consciousness  of  knowledge  possessed.  But, 
except  in  the  case  of  positive  reflection  on  knowledge, 
the  enjoyment  of  knowledge  springs,  not  from  our 
consciousness  of  any  inner  act  of  the  mind,  but  from 
the  object  which  is  known.  Hence  knowledge  is  not 
our  final  objective  end. 

Fourthly,  the  ejtd  is  not  culture. 

As  knowledge,  holiness  and  happiness  are  not  our 
final  objective  end,  so  neither  is  culture  our  end.  It  is 
not  that  which  our  wills  naturally  and  finally  desire. 
First,  the  final  end  of  the  individual  is  not  his  own 
culture,  because  culture  is  an  inner  state,  and  an  inner 
state  cannot  be  our  final  objective  end.  Second, 
culture  is  a  means  merely — a  means  to  the  doing  of 
refined  acts,  and  consequently  it  is  not  our  end.  And 
as  the  culture  of  the  individual  is  not  our  end,  so  neither 
is  our  end  to  be  found  in  the  culture  of  the  race. 
Modem  evolutionists  of  a  certain  school  place  the 
end  of  individuals  in  the  ever-increasing  culture  of  the 
race.  But  as  culture  and  that  which  it  involves,  like 
knowledge,  good-nature,  &c.,  as  states  of  the  individual 
are  not  our  end,  neither  are  they  as  racial  our  end.  To 
adapt  St.  Thomas  Aquinas'  simple  argument.  If  an 
inner  state  is  not  the  proper  end  of  an  individual  ship 
tlicu  the  projier  end  of  a  company  of  ships  cannot  be 
an  inner  state.     So  we  do  not  regard  the  final  objective 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  69 

end  as  a  state  of  the  individual  man  or  of  the  race  of 
men.     The  culture,  therefore,  of  the  race  is  not  our  end. 

All  these  goods  of  the  soul,  the  substance  of  the  soul, 
its  faculties,  its  habits  like  holiness,  its  acts  like  know- 
ledge, St.  Thomas  excludes  by  one  all-embracing  argu 
ment — they  are  all  ordained  to  something  beyond  them 
selves.     The  substance,  faculties,  and  habits  of  the  soul 
are  ordained  to  acts — they  are  means  to  acts,  and,  there 
fore,  cannot  be  the  final  end.      And  acts  of  the  soul  are 
themselves  ordained  to  something  beyond  themselves — | 
namely,  to  their  objects.     The  acts  of  the  human  soul 
are   means   to    the   possession   of   objects.     These   acts, 
therefore,   cannot   be  the  final  objective   end  of  man 
They  are  not  that  which  the  will  ultimately  seeks,  and 
the  possession  of  which  will  give  it  rest. 

{e)  The  final  objective  end  is  not  adjustment  of  inner 
powers  to  outer  environment  (evolutionists). 

As  the  final  end  cannot  consist  in  any  good  of  body 
or  soul,  so  neither  can  it  consist  in  any  internal  good  in 
relation  to  our  surroundings  or  in  the  adjustment  of 
inner  powers  to  outer  environment^  Adjustment  or 
equilibrium  of  our  powers  in  reference  to  environment 
could  no  more  constitute  our  final  end  than  the  har- 
monious relations  of  ships  making  for  port  could  be  the 
end  of  each.  Adjustment  to  conditions  of  environment 
is,  no  doubt,  a  necessary  condition  of  progress  towards 
our  end,  for  all  organisms,  individual  and  social,  pre- 
suppose the  harmonious  working  of  part  with  part  and 
also  harmony  with  their  surroundings.  But  just  as  the 
adjustment  of  one  organ  to  another  within  the  body  is 
not  the  end  of  either  organ  or  of  the  two  together,  so 
the  end  of  man  cannot  be  his  adjustment  to  the  social 
environment. 

(11.)    THE    TRUE      FINAL     OBJECTIVE     END      OF     MAN.        IT 
CONSISTS  OF  THE  INFINITE  GOOD 

Just  as  the  final  end  of  a  tree  must  be  the  realisation 
of  its  full  capacities  as  a  tree,  so  our  final  end  as  men 


70  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

must  fiU  up  the  capacity  of  the  will  for  desiring.  The 
conscious  natural  appetites  hold  the  same  place  in  the 
human  constitution  that  the  unconscious  appetites  hold 
in  the  vegetative  world.  But  the  final  end  of  a  plant 
will  be  that  which  exhausts  fully  its  appetitive  capacity. 
Therefore,  the  final  end  in  the  case  of  a  man  will  likewise 
be  that  which  fully  exhausts  his  appetites.  "  Nothing," 
says  Aristotle,  "  can  be  our  final  end  which  still  leaves 
something  to  be  desired."'  Let  us  see,  therefore,  what 
is  that  object,  the  possession  of  which  alone  leaves 
nothing  to  be  desired. 

As  the  object  of  intellect  is  the  true,  or  the  true-in- 
general,  or  being-in-general,  so  the  natural  object  of  the 
jwill  is  not  this  or  that  particular  good,  but  "  good,"  or 
the  good-in-general.  But  nothing  short  of  an  "  infinite  " 
can  fully  exhaust  the  possibilities  of  that  object  and  of 
the  capacity  of  the  will  of  which  it  is  the  end.  There- 
fore, the  infinite  is  the  final  objective  end  of  the  will. 
No  other  object  can  finally  satisfy  the  will.*  No  matter 
what  finite  object  we  may  select,  there  will  be  always 
objects  realising  different  grades  or  kinds  of  good  outside 
of  that  finite  object,  every  one  of  which  kinds  of  good  is 
contained  in  the  universal  object  "  good,"  and  every 
one  of  which,  therefore,  comes  within  the  capacity  of 
the  will.  Hence  a  finite  object,  or  any  number  of  them, 
must  always  leave  some  parts  of  the  capacity  of  the 
will  unsatisfied.!  They  are,  therefore,  not  our  final 
end.  Nay,  even  the  combined  sum  of  all  finite  objects 
cannot  be  our  end.  First,  because  a  sum  of  finites  is 
itself  finite ;  secondly,  because,  even  were  it  infinite 
as  regards  number,  still,  in  the  sum  of  finites  many 
individuals  must  be  imperfect,  because  in  any  group 
of  jjbjccts  one  thing  must  limit  another.     Thus,  there 

•  "  And  thus  I  know  this  earth  is  not  my  sphere 
For  I  cannot  so  narrow  mc  but  that 
I  Htill  exceed  it." — (Urowning— i'a«/j«<r). 
f  I'erhaps   this  is  what   Schoj)enhauer  nit-aiis   wl  en,   speaking  of 
our  condition  lir-re  below,  lie  refiTS  to  man  as  "  a  burlesque  of  what 
he  should  1m;  "  ("  Stucbes  in  I'rssimism,"  ]>agi'  24). 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUIVIAN  ACTION  71 

cannot  be  in  the  world  an  infinite  amount  of  iron,  since 
some  of  the  places  that  jcoiild  be  occupied  by  iron  are 
occupied  by  sand  or  water.  In  the  same  way,  even  a 
combined  sum  of  finites  is  imperfect,  and  therefore,  if- 
cannot  fully  satisfy  the  will ;  thirdly,  because  the  will 
could  not  enjoy  all  in  a  single  act,  whereas  the  per- 
fection of  blessedness  consists  in  the  simultaneous  having 
of  all  that  we  desire  ;  fourthly,  because  each  of  these 
finites  has  an  end  beyond  itself.  In  nothing  short  of 
the  infinite,  therefore,  shall  the  will  be  satisfied,  and. 
therefore,  nothing  short  of  the  infinite  can  be  our  final 
end.*  Whether  that  object  be  real  or  only  a  thing  con- 
ceived by  the  intellect  we  shall  presently  enquire.  Our 
present  contention  is  that,  real  or  imaginary,  the  infinite 
good  is  the  natural  end  of  the  appetite  of  will,  for  only 
in  that  end  can  the  will  be  set  at  rest. 

The  objective  end  of  man — a  real  object. 

We  have  now  seen  that  the  natural  object  of  the  will — 
the  object  which  alone  can  satisfy  the  natural  craving 
of  the  will— is  the  infinite  good.  We  stated  also  that 
we  had  yet  to  decide  the  question  whether  that  infinite 
good  was  only  a  thing  imagined  or  conceived,  or  whether 
it  was  a  real  object,  really  distinct  from  and  outside  our 
intellects,  as  the  objects  that  we  see  and  feel  are  outside 
the  sense  of  sight  and  touch.  This  question  we  now 
proceed  to  answer.  But  before  doing  so  it  may  be  well 
to  remark  that  there  is  another  science  quite  distinct 

*  St.  Thomas'  succinct  presentation  of  the  above  argument  leaves 
him  open  to  some  misconception.  He  argues  :  "  Objectum  volun- 
tatis quae  est  appetitus  humanus  est  universale  bonum,  ^icut  objectum 
intellcctus  est  universale  verum  ;  ex  quo  patet  quod  nihil  potest 
quietare  voluntalem  hominis  nisi  bonum  universale,  quod  non  rn- 
venitiir  in  aliquo  creato  sed  solum  in  Deo  "  ("  Summa  Theol.,"  I., 
II*.,  II.,  Art.  8.).  It  will  be  understood,  however,  that  just  as  the 
object  of  the  intellect  is  not  the  infinite  but  the  true-in-general,  so 
honiim  universale  as  object  of  appetite  is  really  not  bonum  universale 
in  sense  of  all  goods  or  the  infinite,  but  bonum  (or  bonum-in-universali). 
However,  what  we  have  said  in  the  text  holds  true- — the  only  object 
that  can  satisfy  such  a  desire  of  the  will  is  the  infinite  good.  For 
fuller  treatment  of  the  argument,  see  Cajetan's  Commentary. 


72  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

from  Ethics— namely,  Natural  Theology — whose  pro- 
vince is  to  prove  the  reality  of  the  infinite  good,  and 
which  puts  the  existence  of  the  infinite  good  beyond  all 
doubt.  We  are  here  merely  stating  one  argument,  an 
argument  that  arises  naturally  from  the  consideration 
of  the  human  act  which  is  the  subject  of  Ethics,  and  we 
use  it  without  prejudice  to  the  splendid  arguments  of 
Natural  Theology.  To  these  arguments  the  present  one 
is  simply  offered  as  a  useful  and  interesting  addition. 

We  go  on,  therefore,  to  show  that  the  infinite  good 
is^  real—i.e.,  that  it  is  not  an  abstraction  or  something 
merely  conceived  by  the  mind.  And  we  prove  this  pro- 
position by  means  of  a  principle  which  is  certain  from 
Metaphysics,  but  which  we  hope  also  to  elucidate  and 
establish  here — the  principle,  namely,  that  the  natural 
end  of  a  real  and  natural  thing  must  itself  be  real ;  in 
other  words,  that  nature  docs  not  act  in  vain*  This  is 
an  old  axiom  of  the  Aristotelian  and  mediaeval  philo- 
sophy which  modern  science  has  confirmed  and  illus- 
trated in  a  thousand  ways.  Thus,  to  take  one  or  two 
examples,  if  it  be  certain  that  the  natural  end  of  the 
heart  is  to  send  blood  through  the  body,  then,  since  the 
heart  is  real,  blood  must  also  be  a  reality.  And  if  food 
is  the  natural  end  of  the  natural  appetite  of  hunger, 
then  food  is  real.  And  when  we  say  that  food  and  blood 
must  be  real,  we  do  not  mean  that  they  must  exist  here 
and  now,  but  that  either  they  have  existed,  or  do,  or 

*  This  often  misunderstood  principle,  which  was  so  prominent  a 
feature  in  Aristotle's  philosophy,  does  not  mean  that  in  nature  every- 
thing attains  its  final  end.  It  was  as  evident  to  Aristotle  as  it  is  to 
us  that  of  the  millions  of  seeds,  for  instance,  that  fall  in  the  forest 
very  few  attain  their  end.  The  principle  moans  simply  that  where 
nature  appoints  an  end,  that  end  is  a  reality,  and  can,  given  the  ])ropor 
conditions,  be  really  attained.  It  is  curious  that  philosophers  of  such 
widely  different  schools  of  thought  as  Aristotle  and  St.  Thomas  on 
the  one  hand  and  Kant  on  the  other  should  be  in  agreement  in  regard 
to  this  principle.  In  Dialectic  (AblK)t,  page  242,  text  and  note)  Kant 
explains  that  where  a  want  or  inclination  is  subjective,  i.e.  belongs 
to  the  individual  alone,  we  cannot  jwstulate  the  reality  of  its  object  : 
where  it  is  objective  or  belongs  to  every  rational  being,  its  object 
must  be  real.  In  this  case,  he  tells  us,  we  may  a.ssumc  in  nature  the 
conditions  necessary  for  the  satisfying  of  sueh  want. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  73 

will  exist,  and  in  some  place — we  mean  simply  that 
they  are  real,  that  the  natural  object  of  every  natural 
appetite  is  necessarily  real.  And,  therefore,  since  the 
infinite  good  is  the  ncccssaiN-  natiiiil  1  ml  of  the  appetite 
of  will,  the  infinite  good  is  a  i\al  <  '  jif^t  aird"not  an 
abstraction.* 

Let  us  examine  this  principle  a  little  more  fully,  for 
we  believe  it  has  only  to  be  fully  understood  in  order 
to  secure  for  itself  immediate  acceptance.  There  are 
three  conditions  that  must  be  fulfilled  before  we  can  say 
with  certainty  that  the  object  of  an  appetite  is  neces- 
sarily real,  all  of  which  conditions  are,  indeed,  implied 
in  the  word  "  natural,"  but  which  yet  require  to  be 
expressly  formulated.  These  are — (i)  the  appetite  in 
question  must  be  an  original  part  of  our  constitution, 
and  not  something  artificial ;     (2)   the  object  must  be 

*  The  reader  should  compare  and  contrast  the  argument  here 
given  (a  form  of  argument  which  is  common  in  St.  Thomas,  and  is 
used  by  him  to  prove,  amongst  other  things,  the  immortality  of  the 
soul)  and  the  modernist  view  of  the  proof  for  God's  existence,  which 
latter  view  we  condemn  as,  not  only  untrue,  but  as  contradictory 
and  absurd.  The  modernist  view  is  that  the  existence  of  God  is  not 
provable  intellectually,  that  yet  we  know  Him  to  exist  because  of  a 
feeling  of  need  for  God — a  feeling  by  means  of  which  we  are  brought 
into  direct  communication  with  Him  and  perceive  Him  in  some  way, 
or  feel  Him,  as  truly,  though  perhaps  not  so  clearly,  as  we  feel  many 
individual  objects  of  the  sensuous  world.  But  being  perceived  by 
feeling  only,  we  can  only  apprehend  God  as  phenomenon. — His 
noumenal  or  real  existence,  it  is  said,  is  hidden  from  us. 

Now  this  modernist  theory  is  opposed  in  every  way  to  the  line  of 
argument  followed  in  the  text.  For  (i)  the  argument  given  in  the 
text  is  merely  used  in  confirmation  of  the  other  intellectual  arguments 
of  Natural  Theology,  such  as  the  argument  for  the  necessity  of  a  first 
cause,  arguments  which,  we  maintain,  establish  God's  existence 
beyond  all  possibility  of  doubt.  (2)  Tlie  argument  in  the  text  is 
itself  an  intellectual  argument  and  proof  of  God's  real  noumenal 
existence.  We  know  that  the  natural  end  of  a  natural  appetite  must 
be  real.  And  hence  we  argue  that,  since  God  is  the  end  of  the  natural 
appetite  of  will,  He  must  be  real.  (3)  Our  argument  does  not  pr"- 
suppose  that  our  intellect  apprehends  God  immediately  as  it  beholus 
the  simpler  mathematical  relations  of  whole  and  part  immediately, 
and  as  the  senses  or  feelings  apprehend  their  object  immediately. 
This  is  the  view  of  the  ontologists  which  St.  Thomas  expressly  con- 
demns. Our  argument,  following  St.  Thomas,  is  that  the  immediate 
and  formal  object  of  intellect  is  being-in-general,  and  that  of  will  is 
good-in-general,  but  since  God  is  the  only  thing  that  can  fully  exhaust 
the  capacity  of  these  objects  and  of  the  faculties  that  concern  them, 
He  is  our  ultimate  end,  and  real. 


74  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

essential,  and,  therefore,  desired  by  each  individual  of 
the  species  to  which  the  appetite  belongs  ;  (3)  it  must 
be  a  necessary  and  not  merely  a  suitable  object.  T(J 
explain  : — (i)  The  desire  must  be  original  in  our  conw 
stitution  like  the  desire  for  food,  not  artificial  like  thi 
desire  of  the  miser  for  hoarded  wealth.  For  what  w^ 
say  is  that  nature  does  nothing  in  vain,  but  we  do  not 
attribute  such  unerring  realisation  to  the  desires  of  the 
miser  or  other  artificial  desires,  which  we  admit  are  often 
in  vain.  (2)  The  objects  must  be  essential,  and,  so,  must 
be  desired  by  each  individual.  Consequently,  the  object 
of  a  desire  or  appetite  is  not  necessarily  real  if  it  is  an 
object  of  desire  only  {a)  under  certain  circumstances  or 
at  certain  times,  or  (6)  for  some  men  or  for  a  particular 
class  of  men  only.  Thus  [a)  we  cannot  (like  the 
modernists)  affirm  that  the  Christian  revelation  can  be 
shown  to  be  genuine  on  this  natural  ground  alone  that 
Christianity  is  a  need,  and  that  wherever  it  is  discarded 
men  become  degenerate.  Christianity  (if  we  might 
borrow  an  illustration  from  revelation)  was  not  a  need 
before  the  fall  of  man.  It  is  not  needed,  therefore, 
under  all  circumstances  and  at  all  times,  [h)  Food  must 
be  a  reality  because  it  is  a  need  for  every  man  ;  but  we 
cannot  postulate  the  reality  of  bread  or  of  any  special 
kind  of  food  merely  on  the  ground  that  it  is  desired, 
since  it  is  desired  not  by  all  men  but  only  by  some. 
Again,  truth  in  general  is  desired  by  all  men,  and,  there- 
fore, the  means  of  knowing  truth  must  be  a  reality. 
But  the  knowledge  of  Mathematics  or  of  Physics  is 
desired  by  particular  classes  of  men  only,  and,  there- 
fore, the  mere  desire  for  or  need  of  these  does  not  prove 
that  a  knowledge  is  possible  of  special  sciences  like 
Mathematics  or  Physics.*     The  object,   then,   must  be 

•  Neither  can  we  on  the  mere  ground  of  satisfying  a  need,  postu- 
late the  truth  of  any  special  law  of  Matlu'matics  or  Physics.  We 
could  not,  for  instance,  postulate  the  priucii)l('  of  the  uiiifonnity  of 
nature  on  the  mere  ground  that  it  satislics  the  need  of  "order"  in 
our  conceptions  of  Physics,  for  this  i)rinc.ii>lc  biloiiKS  to  a  special 
science. 


THE  END^  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  75 

a  need  of  every  individual-  of  the  species  to  which  the 
need  beiongs7"anT  it  must  K^uain  Ihc  object  of  their 
appetite  under  all  circuinstaiu cs.  (j)  The  object  must 
be  necessary  and  not  merely  suitable  for  the  satisfaction 
of  ah  appetite.  Thus,  books  are  suItaHe^to^ahd  satisfy 
our  desire  for  knowledge.  But  we  could  not  on  that 
account  alone  postulate  their  reality,  since  they  are  not 
absolutely  necessary  to  knowledge. 

All  three  conditions  are  contained  in  the  word 
"  natural,"  and  they  will,  therefore,  be  understood  as 
implied  w^henever  we  use  the  word  "  natural  "  in  con- 
nection with  our  present  question. 

This  explanation  being  given,  we  go  on  to  show  that 
the  object  of  a  natural  appetite  must  be  real.  Suppose, 
therefore,  that  some  day  in  the  distant  future  we  should 
come  across  a  human  heart,  and  should  come  also  to 
know  that  nature  had  made  that  heart,  and  the  valves 
in  it,  in  order  to  send  blood  through  veins,  we  should 
then  be  at  once  certain  (even  though  we  had  no  other 
ground  of  certainty  than  this)  that  blood  and  veins  were 
a  reality.  We  might  not  be  certain  that  the  heart  had 
succeeded  in  sending  the  blood  through  the  veins,  but 
we  should  be  certain  that  as  the  heart  was  real,  blood 
and  veins  were  also  real.  And  suppose  that  we  found 
a  tooth  and  knew  that  that  tooth  had  as  its  natural  end 
to  chew  food  and  prepare  it  for  the  stomach,  then  we 
should  be  absolutely  certain  that,  as  a  tooth  is  a  reality, 
so  also  its  natural  object,  food  and  stomach,  must  be  a 
reality.  The  reason  is  that  nature  does  not  act'  in  vain. 
For  nature  does  not  think  out,  as  we  do,  her  plans  bit  by 
bit.  She  does  not  to-day  produce  a  random  object  and 
to-morrow  determine  its  end.  She  does  not  first  make 
a  heart,  and  then  declare  that  a  heart  is  good  for  driving 
blood  through  a  body,  and  then  proceed  to  fashion  the 
end.  It  is  because  the  end  is  real  that  she  takes  real  means 
to  its  accomplishment.  It  is  because  she  wants  the  blood 
to  course  through  the  body  that  she  makes  the  heart. 
Hence,  if  we  discover  that  the  means  are  real,  we  may 


^6 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  EtHlCS 


logically  argiie  that  the  end  is  real  also.  Other  examples 
of  this  principle  will  readily  suggest  themselves.  If, 
for  instance,  a  muscle  be  real,  and  its  natural  end  be  to 
move  a  limb,  then  movable  limbs  must  be  a  reality; 
and  if  the  natural  pores  of  a  tree  be  meant  to  suck  up 
moisture,  then,  seeing  the  pores  of  a  tree,  we  should 
judge  with  absolute  security  that  moisture  was  a  real 
thing  in  nature,  and  not  a  mere  imagination  or  abstrac- 
tion of  our  minds.* 

But  the  law  that  holds  for  limbs  and  the  pores  of 
trees  holds  also  for  the  human  will.  Here  we  have  a 
power  of  nature  which  extends  to,  the  ^capacity  of 
which  is  satisfied  only  by,  one  object,  viz.  the 
infinite  good.  And,  therefore,  we  argue,  since  the 
will  and  its  act  are  real,  so  also  is  the  natural  end 
of  the  will  real — namely,  the  infinite  "  good."  The 
last  end  of  the  will,  therefore,  is  no  mere  abstraction. 


*  "  In  applying  this  reasoning  to  the  case  of  the  will  it  is  not  neces- 
sary to  suppose  that  the  will  is  a  distinct  faculty  from  the  rest  of  the 
faculties,  or  that  it  is  a  faculty  at  all,  but  only  that  man  is  naturally 
a  desiring  or  conative  thing — that  he  is  not  like  a  stone  which  has  no 
desire,  that  we  are  naturally  conative  beings  like  the  plant  or  animal 
which,  of  itself  and  as  a  result  of  natural  power  given  it,  moves  to 
ends.  Some  philosophers  have  considered  that  motion  and  appetite 
are  not  natural  phenomena  and  original,  but  only  accidental  results 
of  knowledge.  Nothing  could  be  more  opposed  to  all  that  we  know 
of  the  animal  mechanism  than  this  view.  The  motion  of  a  plant 
growing,  and,  more  particularly,  the  desire  of  animals,  are  not  an 
after-cifect,  or  accidental,  or  an  epiphenomenon,  but  an  original 
function  ;  for  since  animals  have  motor  limbs  adapted  by  nature  to 
respond  to  the  desire  for  ends,  so  the  desire  for  ends  must  be  as  natural 
and  original  as  are  the  limbs  themselves.  Most  of  a  man's  movements 
are  results  of  desires,  and  they  are  by  nature  meant  to  result  from 
desires,  from  ends  perceived  and  wished  for.  We  are,  therefore,  by 
nature,  desiring  animals.  This  is  the  presupposition  of  the  argument 
given  in  the  text.  The  theory  which  makes  of  will  or  conation  a  mere 
accidental  phenomenon  in  man  is  known  as  the  theory  of  "  hetero- 
genetic  "  will.  That  which  we  here  propound  is  known  as  the  "  auto- 
genetic."  In  addition  to  the  above  argument,  drawn  from  the 
mechanism  of  the  body,  we  may  al.so  use  Leslie  Stephen's  argument 
tliat  if  appetite  were  not  an  original  part  of  the  living  constitution 
the  race  of  living  things  could  not  have  survived  a  generation.  With- 
out the  appetite  for  food  the  individual  could  not  subsist  ;  without 
tlie  appetite  ft)r  racial  continuance  the  race  could  not  survive.  A 
fuller  discuHsion  on  this  subject  will  be  given  in  our  chai)ter  on  the 
Good. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  77 

It  is  no  universal  in  mente  merely.     It  is  the  real  infinite 
good.* 

To  the  foregoing  line  of  argument  the  following  is  a 
possible  difficulty  : — the  axiom  on  which  the  argument 
here  defended  rests,  namely,  that  the  end  of  a  real 
natural  appetite  must  necessarily  be  real,  is  an  axiom 
which  is  guaranteed  to  us  b}'^  natural  science  alone. 
Any  argument,  therefore,  which  rests  on  that  axiom 
must,  like  the  axiom  itself,  be  kept  within  the  limits  of 
nature,  and  is  valid  only  within  these  limits.  But  the 
argument  as  here  developed  is  made  to  extend  beyond 
these  limits,  for  it  is  used  to  establish  the  reality  of  the 
infinite  good,  which  is  of  necessity  outside  of  nature. 
Hence  the  argument  is  invalid. 

Our  reply  is — We  grant  that  the  axiom  referred  to  is 
guaranteed  by  natural  science  only.  And,  therefore, 
we  conclude  that  the  only  appetites  to  which  our  argu- 
ment could  validly  be  made  to  extend  are  the  natural 
appetites.  But,  granted  the  natural  appetite,  we  claim 
that  its  object  is  real  whether  that  object  be  in  the 
material  and  natural  world  or  outside  it.  However,  we  | 
also  claim  that  such  object,  even  though  it  may  lie  out- 
side the  visible  universe,  is  yet  in  some  sense  within 


*  The  whole  argument  is  just  an  expansion  of  St.  Thomas',  "  non 
est  inane  naturae  desiderium  "  (Comm.  on  Ar.  I.,  16) — the  itahcs  are 
ours. 

We  must  here  say  a  word  on  the  proof  offered  by  Cardinal  Zigliara 
and  Father  Meyer  for  the  reality  of  the  ultimate  end.  The  desire  for 
this  ultimate  end,  they  say,  is  not  a  free  desire.  It  is  implanted  in 
man  by  nature — i.e.,  by  God  Himsefl.  If  that  end,  therefore,  be 
unreal,  we  are  deceived  by  God — which  is  impossible. 

Our  answer  is  very  simple.  To  drive  us  to  an  end  which  is  unreal 
is  not  necessarily  deception.  It  would  be  deception  if  with  this 
impulse  we  had  also  an  express  declaration  that  the  end  is  real.  It  is 
we  who  deceive  ourselves  if  we  regard  as  real  what  may  be  only  mental, 
when  there  is  no  express  declaration  that  the  end  is  real.  Neither 
could  it  be  considered  vain  or  idle  on  God's  part  to  direct  us  to  an 
unreal  end.  It  would  be  a  vain  thing  to  drive  us  towards  an  unreal 
end  if,  as  Hartmann,  speaking  on  the  subject  of  the  illusoriness  of 
the  desire  for  happiness,  very  sensibly  states,  no  purpose  were  served 
by  such  an  impulse.  But  the  possible  purposes  of  such  an  impulse 
might  be  mapy.  The  purposes  it  might  serve  in  giving,  for  instance, 
some  zp^t  to  life,  we  may  leave  to  the  reader  to  work  out  for  himself. 


78  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  sphere  of  natural  science,  for,  though  beyond  this 
world,  it  is  still  the  natural  complement  to  a  natural 
faculty.     In  this  sense  we  speak  of  it  as  natural.* 

Having  now  seen  that  the  jiatural  object  of  our  will 
is  the  infinite  good,  and  having  seen  also  that  this  infinite 
good  is  not  an  abstract  thing,  a  universale  in  mente,  but 
a  reality,  we  turn  to  ask — What  is  this  infinite  object  ? 
It  is  none  else  but  the  uncreated  good — God  Himself. 
As  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  puts  it — "  Nihil  potest  quietare 
voluntatem  hominis  nisi  bonum  universale,  quod  non 
invenitur  in  aliquo  creato  sed  in  solo  Deo."  There  is  no 
other  real  infinity  but  God.  Every  other  reality  is  finitCj 
and  even  the  sum  of  them  is  finite,  and,  consequently, 
they  could  not  be  the  object  of  perfect  happiness,  or  the 
object  of  our  will.  Of  course,  in  desiring  this  infinite 
good  we  do  not,  as  is  supposed  in  the  theory  of  Ontolo- 
gism,  put  it  before  ourselves  in  every  action  individually 
and  determinately  as  God.  Consciously  and  naturally 
we  desire  only  honiim  or  bonum-in-universali.  But  the 
object  of  that  desire,  the  only  object  which  will  satisfy 
that  desire — in  the  words  of  St.  Thomas,  the  only  real 
object  in  which  this  honum-in-imiversali  is  to  be  found 

*  Modem  ethicians  have  shown  a  strange  aversion  to  any  theory 
of  Ethics  that  would  place  the  final  end  of  man  outside  of  the  finite 
world.  It  should  be  remarked,  however,  first,  that  the  ends  of  natural 
organisms  are  often  separated  from  the  organism  in  time  and  in  space. 
The  end  of  the  plant  seed  is  tree  in  fruit  and  flower.  The  end  of  the 
faculty  of  vision  is  colour.  The  first  end  is  remote  in  point  of  time, 
the  second  in  point  of  space.  The  degree  of  remoteness  in  any  case 
will  depend  on  the  nature  of  the  organism.  Secondly,  if  the  end  of 
man  has  to  be  placed  outside  of  the  finite  world  it  is  because  nature 
has  made  us  so,  and  we  have  to  abide  by  the  natural  necessities. 
Fortunately  or  unfortunately  for  the  ethician  our  human  will  is  such 
that  no  finite  object  can  satisfy  it.  In  every  act  it  aims  not  at  this 
good,  but  at  good  or  bonum  in  universali  and  only  the  infinite  can 
sati.sfy  fully  such  a  desire.  Thirdly,  in  determining  distinctions  of 
right  and  wrong  it  will  not  Ix;  necessary  to  consider  any  other  world 
than  the  present.  As  our  criterion  will  show,  we  base  these  distinctions 
on  an  examination  of  our  natural  constitution,  i.e.,  our  faculties  and 
their  immediate  objects.  For  instance,  the  rc'(|uirements  of  life  and 
health  <lctennin(!  the  law  in  regard  to  eating  and  drinking,  life  and 
health  lx.'ing  the  immediate  natural  end  of  the  appetite  for  food. 
ICvcn,  therefore,  though  the  end  of  man  lies  outside  this  material  world, 
our  study  of  good  and  evil  is  a  purely  natural  science — it  is  based  on 
purely  natural  facts  and  principles. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  79 

— is  God.     And,   therefore,  in  God  only  shall  the  will 

reach  its  end  and  be  at  rest.     "  Fecisti  nos,"  says  St. 

Augustine,    "  ad    Te,    Domine,    et    inquietum  est    cor 
nostrum  donee  requiescat  in  Te." 


(c)  On   the  Attainment  of  our   Last   End,   or   on 
THE  Subjective  Final  End  (Beatitude) 

On  the  subjective  final  end  of  man  or  the  attainment 
of  our  last  end  four  questions  arise  : — 

(i)  What  is  this  subjective  state — is  it  a  faculty,  a 
habit,  or  an  act  ? 

(2)  If  an  act,  of  what  faculty  is  it  an  act  ? 

(3)  For  perfect  happiness  is  it  necessary  that  the 
exercise  of  our  highest  faculty  should  be  accompanied 
by  that  of  the  other  faculties  also  ? 

(4)  Is  perfect  happiness  attainable  ? 

(i)  Final  happiness,  or  the  attainment  of  our  last  end, 

is  an  act. 

Faculties  and  habits  are  merely  means  to  acts — they 
are  in  potentia  to  their  own  acts — w'hereas  our  final 
perfection  must  have  nothing  incomplete  about  it  ;  it 
must  not  be  mere  potentia.  We  have  eyes  and  the 
power  of  vision  that  we  may  see,  virtues  that  we  may 
live  well,  intellects  that  we  may  know.  In  the  order  of 
nature  "  act  "  is  the  end  and  principle  of  all  powers. 
Unused  faculties,  faculties  that  never  come  into  act, 
are  useless  and  have  no  place  in  nature,  and  naturally 
they  often  degenerate  and  disappear.  Man's  perfect/ 
happiness,  then,  will  consist  in  an  act. 

(2)  Our  final  happiness  will  consist  in  an  act,  not  of 
the  sensitive,  but  of  the  intellectual  faculty. 

This  proposition  depends  on  another  former  proposi- 
tion, that  the  final  objective  end  of  man  is  the  infinite 


8o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

good.  Now,  the  infinite  good  can  be  attained  by  intel- 
lect but  not  by  sense,  and,  therefore,  the  essential  act  of 
our  final  happiness  will  be  an  act  of  the  intellectual 
faculty  and  not  of  sense.  Of  course,  in  the  attainment 
of  the  infinite  the  senses  also  must  experience  their 
proper  happiness  in  some  way,  since  in  the  infinite  is 
contained  the  end  or  object  of  the  senses  as  well  as  of 
the  intellect.  Still,  it  would  be  a  mistake  to  consider 
the  act  of  the  senses  as  needed  essentially  in  the  attain- 
ment of  our  final  end.  For  the  senses  are  means  o.nly 
to  the  higher  knowledge  of  the  intellect,  and  they~are 
often  little  more  than  a  hindrance  to  us  in  our  intellectual 
work  or  in  the  exercise  of  our  highest  and  best  opera- 
tions. Of  the  delight  of  the  senses,  however,  following 
the  attainment  of  our  last  end  we  shall  say  something 
more  presently. 
4  Now,  in  man  there  are  three  kinds  of  intellectual 
lactivities — (a)  those  of  the  speculative  intellect,  {b)  of 
Ithe  practical  intellect,  and  (c)  of  the  will. 
'  But  the  attainment  of  our  final  end  cannot  be  an  act 
of  the  practical  intellect,  for  the  acts  of  the  practical 
intellect  are  themselves  a  means  to  the  work  which  they 
subserve,  and,  consequently,  they  could  not  constitute 
our  highest  perfection.  Neither  can  it  be  an  act  of  the 
will.  The  act  of  the  will  is  twofold — desire  and  delight. 
I'he  first  supposes  the  end  yet  unattained,  and,  there- 
fore, it  could  not  constitute  our  final  happiness, 
which  is  the  attainment  of  the  end — consecutio  finis. 
The  second  supposes  the  end  already  attained,  and 
is,  therefore,  a  consequence  of  the  attainment  of 
happiness. 

The  essential  act,  therefore,  which  will  constitute  the 
attainment  of  our  last  end  is  an  act  of  our  speculative 
intellect — -an  act,  that  is,  of  contemplation — as  Aristotle 
expresses  it,  ^  an  act  of  the  soul  according  to  the  best 
and  most  perfect  virtue."  In  the  contemplation  of  the 
last  objective  end,  in  that  degree  which  nature  makes 
possible  for  us,  lies  the  act  of  our  soul  according  to  its 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  8i 

most  perfect  virtue.*  But  this  act  of  the  intellect  will 
be  accompanied  by  delight  of  our  wills  [bonum  concomi- 
tans)  in  the  fruition  of  our  final  end,  and  also  by  delight 
in  our  senses  in  so  far  as  sense  can  share  in  the  attain- 
ment of  our  end. 

We  shall  now,  in  order  to  bring  out  more  clearly  this 
doctrine  of  man's  subjective  final  end — that  the  end  con- 
sists in  the  highest  act  of  intellect — contrast  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas'  teaching  with  two  other  widely  different  and 
well-known  theories  of  modern  philosophy — (i.)  that  of 
Professor  Paulsen  and  Professor  Simmel,  on  the  one 
hand,  that  man's  end  consists  in  the  "  normal  develop- 
ment of  the  vital  functions,"  as  Paulsen  says,  and  in 
the  "  maximum  of  activity,"  as  Professor  Simmel  says  ; 
and,  on  the  other  hand,  (ii.)  the  view  of  Schopenhauer, 
that  the  end  of  man  is  the  nirvana.  No  theories  could 
be  more  opposed  than  that  of  Schopenhauer  and  that  of 
Paulsen  and  Professor  Simmel. 

(i.)  According  to  St.  Thomas  our  final  happiness  will 
consist  in  our  knowledge  of  the  infinite,  which  know- 
ledge will  be  accompanied  by  a  corresponding  delight. 
According  to  Professor  Paulsen  our  final  end  is  the 
normal  development  of  our  faculties.  Now,  this  view  of 
Professor  Paulsen  is,  in  the  first  place,  not  very  enlight- 
ening, for  it  does  not  tell  us  what  our  development  is  t 
consist  in  or  towards  what  end  it  is  directed.  In  th 
second  place  it  is  untrue.  For,  first,  development  is  not 
the  end  of  anything.  A  tree  develops  in  growing.  But 
growing  is  not  the  end  of  a  tree.  Growth  is  itself  a 
means  to  the  final  act  of  the  tree — its  end  lies  in  the. 
final  act.     Secondly,  the  man  who  lives  a  good,  rational 

*  Some  writers  would  seem  to  insinuate  that  mere  knowledge 
could  never  afford  us  full  human  satisfaction  no  matter  how  great  the 
object.  It  should  be  remembered,  however,  that  in  the  last  analysis 
all  pleasure  is  based  on  cognition.  The  pleasures  of  taste  and  touch 
are  based  on  'sense  cognition  or  sense  consciousness.  The  enjoyment 
of  anything  possessed  is  a  pleasure  of  cognition.  What  else,  for 
instance,  is  there  in  the  enjoyment  of  scenery,  of  conversation,  of 
friends,  except  some  cognitive  act,  an  act  either  of  intellect  or  of 
sense  ? 

V'ol.  1—6 


e 


^^^  ou 


82  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

life  develops  liis  faculties  normally,  yet  such  a  man  has 
surely  not  attained  his  ultimate  end.  Our  ultimate  end 
fills  up  the  full  measure  of  our  capacities.  But  no  man's 
will  can  be  satisfied  here  below,  even  whilst  his  functions 
are  being  normally  developed.  Thirdly,  when  we  attain 
to  knowledge  we  no  longer  require  to  study.  When  we 
reach  the  end  of  our  journey  we  do  not  need  any  longer 
to  walk.  So  also  there  are  some  faculties  that  are 
merely  means  to  others,  and  if  is  not  necessary  that 
such  faculties  should  continue  to  develop  or  to  exercise 
themselves  when  we  have  attained  our  final  end.  Hence 
our  final  end  is  not  necessarily  the  normal  development 
of  all  the  functions. 

Professor  Simmel's  view  *  that  the  end  of  man  is  the 
maximum  of  activity  recalls  St.  Thomas'  doctrine  that 
the  subjective  final  end  of  man — that  is,  the  attainment 
of  our  final  end — consists  in  an  act.  Now,  naturally, 
the  knowledge  of  the  infinite  good  will  involve  the  maxi- 
mum of  intellectual  activity.  But  Professor  Simmel's 
view  makes  no  distinction  of  activity  which  is  merely 

means  "  and  activity  which  is  "  end."  But  many  of 
our  activities  are  means  only.  Hence  they  need  not  be 
included  in  our  final  end.  Besides,  the  end  does  not 
imply  the  maximum  of  all  activities,  even  if  all  remained. 

e  can  scarcely  believe,  for  instance,  that  our  final  end 
summum  bonum  implies  the  maximum  of  vegetative 
activity,  for  example,  maximum  digestion  and  maxi- 
mum growth  ;  or  the  maximum  of  sensile  activity,  for 
instance,  the  maximum  of  hearing  or  of  touch  ;  or  the 
maximum  of  motor  activity,  for  instance,  the  swiftest 
movements ;  or  even  the  maximum  of  imagination, 
which  would  mean  fever  and  madness  and  not  the 
healthy  activity  of  the  enjoyment  of  our  final  end.  If, 
therefore,  this  theory  of  Professor  Sunmel's  is  to  be 
saved  from  such  absurdities,  we  must  regard  it  as  mean- 

•  Modern  philosophers  call  this  view,  that  the  end  consists  in 
activity,  the  theory  of  cncrgism.  They  oppose  it  to  the  Hedonistic 
theory  that  the  end  is  pleasure. 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  83 

ing .  that  man's  end  is  the  maximum  activity  of  the 
highest  faculty  and  the  due  and  subordinate  activity  of 
the  others — and  then  Professor  Simmel  is  at  one  with 
St.  Thomas,  except  that,  first,  whereas  St.  Thomas  points 
out  that  our  highest  activity  consists  in  the  attainment 
of  the  highest  and  fullest  object  which  intellect  is  capable 
of  attaining,  Professor  Simmel  does  not  sa}'  in  what  the 
maximum  of  activity  consists  ;  and,  secondly,  Professor 
Simmel's  view  represents  all  the  faculties  as  involved 
in  the  final  act,  whereas  we  know  that  some  of  them 
are  only  means,  and  that  consequently  they  will  form 
no  necessary  part  of  the  attainment  of  our  final  end,  if 
the  final  end  can  possibly  be  attained  without  them. 
And  it  certainly  can  be  attained  without  some  of  them. 
The  question  whether  and  how  far  the  lower  senses 
and  passions  will  be  needed  as  integral  parts  of  happiness 
will  be  treated  presently. 

(11.)  Schopenhauer's  theory  that  our  end  is  the  Nir- 
vana *  is  the  direct  opposite  of  that  of  Professors  Simmel 
and  Paulsen,  f  It  is  opposed  also  in  the  fullest  way  to 
St.  Thomas  Aquinas'  theory  that  the  end  of  man  is  the 
highest  human  activity,  for  the  Nirvana  is  the  absence 
of  all  activity.  Now,  the  Nirvana  is  not  our  natural 
end,  for  no  appetite  tends  naturally  to  its  own  annihila 
tion  or  to  inaction.  On  the  contrary,  all  nature  tenc'j 
to  movement  and  to  the  production  of  its  highest  a^ 
Nature  aims  at  its  own  maintenance  and  development, 
and  if,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  maintenance  be  not  secured 
or  if  development  cease,  that  effect  is  the  result,  not  of 
natural  tendency  from  within,  but  of  antagonistic  forces 
from  without,  and  of  the  failure  of  natural  conditions 
within.  All  living  things  tend  to  live.  They  resist  dis- 
ruption.    Conscious  life  tends  to  continued  conscious- 

*  "  The  denial  of  the  will  to  live  is  the  way  of  redemption  " 
("  Studies  in  Pessimism,"  page  27). 

t  Indeed,  errors  in  philosophy  have  a  curious  way  of  grouping 
themselves  in  opposition.  The  philosophy  of  one  age  regards  maa  as 
mure  matter,  that  of  another  as  mere  mind.  Not  less  opposed  are 
the  views  of  moiiern  ethicians  on  man's  final  end. 


4Vi 


84  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

ness,   not   to  forgetfiilness.     The  Nirvana,   therefore,   is 
not  our  final  natural  end. 

(3)  Does  integral  happiness  include  the  exercise  of  all 
the  faculties  ? 

To  this  question  Reason  can  give  no  very  full  and 
satisfactory  reply.  The  essential  factor  in  perfect  happi- 
ness is  the  act  of  the  intellect  about  its  highest  objectju 
and  with  that  act  will  go  the  delight  of  the  will  in  the 
attainment  of  its  final  end.  But  our  principal  difficulty 
concerns  the  delights  of  the  senses  and  the  lower  pas- 
sions, many  of  which  are  but  a  means  to  our  highest 
activities  here  below.  Will  they  have  a  place  in  the 
enjoyment  of  our  final  end  ?  This  is  no  easy  question 
to  answer,  and  whatever  answer  we  give  to  it  can  only 
be  of  the  most  general  kind.  We  can,  however,  say 
with  some  security  that  such  passions  as  concern  the 
means  only  by  which  we  reach  our  end,  and  are  in  no 
sense  an  end  in  themselves,  will  possibly  then  not  be 
active,  for  when  we  have  reached  the  end  of  all,  those 
functions  which  could  concern  the  means  only  could 
serve  no  purpose  in  our  constitution.  But  such  passions 
as  have  a  worth  of  their  own  may  still  be  active.  We 
shall,  for  instance,  still  enjoy  friends,  for  even  when  we 

ave  attained  our, end  it  will  be  a  pleasure  to  have  finite 

inds  to  confer  with.  Some  passions,  therefore,  may 
remain,  and  whichever  of  them  do  remain  will  have  to 
be  satisfied  according  to  Reason.  There  will  be  the 
hcatitudo  concomitans  as  well  as  the  cssentialis. 

Again  it  may  be  that,  with  the  attainment  of  the  per- 
fect good,  imperfect  goods  may  lose  their  value  and 
attraction  for  us,  particularly  goods  of  the  sense  world. 
The  vulture  glutting  itself  with  carrion,  or  the  insect 
feeding  on  putrid  matter,  derives  pleasure  from  devour- 
ing food  of  a  kind  which  would  produce  in  a  human 
being  only  a  sickening  sensation  of  disgust.  In  like 
manner,  some  of  those  things  that  now  seem  delightful 
to   UB  and   excite   the   pasHion.s   may,   when    the   end   is 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  85 

attained,  lose  their  attraction  for  us  altogether,  or  even 
become  positively  distasteful.  It  may  be,  therefore, 
that  the  passions  will  be  no  longer  active  when  we  have 
gained  our  end. 

For  another  reason  also  it  may  be  that  with  the  at- 
tainment of  our  end  the  exercise  of  our  lower  faculties 
may  not  be  necessary,  for,  as  St.  Thomas  remarks,  it  is 
quite  possible  that  at  the  end  we  shall  be  able  to  receive 
all  the  enjoyments  of  every  sense  and  of  the  passions, 
even  without  the  exercise  of  the  senses  or  the  passions. 
For  even  now  the  higher  intellectual  enjoyments  are 
found  at  times  to  work  back  on  the  senses,  and  to 
create  in  them  a  sensuous  enjoyment.*  And  if  this 
happens  in  the  case  of  finite  objects,  it  may  more  easily 
happen  in  the  case  of  such  an  object  as  the  infinite,  in 
which  the  good  of  every  sense  and  passion  is  fully  con- 
tained— modo  eminentiori.  All  these  things,  however, 
are  above  philosophy  to  a  large  extent,  and  mere  Reason 
can  tell  us  very  little  about  them. 

(4)  Perfect  happiness  attainable  by  matt. 

A  school,  known  as  the  Elpistic  school  of  Ethicians, 
have  taught  (and  in  their  doctrine  they  are  mainly 
influenced  by  Kant)  that  the  end  of  man  consists  in  a 
never-ceasing  approach  of  Reason  and  the  will  to  some 
far-away  ideal — an  ideal  which  keeps  always  drawing  us 
on  to  its  realisation,  but  which  \'et  can  never  be  realised 
in  fact.  The  more  }ou  increase  the  sides  of  a  polygon 
inscribed  in  a  circle  the  more  it  approaches  the  circle, 
yec  it  can  never  become  one  with  the  circle.  Certain 
lines  known  as  asymptotes  keep  ever  approaching  to 
certain  curves,  yet  can  never  meet  them.  So,  it  is  con- 
tended, it  is  man's  fate  ever  to  approach  the  ethical 
ideal  asymptotically  ;    and  as  the  horizon  flies  at  our 

*  Music,  splendid  oratory,  or  witnessing  any  triumphal  event  may 
excite  pleasure,  not  only  in  the  senses  directly  concerned,  but  in  other 
senses  as  well. 


86  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

approach,  so  does  the  end  of  man,  his  final  blessedness 
or  goodness  or  happiness,  whatever  it  is,  keep  always 
departing  from  him.  "  Hope  springs  eternal,"  yet  hope 
shall  never  be  converted  into  fruition.  Hope  it  must 
always  remain.  This  theory  has  been  developed  by 
Kant,  Spencer,  Green,  and  many  others,  and  against  it 
the  present  argument  is  directed. 

•  St.  Thomas  treats  of  this  question,  whether  perfect 
happiness  is  actually  attainable,  very  briefly  and  suc- 
cinctly indeed.  He  tells  us  that  perfect  happiness  is 
attainable  because  we  have  by  nature  the  capacity  of 
perfect  happiness — i.e.,  we  are  able  to  desire  it  and  do 
naturally  desire  it.  His  argument  may  be  expanded  thus — 
the  desire  for  perfect  happiness  is  not  an  accidental 
growth  in  man.  It  is  a  ■nntural.-capad.ty,  a  natural 
desire.  It  must ,  therefore.  Jbe  capable  of  fulfilment . 
Why  ?  Because  nature  does  not  act  in  vain.  When 
men  set  ends  before  themselves,  these  ends  are  not 
always  possible  of  attainment.  But  nature  cannot  so 
fail.  If  the  end  or  capacity  of  a  tree  be  to  bloom,  then 
blooming  is  an  attainable  perfection — a  something  to 
which  the  tree,  if  properly  nursed  and  properly  directed, 
may  come.  Individual  trees  may,  indeed,  fail  to  bloom, 
for  nature  may  be  crossed  in  many  ways,  and  so  our 
present  thesis  is,  not  that  every  man  will  gain  the  end, 
but  only  that  the  end  is  attainable.  Whether  the 
individual  trees  attain  their  end  depends  altogether  on 
the  chances  they  get.  But  "  to  bloom  "  is  an  atfain- 
able  end,  and  many  trees  will  dc  facto  succeed  in  reaching 
it.  The  reason  is  that  with  nature  the  end  is  first  and 
before  all,  and  the  principle  of  all.  It  is  the  cause  of 
the  means  and  it  is  only  because  of  its  reality  and  in 
order  that  it  may  be  attained  that  the  means  are  brought 
into  existence.  To  blossom  and  bear  fruit — that  is  the 
first  thing  in  nature's  plan  ;  and  because  that  end  is 
attainable,  therefore  is  the  tree  provided  with  roots, 
bark,  arteries,  capacities — with  all,  in  fact,  that  it  is  and 
all  that  brings  it  to  its  natural  perfection.     It  is  so  also 


THE  ENDS  OF  HUMAN  ACTION  87 

with  man.  We  have  not  directed  ourselves  to  perfect 
happiness — to  the  attainment  of  the  infinite  good ; 
nature  has  directed  us  to  it  and  given  us  a  capacity  for 
it,  just  as  nature  has  given  to  the  tree  the  capacity  to 
flower.  The  appetite  for  the  infinite  good  belongs  to 
our  very  essence,  and  there  is  no  escaping  from  it.  Per- 
fect happiness,  we  conclude,  is,  therefore,  attainable  by 
man.  If  all  the  requisites  of  nature  are  fulfilled  the 
tree  will  bloom.  If  all  the  requisites  of  human  nature 
are  fulii]lg.d  by  us  and  all  the  natural  laws  are  observed,* 
then  will  a  man  reach  his  final  natural  end.  If  not,  he 
fajls^ 

But    where    is    this    perfect    happiness    realisable  ?  f 

*  We  speak  here  according  to  Reason  only.  The  higher  laws  may 
demand  more  of  us  than  nature  demands,  because,  as  a  matter  of 
fact,  we  know  from  revelation  that  in  the  end  we  shall  have  more 
than  natural  happiness. 

t  A  word  on  this  question  of  how  we  shall  enjoy  God.  It  is  plain, 
as  we  have  said,  that  our  final  happiness  is  not  to  be  had  in  this  world 
What  better  opportunities  we  shall  have  for  contemplating  and  study- 
ing God  in  another  world,  philosophy  cannot  tell  us.  It  is  certain, 
however,  that  the  vision  of  the  soul  will  be  much  clearer  and  stronger 
when  we  have  escaped  from  the  material  conditions  of  this  life  than  it 
is  now.  Here  everything  distracts  us  instead  of  centering  round  our 
final  end,  and  leading  us  on  to  Him.  When  we  are  in  possession  of 
the  end,  not  only  shall  we  know  Him,  but  we  shall  see  all  things  in 
their  true  perspective  as  leading  up  to  Him. 

In  speaking  thus  we  are  not  encroaching  on  revelation.  The 
knowledge  of  God  of  which  we  have  spoken  is,  as  we  have  proved, 
attainable  in  the  order  of  nature,  though  not  in  this  world.  It  is  still 
natural  knowledge — i.e.,  knowledge  got  by  abstraction  from  creatures. 
From  all  that  we  have  known  here  and  from  all  that  we  shall  see  in 
the  next  world  we  shall  rise  to  the  knowledge  of  God.  This  means 
that  we  shall  still  know  Him  by  an  act  of  our  ordinary  Reason,  but 
perfectly  according  to  Reason.  Reason  does  not  tell  us  more  than 
this.  Revelation,  however,  goes  farther  and  declares  to  us  that  for 
the  knowledge  of  God  of  which  nature  holds  out  hope  to  man,  there 
will  be  substituted  a  higher  knowledge  altogether — viz.,  that  of  the 
beatific  vision,  the  vision  of  God  seen  face  to  face,  seen  in  Himself, 
directly  and  personally.  Knowledge  by  abstraction  is  possible  to  our 
natural  faculties.  But  the  beatific  vision  or  the  knowledge  of  God 
seen  "  face  to  face  "  is  out  of  the  reach  of  nature  and  of  Reason  alto- 
gether. It  consists  in  the  indwelling  of  God  Himself  in  our  intellects 
and  in  our  seeing  Him  by  means  of  Himself.  Of  this  state  or  act 
our  natural  Reason  can  know  absolutely  nothing  apart  from  revelation, 
and  not  being  the  object  of  any  natural  science  it  lies  outside  the 
trovince  of  Ethics.  But,  by  Reason  we  know  what  Aristotle  knew 
phat  the  supreme  happiness  of  man  is  to  be  found  in  the  act  of  the 
highest  faculty,  according  to  Reason,  in  a  perfect  natural  life.     We 


88  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Plainly  not  in  this  life.  Do  what  we  may  here,  we 
cannot  be  perfectly  happy.  And  if  not  realisable  in 
this  world,  what  then  ?  Plainly  in  another.  If  not  in 
winter,  then  in  summer.  If  not  on  stony  ground,  then 
in  the  better  soil.  If  not  here  and  now,  then  elsewhere 
and  hereafter.  It  is  the  same  in  all  departments  of 
nature — with  the  trees  and  with  man.  Nature  has 
many  seasons  and  man}^  places.  To  limit  her  purposes 
and  her  powers  to  one  place  or  time  would  be  to  take  a 
very  limited  view  of  her  extent  and  her  powers.* 

know  from  Ethics  what  the  act  and  faculty  in  question  are,  and  we 
know  some  of  the  conditions  of  the  perfect  natural  life — they  are 
different  from  life  as  we  actually  find  it. 

*  All  that  we  have  said  in  the  present  section  on  the  possibility 
of  attaining  our  final  natural  end  becomes  clearer  and  more  cogent 
still  on  the  supposition  of  a  Creator  and  of  Divine  Providence. 

At  the  end  of  this  chapter  it  may  not  be  out  of  place  to  anticipate 
something  of  what  will  be  said  in  our  chapter  on  "  the  criterion,"  in 
order  to  explain  what  actions  will  lead  to  our  fmal  end— a  question 
which  will  already  have  occurred  to  most  readers.  Speaking  according 
to  mere  Reason  we  can  say  with  certainty  that  just  as  a  plant  tends 
to  its  final  perfection  in  summer  by  having  its  natural  wants  supplied 
before  the  summer  arrives,  so,  by  the  perfect  fulfilment  of  nature's 
laws  here  below  man  tends  naturally  to  attain  his  final  perfection  in 
the  place  and  under  the  conditions  in  which  that  perfection  shall 
become  possible.  What  those  laws  are  will  be  explained  in  our 
chapters  on  "  The  Criterion  "  and  "  On  Laws." 


CHAPTER  IV      I 
ON  GOOD  AND  EVIL  V 
{a)  Meaning  of  Good 

(r)  Taken  in  its  broadest  and  most  generic  accepta- 
tion, we  may  defme  the  "j?oo(jJl  with  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas  as  "  the  object  or  end  of  app)etitc,"  and  with 

Aristotle — o?    X"P"'    Ta     AoiTra     TTptiTTCTai      ...     to    TeAo<i — 

th^_£nd  for  which  anYthing_is  done.  Were  there  in 
the  world  no  such  thing  as  ag^iine*  there  would  be  no 
such  distinction  as  that  of  "  good  "  and  "  evil,"  just  as 
if  there  were  no  intellect  in  the  world  there  could  be  no 
truth.  But  in  various  objects  there  are  various  appe- 
tites or  JLendencies,  and  what  satisfies  these  yniions 
appetites  we  speak  of  as  good  ;  what  opposes  them  we 
describe  as  "eviTj  also  what  leads  to  the  ends  of  the 
appetites^x  is„.a.rneans  to  them *is~gbod',"  and  what~teads 
away  from  them  is  evil.  Thus  We  caira~1cniTe"good  if 
it  cutsTbecause  that  is  the  end  we  wish  it  to  fulfil.  We 
call  medicine  good  because  it  cures,  and  we  call  curing 
good  because  health  is  something  that  men  desire. 

The  gQod^tlien,  is  defined__by  refererirp  in  nppptifp 
It  is  the  object  or  end  of  appetite.* 

Now,  sometimes  there  are,  even  in  the  one  being,  a 
great  number  of  appetites,  and  it  is  even  possible  that 
these  may  be  in  partial  conflict  w'ith  one  another — that 

*  It  may  be  well  to  tell  the  reader  at  this  point  that  the  moral 
good  is  simDhLikinorQ  specific  determinatirfp  of  ihi'i  p«m«ral  conception 
ofjhc  "  good . ' '  The  mpral  t^oofl  is  any  act  wlij^-.h  is  direr.t^fj,  ]iy  Rpa«;np 
to  the  final  eml^tng  end  which  fully  satisfies  our  appetitive  capacity, 
afTcPwhich  therefore  cannot  serve  a^  a  mere  means  to  something  else. 
This  is  not  only  St.  Thomas'  view,  but  the  view  of  most  modern 
ethicians.  "  Morality,"  says  Bradley,  "  implies  an  end  in  itself " 
("  Ethical  Studies,"  page  60). 


90  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

is,  that  the  same  object  which  will  satisfy  one  appetite 
will  prevent  the  satisfaction  of  another.     For  instance, 
the  same  food  that  will  satisfy  the  appetite  of  the  palate 
will  often  hinder  the  attainment  or  preservation  of  that 
which  is  more  desired  than  the  pleasures  of  the  palate — 
namely,  our  health  and  life.     In  such  cases  it  is  often 
not  easy  to  say  whether  the  object  that  gives  rise  to 
such  diverse  effects  should  be  called  good.     The  obvious 
■I  rule  to  be  followed  is  that  the  wider  appetite,  or  the 
/appetite   corresponding  to   the   farther  off   end,   should 
/  take  precedence,  and  that  the  "  good  "   should  be  de- 
/  termined  by  reference  to  it.     For  the  nearer  and  narrower 
end  is  always  conceived  as  mere  means  to  the  wider  and 
more  remote,  as  is  evident  from  the  case  given  of  foods, 
which  at  the  same  time  please  the  palate  and  injure  our 
life.     Such  an  object  could  not  be  regarded  as  good,  for 
it  conflicts  with  the  wider  and  more  fundamental  appe- 
tite— that,  namely,  for  our  life.     In  the  same  way  many 
adtB,  though  they  satisfy  particular  appetites,  are  op- 
posed to  our  appetite  for  the  final  end — and  in  no  cir- 
I  cumstances  could  an  object  that  leads  us  from  the  at- 
l/tainment  of  our  final  end  be  good.     For  in  relation  to 
the  final  end  every  other  particular  object  is  qi£iiiis  only, 
and,  no  matter  what  the  pleasure  that  attaches  to  their 
attainment,  it  would  be  irrational  to  speak  of  them  as 
good  if  they  keep  us  from  attaining  our  final  end.     All 
this,   however,   in   no   way   conflicts   with  our   opening 
statement  that  the  "  good  "  is  the  object  of  appetite.* 
On  the  contrary,  what  we  have  just  said  confirms  and 
explains  our  definition  of  the  good,  for  the  principal  end 
is  the  final  end,  and  an  object  that  opposes  the  principal 
end  ceases  to  be    a   real  or  true  end.     "  We  call  that 
/  simply     an     end     (aTrAws    ^v    t«A«ioi'),"     saj's     Aristotle, 
"  which  is  desirable  of  itself  and  not  for  something  else," 


•  This  i«  Aristotle's  definition — "  Bonum  est  quod  omnia  apiictiml," 
by  which  is  moant  not  what  everything  seeks,  but,  as  St.  Thomas 
explains  ("  S.  Thcol.,"  I.,  y.  VI.,  Art.  2),  what  anything  seeks,  ur 
any  object  that  is  sought, 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  91 

i.e.,  the  final  end.     What  opposes  it  is  not  a  real  end  or 
good. 

But  it  is  not  to  be  considered,  since  goodness  is  that 
in  an  object  which  makes  it    conformable  to   appetite, 
that,  therefore,  the  goodness  of  objects  is  an  arbitrary/  /' 
relation  which  depends  on  the  passing  and  changeable/ 
desires  of  the  human  will.     We  shall  see  presently  that 
there    are    some    things    which    a    man    w«s^__desire,. — 
since  there  are  in  man  natural  appetites  with  natural 
objects.     These  objects  wiTTbe  permanently  and  neces- 
sarily good. 

Now,  objects  of  appetite  are  of  two  kinds.  They  are 
either  such  as  are  desired  as  J3ieiins.,only  to  something 
else,  or  they  are  such  as  are  desired  on^^tkeirjnvn  account 
as  affording  satisfaction  of  themselves.  TheionTOfwe 
speak  of  as  bonunt  utile.  The  latter  are  distinguished 
into  two  classes.  The  end  of  appetite  is  either  that 
state  of  contentment  which  ensues  in_  the  nppptitp  on 
the  attainmenFol  an  obiectdesired,  or  it  is  the  object 
Itself  whose  altammenF^ings  to__the  appetite  satisfac- 
tjon.  The  former  we  speak  of  as  honum  delectabile,  the 
latter  as  honum  ho7testum.  All  ends  of  action  reduce  to 
these  three  classes  of  end  or  good,  which,  however,  are 
not  all  of  equal  im.portance  to  the  will.  Of  the  bonunt 
delcdabile  and  bonum  honestum  the  latter — that  is,  the 
bonum  honestum — is  primary,  as  we  proved  in  our  last 
chapter.  Next  in  order  of  importance  comes  the  bonum 
delcctabile.  The  bonum  utile  is,  strictly  speaking,  not 
an  end  of  appetite  at  all  since  in  itself  it  does  not  give 
satisfaction.  It  is  an  end,  only  in  the  sense  of  being 
desired  ;  and,  therefore,  in  the  order  of  nature  it  is  the 
least  fundamental  of  all.  We  now  proceed  to  a  more 
specific  determination  of  this  general  conception  of 
"good." 


(2)  "  Good "   and   "  beinq  "    {esse,   i.e.,    actuality)    are 


one. 


Good  and  being  are  one  because  (i.)  all  good  is  beinp^, 


92  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

and  (ii.)  all  beinp;  is^^togd.  and  it  is  good  in  so  far  as  it 
is  being. 

(i.)  That-^  all  goodjs  beingj^  needs  rio  proof.  If  it  is 
not_  being  JL-is  nothing,  ^and  "  nothinsili— cour^"  iiot 
possibly  ..JDe_J±e-..j3bie£t__af__,appetite.  A  tendency  to 
nothing  is  no  tendency.  Hence  all  good  is  being, 
(ii.)  But  that  "  all  being  is  good  "  is  established  as 
follows  : — Every  object_cliiigs  to  *  its  own  being — that 
is,  it  resists  disruption  or  a^unihilajLion.,  A  diamond,  a 
plant,  and  aii  "ammar  all  tend  to  remain  in  being — that 
is,  they  resist  destruction.  If  they  did  not  cling  to  their 
own  being  there  would  be  no  sufficient  natural  reason 
why  they  should  continue  in  existence  once  they  are 
produced,  or  why  they  should  continue  to  exist  in  this 
or  that   species   once  they   are   produced  in   a   certain 

*  "  Ratio  enim  boni  in  hoc  consistit  quod  aliquid  sit  appetibile  .  .  . 
manifestum  est  autem  quod  unumquodque  est  appetibile  secundum 
quod  est  perfectum  nam  omnia  appetunt  suam  perfectfionem.  In 
tantum  est  autem  perfectum  unumquodque  in  quantum  est  actu. 
Unde  manifestum  est  quod  in  tantum  est  aliquid  bonum  in  quantum 
est  ens  ;  esse  enim  est  actualitas  omnis  rei  "  (St.  Thomas,  "  S.  Theol." 
I-)  Q-  v.,  Art.  i).  Again,  St.  Thomas  says — "  Bonum  non  addit 
aliquid  supra  ens  sed  rationem  tantum  appctibilis  et  perfcctionis  quod 
convenit  ipsi  esse  in  quacumque  natura  sit  "  (I.,  Q.  V.,  Art.  3). 

Again,  St.  Thomas  writes,  "  De  Vcritate,"  Q.  XXI.,  Art.  2 — "  Cum 
ratio  boni  in  hoc  consistat  quod  aliquid  sit  pcrfcctivum  alterius  per 
modum  finis  ;  omne  id  quod  invenitur  habere  rationem  finis  habot  ct 
rationem  boni.  Duo  autem  sunt  de  ratione  finis,  ut  sc.  sit  appelitum 
vcl  desideratum  ab  his  quae  finem  nondum  attingunt  aut  sit  delectum 
et  quasi  delectabile  ab  his  quae  finem  participant  ;  cum  ejusdcm 
rationis  est  tendere  in  finem  et  in  fine  quodammodo  quiesccre.  .  .  . 
Hacc  autem  duo  invcniuntur  competcre  ipsi  esse.  Quae  enim  esse 
nondum  participant,  in  esse,  quodam  naturali  appctitu,  tendunt  ; 
Omnia  autem  quae  jam  esse  habent  illud  esse  suum  naturaliter  amant 
ct  ipsum  tota  virtute  conservant.  .  .  .  Ipsum  igitur  esse  habet  ratio- 
nem lx)ni.  Unde  sicut  impo.s.sibile  est  quod  sit  aliquod  ens  quod  non 
habeat  cs.sc,  ita  neccsse  est  quod  omne  ens  sit  bonum  ex  hoc  ipso  quod 
esse  habet.  .  .  .  Cum  autem  Ix^num  rationem  entis  inchidat.  .  .  im- 
pos.sibile  est  aliquid  esse  lx)num  quod  non  .sit  ens  ;  ct  ita  rclinquitur 
quod  Ix>num  ct  ens  convertuntur." 

This  doctrine  that  everything  tends  to  the  conservation  of  its  own 
being  is  taught  expressly  by  many  modem  philosophers.  Of  living 
things  C8p<'cially  (liey  make  this  as.sertion.  Thus  M.  Guyau  writes — 
"  La  tendance  a  per.s6vd'rer  dans  la  vie  est  la  loi  n6ces.sairc  de  la  vie, 
non  sculcmcnt  die/  I'liomme  mais  chcz  tous  les  ftrcs  vivants."  But 
the  very  same  force  that  makes  the  plant  resist  the  destruction  of  its 
life  makes  even  an  inorganic  substance  resist  disruption  of  its  being — 
this  force  attaches  to  every  being. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  93 

species.     Hence  all  being  is  the.  pbject_ofji2gfijLiie-(M"-  of 
tendency,  at  least  -to  tlie'  thing  itself  which  is  actualised, 
which  has  the  being  in  question  ;   and  since  that  is  good 
which  is  the  object  of  appetite,  it  follows  that  all  beine;  x^' 
is  good  in  so  far  as  it  has  actuality  or  actual  being.      U 

(3)  The  good  is  as  such  an  attribute  of  reality  {bonum 
est  in  rebus).* 

We  now  come  to  a  third  point  in  our  determination 
of  the  "  good  " — the  good  is  as  such  an  attribute  of 
reality.  Whereas  the  "  true "  exists  in  and  belongs 
primarily  to  mind,  the  "  good,"  on  the  other  hand, 
essentially  includes  a  reference  to  real  existence,  since 
actuality  is  the  principle  of  good  in  all  being. 

No  object,  therefore,  is  good  or  can  become  an  object 
of  desire  except  in  so  far  as  it  either  has  or  is  supposed 
to  have  actuality.  An  economist  is  perfect  intellectually 
who  can  deal  properly  with  money  in  idea.  But  if  he 
desires  money  he  desires  it,  not  as  existing  in  idea  but 
as  existing  in  act — as  actual  or  real.  Therefore,  only  as 
real,  as  actual,  can  a  thing  become  an  end  of  desire 
Actual  being,  therefore — being  in  real  existence— is  the 
universal  form  of  all  objects  of  appetite,  and,  therefore(^/' 
of  all  good. 

(4)  "  Good  "  is  fulness  of  being. 

Though  "  good "  and  "  being "  are  one,  yet  not 
evefythffrgThat  has~being, "oF^tuality^  thereHy  good 
sim'pty~~dnd  abJbJuleJy'.  A  horse  may  have  good  sight, 
good  KearThg^^fhaf~is,  it  may  be  good  with  a  qualifica- 
tion (as  St.  Thomas  says),  but  it  is  not  simply  or  abso- 
lutely good—  i.e.,  it  is  not  a  good  horse  unless  it  has  all 
the  being  that  is  naturally  due  to  a  horse.  Foi:  all  ob- 
jects naturally  seek  the  perfection  that  is  proper  to  their 
nature,  and  if  they  do  not  come  toTheir  propeFperfec- 

*  "  Terminus  appetitus  quod  est  bonum  est  in  appetibili  ;  sed 
terminus  cognitionis  quod  est  verum  est  in  ipso  intellectu  "  ("  S. 
TheoL,"  I.,  (^.  XVI.,  Art.  i). 


04  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

tion  it  is  because  nature  has  been  prevented  from 
achieving  the  end  which,  given  the  proper  conditions, 
they  would  achieve.  The  good  of  an  object,  therefore, 
is  its  natural  perfection.  This  we  call  fulness  of  being. 
A  thing,  then,  has  fulness  of  being  and  is  absolutely 
good  when  it  has  all  the  natural  parts,  and  all  up  to 
nature's  standard.*  But  if  anything  is  wanting  in  any 
of  those  parts  that  are  naturally  due  to  it,  the  thing  is 
bad.  To  be  bad  it  is  not  necessary  that  everything  in 
an  object  should  be  bad.  It  is  enough  if  there  be 
any  falling  short  of  the  right  standard.  If  complete 
absence  of  good  were  necessary  before  we  could  speak 
of  an  object  as  bad,  it  would  be  impossible  that  we 
I  should  ever  speak  of  a  bad  object,  for  in  every  kind  of 
//  object  there  must  be  some  good,  some  actuality.  Hence, 
whereas  in  respect  of  degrees  of  goodness,  goodness  is 
of  two  kinds — relative  and  absolute— a  bad  object,  on 
the  other  hand,  can  never  be  corhpletely  bad,  and 
consequently  we  have  given  the  full  lyieaning  of  badness 
when  we  say  that  an  object  is  bad  or  falls  short  of  the 
natural  standard  in  any  degree  ;  and  for  that  reason 
we  speak  of  anything  in  which  there  is  some  want  as 
bad  (simply  and  without  qualification),  whereas  before 
we  speak  of  anything  as  good  (simply  and  without 
qualification)   we  require  that  it  be  all  good.     A  lame 

/horse  may  have  good  sight,  but  it  is  a  bad  horse  ;  it 
may  be  good  with  a  qualification,  but  we  do  not  speak 
of  it  as  good  simply — as  a  good  horse — on  the  contrary, 
we  speak  of  it  as  a  bad  horse  because  it  has  not  its 
natural  fulness  of  being.  Hence  the  formula,  "  Bonum 
ex  Integra  causa  — malum  ex  quocumque  defectu." 
S>/Hiiman  good  is  fulness  of  human  being.  As  we  have 
said,  a  being,  to  be  good,  must  have  all  its  natural  parts 

•  More  would  not  be  good.     We  do  not  look  for  beautiful  plumage 
in  a  horse,  nor  for  the  strength  of  a  stallion  in  the  dove. 
"  Ih  the  creature  too  imperfect,  say  ? 
Would  you  mend  it 
And  so  end  it 
Since  not  all  addition  perfects  aye  ?  " — Browning. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  95 

and  all  up  to  nature's  standard.  A  human  person, 
therefore,  to  be  good  must  have  all  the  parts  that 
belong  naturally  to  a  human  being,  and  all  up  to 
nature's  standard.  But  "  parts  "  are  of  many  kinds. 
There  are  integral  parts — e.g.,  hands,  feet,  and  head — 
ind  there  are  potential  parts,  or  faculties.  All  these 
parts,  integral  and  potential,  are  necessary  to  the  per- 
fect man. 

Now,  of  these  goods,  some  are  given  to  man  by  nature 
herself  from  the  beginning — for  instance,  hands  and  feet 
— while  some  are  acquired  by  operation.  But  of  these 
latter,  some  are  acquired  by  the  operation  of  nature, 
and  are  not  under  man's  control — e.g.,  the  digestion  of 
food — whilst  others  are  acquired  by  man's  own  effort 
and  activity,  e.g.,  eating,  reading,  the  acquirement  of 
learning.  Now  of  these  three  classes  of  goods  the  first 
two  have  no  right  to  be  regarded  as  part  of  the  subject- 
matter  of  Ethics.  Ethics  is  the  science  of  human  con- 
duct, and  it  treats  of  those  goods  that  are  won  by  our 
activities — that  is,  the  attainment  of  which  is  under  our 
control.  Ethics  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  goods 
which  nature  gives  us,  or  with  other  goods  in  so  far  as 
their  maintenance  depends  upon  the  operation  of  nature. 
It  has  to  do  with  the  human  act  as  controlled  by  us,  or 
with  what  is  acquired  by  human  effort.  Only  such 
things  are  morally  good. 

(5)  The  goodness  or  fulness  of  being  of  the  human  act 
depends  principally  upon  its  object  or  end. 

All  the  faculties  of  man  relate  to  objects  or  ends, 
either  external  or  internal.  Their  use  consists  in  the 
attainment  of  their  objects — their  right  use  or  the  ful- 
ness of  being  proper  to  the  human  act,  consists  in  the 
attainment  of  the  right  or  proper  objects  or  ends.  And 
when  we  speak  of  the  end  it  must  not  be  thought  that 

♦  "S.  Thcol.,"  I.,  II.,  Q.  XVIII.,  Art.  2. 


96  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

we  refer  exclusively  to  the  remote  purpose  of  our  act. 
By  end  we  here  mean  any  object  on  which  is  engaged 
any  faculty  employed  in  our  act.  In  a  single  act  these 
may  be  many  and  various.  In  stealing,  for  instance,  the 
object  of  the  external  act  is  another  man's  money.  The 
object  of  the  internal  act  of  the  will  includes  both  this 
and  any  further  purpose  at  which  we  aim  in  stealing 
{finis  operantis).  All  these  are  objects  and  designate 
our  act.  Considering  the  external  element  of  taking 
money  our  act  is  one  of  stealing  :  considering  the  purely 
internal  element  it  is  one  of  avarice  or  hatred  or  some- 
thing else.  Usually,  however,  in  designating  the  object 
of  the  human  act  it  is  to  the  internal  desire  as  externated 
that  we  chiefly  refer  and  that  to  which  it  refers  is  spoken 
of  as  object ;  our  further  purely  internal  purpose  is 
called  the  end.  In  the  present  paragraph,  however,  we 
speak  of  object  and  end  indifferently — as  anything  to 
which  a  faculty  is  directed.  In  this  sense  we  say  that 
the  object  or  end  specifies  the  act.* 

But  though  the  goodness  of  conduct  consists  essen- 
tially in  its  end,  there  are  other  elements  in  conduct 
which  contribute  to  its  goodness — viz.,  the  circumstances 
of  conduct.  An  act  may  want  "  due  quantity  according 
to  Reason,  due  place,  or  anything  of  that  sort,"  and  an 
act  is  good  or  evil  by  reference  to  all  these  things. 
However,  it  is  worthy  of  remark  that  it  is  the  end  that 
determines  the  proper  circumstances,  just  as  it  is  the 
ends  which  a  man  wishes  to  gain  that  determine  whether 
a  movement  ought  to  be  fast  or  slow.  And  so  we  say 
that  the  fulness  of  being  of  a  human  action  is  determined 
by  its  end. 

*  The  conception  of  moral  goodness  is  thus  seen  to  be  a  develop- 
ment from  that  of  metaphysical  goodness  or  goodness  as  identical 
with  being.  The  series  of  conceptions  given  in  the  text  may  be  briefly 
represented  as  follows  : — the  good  as  being,  as  fulness  of  being,  as 
fulness  of  natural  being,  as  fulness  of  natural  human  being  :  the 
moral  good  will  consist  of  fulness  of  such  part  of  our  natural  human 
being  as  is  acquired  by  human  ellort  and  controlled  by  Keason  and 
what  is  natural  in  it  will  be  determined  chiefly  by  the  natural  objects 
oi  our  faculties. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  97 

(6)  The  good  of  human  conduct  is  determined  by  the 

final  end. 

A  movement  or  tendency  may  have  many  ends,  ac 
when  a  man  desires  to  get  m.oney  in  order  to  help  the 
poor,  so  that  by  helping  the  poor  he  may  acquire  a  good 
name.  But  the  dominant  end  of  anything  is  its  final 
end.  Consequently,  as  we  pointed  out  in  the  beginning 
of  this  chapter,  that  conduct  which  does  not  lead  us  to 
our  final  end  is  a  failure  and  bad,  no  matter  what  inter- 
mediate ends  we  may  succeed  in  attaining  by  means  of 
it.  Since,  therefore,  moral  science  treats  of  the  goodness 
or  badness  of  human  conduct,  and  since  the  principal 
goodness  or  fulness  of  being  that  is  proper  to  a  human 
act  is  its  direction  to  the  end,  and  since  the  final  end  is 
the  end  [Tf-KuoraTov  rovrm),  we  may  define  a  good 
moral  action  as  "  action  done  under  the  control  of 
'Reason  and  leading  to  man's  final  end."  ♦ 


(6)  Of    the     Moral    Determinants — or    of    those 
Things  that  make  an  Act  Good  or  Evil 

Let  us  on  account  of  its  importance,  resume  what  we 
said  in  our  last  section  on  the  different  elements  con- 
tributing to  morality  in  the  human  act.  7^£  moral 
determinants  of  an  action  are  all  those  tjungs  that  go^to 
make  ajLaction  good  or  evil,  better  or  worse.     The  prin- 


cipal moral  determinants  enumerated  by  the  scholastics) 
are  three — tjie  object, f  the  end^  and  the  circumstancegjL 

•  We  repeat,  however,  our  statement  already  made  and  which 
will  be  proved  later,  that  it  is  through  an  examination  of  our  natural 
constitution  that  we  determine  what  acts  are  suitable  and  lead  to 
the  final  end. 

I  By  "  object  "  here  we  mean  the  object  of  the  action — that  is, 
of  the  whole  action  which,  we  here  assume,  is  an  external  act.  By 
"  end  "  here  is  meant  the  finis  operantis,  or  the  purpose  which  we 
wish  to  accomplish  by  our  act.  Both  of  these  are  included  in  what 
was  before  spoken  of  as  "  the  end  of  the  will  "  which  we  identified 
with  the  good,  for  the  will  takes  in  the  whole  thing  desired,  including, 
therefore,  both  object  and  that  to  whigh  our  action  is  meant  finally 
to  lead  {finis  operantis). 

Vol.  1—7 


98  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

These  determinants  may  be  more  easily  understood  from 
an  example  than  by  their  definition.  We  shall  take  as 
our  example  the  case  of  a  complete  human  act  having 
an  inner  and  an  outer  element.  In  murder  the  act 
whose  morality  is  in  question  is  the  act  of  killing.  The 
object — that  is,  the  formal  moral  object  of  this  act — is  a 
person  over  whom  I  have  no  authority — someone  who 
is  not  subject  to  me.  The  circumstances  are  that  I  do 
the  deed  at  such  a  time,  place,  &c.  The  end  is  that 
which  I  purpose  gaining  by  the  act — for  instance,  satis- 
faction for  some  wrong  or  the  obtaining  of  money. 

The  object  is  the  specifically  moral  factor  in  all  acts. 
It  is  that  which  specifies  the  act,  which  gives  it  a  name 
and  puts  it  in  a  class.  Thus  to  destroy  the  life  of  another 
is  homicide.  To  take  the  goods  of  another  is  stealing — 
that  is,  these  acts  are  put  by  their  respective  objects  into 
a  particular  moral  species,  to  which  we  attach  a  par- 
ticular name.  It  is  with  the  consideration  of  the  objects 
of  acts,  therefore,  that  the  Science  of  Ethics  is  princi- 
pally concerned.  For  it  is  through  the  consideration  of 
objects  that  the  code  of  general  laws  is  Qonstructed. 
which  to  Ethics  are  what  the  general  physical  laws  are 
to  Physics.  \ 

Now,  if  the  object  of  an  act  is  bad  the  act  itself  is 
bad  ;  but  if  the  object  is  good  the  act  may  still  not  be 
good,  for  we  have  still  to  consider  the  circumstances 
and  the  end  or  the  finis  operantis. 

The  circumstances.  In  every  individual  act,  besides 
the  specific  moral  character  which  depends  on  object, 
there  is  also  an  individual  moral  character  which  de- 
pends on  circumstances.  Thus,  it  is  worse  to  murder 
one's  father  than  to  murder  a  stranger,  and  worse  to 
steal  ten  pounds  than  five.  Now,  an  act  should  be 
good  not  only  in  its  object  but  in  its  circumstances. 
For  morality  denotes,  as  we  have  already  seen,  a 
certain  fulness  of  being,  and  to  have  fulness  of  being 
means,  not  merely  to  be  in  a  certain  species,  but  to  have 
suitable    individual    characteristics    as    well.     So     the 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  99 

individual  moral  act  has  its  circumstances  as  well  as  its 
object,  which  should  all  be  good.  Still,  not  every  cir- 
cumstance counts  in  the  morality  of  the  act.  And  of 
those  that  do  count  some  only  increase  or  diminish  the 
morality,  as  in  the  examples  given,  whilst  others  add  on 
a  specifically  new  moral  relation  to  that  which  results 
from  the  object.  Thus  to  steal  six  pounds  is  only  worse 
than  to  steal  five  ;  but  to  kill  a  father  is  not  only  homi- 
cide but  patricide.  The  fact  that  this  is  one's  father 
adds  on  a  specifically  new  crime.* 

How  the  circumstances  affect  the  morality  of  an  act. 

The  circumstances  give  rise  to  a  twofold  law  in  action  : 
(a)  first,  a  negative  law — there  must  be  no  bad  circum- 
stance ;  (b)  second,  a  positive  law — every  circumstance 
that  is  necessary  for  the  due  performance  of  the  act — 
that  is,  for  the  attainment  of  the  natural  end  of  action 
— must  be  present,  else  the  act  is  not  good.  Now,  in 
regard  to  this  second  point,  it  is  to  be  noted  that  some- 
times the  attainment  of  the  natural  end  of  an  act  does 
not  depend  wholly  on  that  which  the  agoit  does,  nor 
does  it  follow  immediately  on  the  performance  of  his 
action,  but  requires  along  with  the  action  of  the  agent 
a  subsequent  process  also  with  which  the  agent  has 
nothing  to  do,  and  which  depends  altogether  on  nature. 
Now,  in  such  cases,  provided  that  all  the  circumstances 
necessary  for  the  due  performance  of  our  own  share  of 
the  act  are  present,  the  act  is  lawful,  and  it  is  lawful 
even  though  nature  should  afterwards  fail  in  the  work 
proper  to  her,  thus  preventing  the  accomplishment  of 
the  natural  end.  Thus  the  use  of  matrimony  is  lawful 
even  though  one  of  the  parties  happens  to  be  sterile. 
The  natural  end  fails  to  be  accomplished.  ,-'fiut  for  that 
the  parties  are  not  responsible. 

*  The  scholastics  give  the  following  rough  enumeration  ot  the 
principal  determinants — quis,  quid  (the  effect),  ubi,  qitibus  auxiliis, 
cur,  qitomodo,  quando. 


TOO  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

The  end  aimed  at  {finis  opcrantis  *)  is  the  original 
source  of  the  whole  act,  for  the  act  that  we  do,  with 
its  object  and  its  circumstances,  is  nothing  more  than 
means  to  the  realisation  of  the  end  aimed  at.  And  as 
a  man  intends  the  end  more  than  the  means,  so  the 
end  is  in  one  sense  the  principal  moral  element  in  the 
act.  Still  the  object  and  circumstances  have  their  own 
morality  apart  from  the  end  aimed  at,  and  unless  the 
object  and  circumstances  are  good  the  act  is  bad  in 
spite  of  the  fact  that  the  end  aimed  at  may  be  most 
praiseworthy.  This  is  expressed  by  sa3'ing  that  the 
end  does  not  justify  the  means.  By  the  means  we  wish 
to  signify  all  that  we  do  in  order  to  attain  our  end.  A 
good  end  could  not  justify  an  act  or  a  means  which  is 
in  itself  bad. 

Hence  to  take  a  bad  means  to  a  bad  end  is  to  commit 
two  crimes,  whilst  to  take  a  bad  means  to  a  good  end  or 
a  good  means  to  a  bad  end  is  one  crime. 

NOTE  ON   THE   QUESTION   OF  MOR.ALLY   INDIFFERENT   ACTS 

A  question  of  very  great  importance  in  the  Science  of 
Ethics  is  whether  there  can  be  such  a  thing  as  a  morally 
indifferent  act,  or  whether  all  deliberate  human  acts  are 
either  morally  good  or  morally  bad.  Some,  with  Scotus, 
maintain  that  acts  may  be  indifferent,  and  not  only  in  specie, 
t.e.,  considered  in  the  abstract,  or  apart  from  the  individual 
circumstances,  but  also  in  individuo,  or  having  regard  to 
the  circumstances  also.  St.  Thomas  Aquinas,  on  the  other 
hand,  contends  that  whereas  in  specie  an  act  may  be 
indifferent,  in  individuo  it  cannot  be  indifferent  but  must 
be  either  morally  good  or  bad.  This  latter  is  the  view  which 
commends  itself  to  us,  and  we  shall  devote  the  present  text- 
note  to  establishing  its  truth.  >.   i^^. 

That  acts  may  be  morally  indifferent  considcrccl'tn  specie, 
or  apart  from  the  individual  circumstances,  is  self-evident, 
and,  so  far  as  we  are  aware,  is  also  undisputed.  To  lift  up  a 
stone  from  the  earth,  to  look  around,  to  move  the  finger, 
arc  in  thetnsi-lves  ncithcT  good  nor  evil,  for,  in  themselves, 

•  The  end  aimed  at,  though  part  of  the  object  of  the  inner  will,  is 
the  principal  circumstance  in  relation  to  the  external  act.  Thus  the 
end  aimed  at  (for  instance,  riches  or  rovcngc)  is  a  circumstance  of  the 
act  of  stealing. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  loi 

they  neither  help  nor  retard  one's  perfection  in  any  way. 
Such  acts  may  be  either  good  or  bad/according  to  the  cir- 
cumstances in,  and  particular!}'  the /intention  with  which 
we  do  them. 

Our  teaching  in  regard  to  the  indi-Oidual  act  will  be  divided 
into  two  parts.  We  shall  show  {a)  that  without  considering 
the  end  aimed  at  by  the  agent,  and  attending  merely  to  the 
object  and  other  circumstances,  the  individual  act  is  nearly 
always  either  good  or  bad  ;  (6)  that  when  the  end  aimed  at 
is  taken  into  account,  the  individual  act  is  seen  to  be  nlivays 
either  good  or  bad — it  can  never  be  indilfcrent.* 

(a)  Every  human  act  involves  the  exercise  of  a  man's 
inner  powers,  physical  and  mental,  and  every  exercise  of 
the  inner  powers  of  an  organism  affects  that  organism  well 
or  ill  in  relation  to  its  natural  perfection.  Anything,  e.g., 
that  affects  the  nutritive  action  of  a  tree  in  any  way,  affects 
it  for  good  or  evil.  Anything  that  accelerates  or  retards 
the  circulation  of  the  blood  either  impairs  or  benefits  the 
animal  in  some  way.  So  also  man  is  affected  well  or  ill  by 
each  human  act.f  In  the  cases  just  mentioned  not  every 
element  present  may  affect  the  organism  well  or  ill,  but 
sometliing  will  practically  always  be  present,  as  we  know 
from  experience,  so  to  affect  it. 

The  following  calculation  may  give  us  a  clearer  notion  of 
the  same  conclusion,  and  perhaps  also  the  reason  why  it  is 
so  difficult  to  perform  an  act  which  will  be  purely  indifferent. 
If  each  of  the  circumstances  that  go  to  make  up  the  act  and 
also  the  object  of  the  act  may  be  either  good,  bad  or  indifferent, 
the  chances  are  very  small  that  all  together  will  belong  to 
the  indifferent  category.  If  there  are  seven  circumstances 
the  chance  that  they  and  the  object  will  be  indifferent  is 
represented  by  the  fraction  "  one  "  divided  by  "  tfiree  to 
the  power  eight,"  which  is  a  very  small  chance  indeed. 
Now  whereas  an  act  is  bad  if  any  element  in  it  is  bad,  and 
good  if  there  is  one  good  element  provided  all  the  others  are 
at  least  indifferent,  +  to  be  morally  indifferent  an  act  should 

*  The  distinction  between  '  a  '  and  '  b  '  above  is  suggested  by  St. 
Thomas'  words  :  "  oportet  quod  quilibet  actus  habet  aliquam  cir- 
cumstantiam  per  quam  trahatur  ad  bonum  vel  malum,  ad  minus 
(italics  ours)  ex  parte  intentionis  finis." 

t  Acts  that  relate  to  Society  are  as  little  likely  to  be  indifferent 
as  those  that  affect  indivitluals.  We  can  scarcely  imagine  any  bill 
passing  into  law  that  would  not  benefit  or  injure  society  in  some  way. 

X  An  act  may  be  good  in  spite  of  innumerable  indifferent  elements. 
If  everything  in  a  good  act  should  be  good  a  good  act  would  be  im- 
possible since  in  every  good  act  there  are  some  indifferent  circumstances. 


102  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

be  indifferent  in  every  particular.     And  therefore  very  few 
acts  can  be  morally  indifferent. 

(6)  Let  us  now  take  up  the  second  point  of  view  that, 
viz.,  of  the  end  aimed  at.  Taking  this  element  into  account 
it  becomes  clear  that  not  only  nearly  every  act  but  every 
act,  provided  it  is  deliberate,  is  either  morally  good  or  bad, 
and  that  therefore  none  can  be  indifferent.  An  act  that 
is  indifferent  in  its  circumstances  and  its  object  will,  we 
claim,  be  made  good  by  at  least  one  element,  an  element 
that  is  present  in  every  act,  viz.,  that  it  is  directed  by  the 
will  to  the  final  end.  Any  act  is  morally  good  which  is 
deliberate,  and  which  leads  to  the  final  end.  Now,  we  are 
at  present  considering  only  deliberate  acts  and  we  know  that 
the  will  must  always  desire  the  final  end,  i.e.,  it  is  necessitated 
by  its  own  inner  nature  to  desire  this  end.  What  is  sought 
is  sought  as  leading  to  the  final  end.  Provided  therefore 
that  there  is  no  bad  element  in  the  act,  that  all  else  is  in- 
different, this  direction  of  our  act  to  the  final  end  suffices 
of  itself  to  confer  on  it  the  character  of  goodness,  and  makes 
of  an  act  otherwise  morally  indifferent  a  morally  good  act. 
"  The  mere  fact,"  *  writes  St.  Thomas,  "  that  we  refer  a 

*  "  S.  Theol."  I.  II*  xix.  7,  "  ordo  ad  finem  consideratur  ut  ratio 
quaedam  bonitatis  ipsius  voliti." 

Two  difficulties  have  to  be  considered  here  (a)  in  a  bad  act  the 
will  tends  to  the  final  end  ;  yet  the  act  is  not  thereby  rendered  good. 
Why  should  the  same  tendency  of  the  will  render  an  act  good  which 
is  otherwise  indifferent. 

We  reply,  first,  the  direction  of  the  will  to  the  final  end  is  an  element 
of  goodness  even  in  a  bad  act.  There  is  no  act  that  is  wholly  bad. 
Such  direction  of  the  will  must  also  constitute  an  clement  of  goodness 
in  the  case  of  an  act  otherwise  indifferent.  On  the  other  hand  this 
element  of  goodness  does  not  bring  a  bad  act  into  the  category  of 
good  acts,  since  an  act  is  bad  if  it  contains  any  bad  element,  whereas 
it  can  bring  an  act  otherwise  indifferent  into  the  category  of  good 
acts  because  for  goodness  one  good  clement  suffices  provided  there  is 
no  bad  element. 

Secondly,  the  bad  element  in  a  bad  act  fnistrates  the  effort  of  the 
will  to  refer  it  to  the  final  end — the  bad  element  is  simply  non-reieniMe. 
We  shall  explain  by  mcins  of  an  analogy.  Any  indiflerent  si,i;ii  or 
act,  e.g.  touching  the  hat  may  be  made  a  means  of  friendly  salutation 
provided  we  direct  it  to  that  end  (C)rdo  ad  finem  etc.,  as  above).  But 
no  intention  of  ours  could  make  a  blow  in  the  face  an  act  of  friendly 
salutation.  The  unfriendly  element  intrinsic  to  such  an  act  would 
frustrate  the  intention  of  our  will.  So,  the  bad  element  in  a  bad  act 
frustrates  the  will's  effort  to  diri-rt  it  to  the  final  end.  This  is  not 
the  case  with  an  act  containing  no  bad  element. 

(h)  The  s<!Cond  dKlficuKy  is  tin?  following — to  be  morally  good  an 
act  should  Ixr  free  ;  but  the  only  good  element  in  the  act  referred  to 
in  i\ur  U'xt  is  not  free.  The  desin-  of  the  will  for  the  (inal  end  is  not 
free.     Therefore   an   act  indifferent   in    every   other   resj)ect   though 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  103 

thing  desired  to  some  (good)  end  confers  upon  that  thing  a 
certain  goodness  ;  as,  for  instance,  if  a  man  were  to  fast  in 
God's  honour  (propter  Deum)  his  fast  would  become  through 
this  very  fact  (ex  hoc  ipso)  a  good  thing."  But  the  ultimate 
end  is  par  excellence  the  good  end.  Every  act  therefore  in 
which  there  is  no  evil  element  becomes  a  good  act  by  virtue 
of  its  being  done  for  the  final  end." 

But  though  we  have  said  that  apparently  indifferent  acts 
like  lifting  a  straw  or  moving  one's  finger  are  made  good  at 
least  by  their  being  directed  to  the  final  end,  we  wish  it  to 
be  understood  that  we  are  far  from  claiming  that  this  is 
their  only  title  to  goodness.  On  the  contrary,  such  trifling 
acts  as  lifting  a  straw  are  good,  as  a  rule,  on  another  title 
also — that,  viz.,  of  the  proximate  end  aimed  at  {finis  operantis), 
which  end  is  often  no  other  than  the  object  of  some  funda- 
mental natural  appetite.  These  appetites  and  their  deriva- 
tives are  very  many  :  they  often  move  us  to  act ;  and  their 
ends  often  constitute  the  true  purpose  of  what  we  do,  even 
when  we  are  not  aware  that  any  such  motive  is  present. 
In  other  words  when  a  man  lifts  a  straw  from  the  ground  he 
does  so,  not  for  nothing,  but  either  for  exercise  or  from 
curiosity  {i.e.,  for  knowledge),  or  to  escape  the  ennui  of 
inactivity,  etc.,  all  of  which  are  either  objects  of  natural 
appetites,  or  derivatives  from  them.  The  act  is  prompted 
by  and  satisfies  some  natural  appetite,  and,  the  end  of  these 
appetites  being  natural,  the  act  which  promotes  them  is 
good.  "  Even  the  most  trifling  acts,"  says  St.  Thomas, 
"  though  not  ordained  to  any  extrinsic  end  are  yet  ordained 
to  the  good  of  the  individual  inasmuch  as  they  delight  him 
and  satisfy  his  desires  (sunt  requiem  praestantes),"  * 

If.  however,  there  are  some  acts  which  are  wanting  in 


rendered  good  by  one's  desire  for  the  final  end,  cannot  through  this 
fact  be  rendered  morally  good.  We  answer^ — an  act  which  is  in  itself 
free  can  be  taken  out  of  the  indifferent  category  and  made  good  by 
any  good  circumstance,  that  is  any  circumstance  that  helps  to  our 
natural  perfection  even  though  such  circumstance  be  not  free.  In 
fact  it  is  very  rarely  that  these  circumstances  though  contributing  much 
to  the  goodness  of  the  human  ret  are  free.  An  act  is  brought  into  the 
moral  sphere,  i.e.  is  capable  of  becoming  either  morally  good  or  morally 
bad  if  it  is  itself  free  ;  and,  if  such  an  act  is  made  to  promote  our 
natural  perfection  through  the  presence  of  any  circumstance,  whether 
this  circumstance  is  free  or  not,  our  act  is  brought  into  the  category 
of  good  acts  thereby,  just  as  freely  falling  in  battle  is  not  only  patriotic 
but  meritorious  even  though  the  love  of  country  which  inspires  our 
act  is  not  free  but  a  necessary  and  irresistible  habit  of  our  will. 

*  "  S.  Theol.,"  I.  11=^.  I.  6.     It  is  the  objects  of  appetite  that  bring 
it  to  rest  [requiem  praestantes). 


104  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

such  motives  as  \vc  have  just  mentioned,  even  these  acts 
are  caught  up  by  our  ever-present  desire  for  the  final  end, 
and  if,  otherwise  without  evil,  arc  made  good  by  that  desire.* 


(c)  That  there  is  a  Natural  Distinction  of  Good 
AND  Evil 

Having  shown  that  the  goodness  of  the  human  act 
is  its  tendency  to  the  objects  of  the  appetites,  we  now 
go  on  to  show. that  there  is  a  natural  distinction  of  good 
and  evil,  that  good  and  evil  are  not  arbitrary,  that  they 
do  not  change  according  to  our  passing  whims  and 
desires,  that  some  things  are  always  good,  and  some 
always  evil.  Our  proof  of  this  proposition  must  mani- 
festly consist  in  showing  that  man  is  possessed  of  certain 
permanent  natural  appetites,  of  appetites  that  are  not 
of  his  own  making  but  belong  inseparably  to  his  human 
nature  as  heart  and  head  and  hands  belong  to  his 
physical  constitution.  If  we  shall  succeed  in  establish- 
ing the  existence  of  natural  appetites  in  man  with  I 
natural  objects,  we  shall  also  have  succeeded  in  estab- 
lishing the  existence  of  natural  moral  distinctions. 

Now,t  before  proceeding  to  discuss  this  question  of 
the  existence  in  man  of  natural  appetites,  it  may  be 
useful  to  enquire  why  some  ethicians,  whilst  admitting 
that  man  is  possessed  of  natural  capacities  and  appetites, 
still  refuse  to  recognise  the  existence  of  a  natural  dis- 
tinction of  moral  good  and  evil.     The  reason,  it  seems 

•  Thus  the  same  bountiful  economy  of  nature  which  is  observable 
in  the  physical  world  is  found  to  extend  to  the  moral  as  well.  Nature 
will  herself  brinj^  the  plant  to  perfection  if  no  impediment  is  placed  to 
her  work.  In  the  same  way  every  human  act  is  made  to  lead  to  our 
final  end  provided  no  impediment  is  placed  in  nature's  way. 

f  Wc  are  here  dealin^^  with  one  of  the  mo.st  important  problems 
of  ethical  science  The  theory  that  there  are  no  natural  distinctions 
of  good  and  evil  has  been  variously  expres.sed.  Sometimes  it  is  claimed 
that  good  and  evil  are  mere  imagination,  .as  in  the  phra.se  ; — nothin;^ 
is  good  or  bad  but  our  inuiKination  makes  it  so.  .Mmost  identical 
with  this  theory  is  tlie  vi<'w  that  all  morality  is  relative  to  the  individual, 
as  in  Albany's  remark  (in  King  Lear)  "  wisdom  and  goodness  to  the 
vile  seem  vile."  So  also  wc  have  "  to  the  pure  mind  everything  is 
pure." 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  105 

to  us,  is  that  many  philosophers  who  are  not  of  the 
Aristotehan  tradition  have  been  accustomed  to  regard 
the  "  moral  good "  as  something  quite  distinct  from 
objects  of  natural  appetition,  as  something  mystical  and 
ethereal,  as  an  ideal  rather  than  a  reality  of  our  human 
nature  ;  and  so  morality  comes  to  be  identified  rather 
with  the  suppression  of  desire  than  with  its  exercise, 
with  the  restrictions  imposed  by  external  admonition 
and  law  rather  than  with  ordinary  human  liking  and 
disliking. 

Now,  this  is  not  the  view  of  moral  goodness  adopted 
in  the  present  work,  and  we  have  shown  that  it  is  not 
the  true  view.  The  good  is,  as  we  have  shown,  the 
object  of  appetite,  and  provided  an  appetite  comes  within 
the  control  of  Reason  and  is  directed  to  the  ultimate  end, 
the  attainment  of  its  natural  object  is  a  moral  good.  Thus, 
even  eating  and  conversation  may  be  morally  good  in 
the  same  sense  that  almsgiving  or  any  other  lofty  and 
unselfish  act  is  morally  good,  provided  only  that  they 
be  free  acts  and  directed  by  our  intellects  to  the  final 
end.  The  "  moral  good,"  therefore,  is  not  a  mystic  or 
ethereal  something,  but  simply  the  object  of  appetite  as 
directed  by  Reason,  and  hence,  if  there  be  natural  appe- 
tites controllable  by  Reason,  there  must  also  be  natural 
distinctions  of  good  and  evil. 

Let  us,  then,  first  determine  the  various  kinds  of 
appetite.  "By  appetite  we  mean  any  tendency,  move-/ 
ment,  or  inclination  to  the  attaining  of  an  end.^  Now, 
appetites  may  incline  to  ends  in  many  ways,  either  con- 
sciously or  unconsciously  ;  vitally— that  is,  as  a  result 
of  living  forces — or  non-vitally.  The  animal's  desire  for 
food  is  a  conscious  inclination.  The  tendency  of  the 
tree  to  flower  is  unconscious.  Assimilation  and  growth 
are  vital  tendencies.  Gravitation  and  the  tendency  of  a 
crystal  or  of  iron  to  exhibit  certain  properties  of  colour, 
form,  and  weight  are  non-vital  tendencies.  But  any 
tendency,  conscious  or  unconscious,  vital  or  non-vital, 
is  what   we  mean   by   appetite.     When   such  tendency 


io6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

springs  out  of  the  essence  of  an  object  and  is  not  the 
result  of  accident  or  of  some  mere  passing  desire  the 
appetite  is  spoken  of  as  natural. 

Now,  without  attempting  a  complete  enumeration  of 
the  appetites,  we  may  give  here  what  we  consider  their 
principal  division.  We  divide  appetites,  following  St. 
Thomas  Aquinas,  into  two  classes — physical  *  and 
psychical  or  cognitive.  Physical  appetites  are  those 
that  spring  immediately  out  of  the  nature  of  a  thing 
and  have  no  dependence  on  knowledge.  Psychical 
appetites  are  those  which,  though  possibly  grounded 
in  nature,  yet  depend  on  and  proceed  from  knowledge. 
Nutrition  and  growth  are  physical  appetites.  The  love 
of  wine  is  psychical. 

A  few  prominent  instances  of  these  two  classes  of 
appetites  will  suffice  to  show  their  diversity  and 
character,  and  how  the  nature  of  the  appetite  in  each 
case  depends  upon  the  kind  of  being  to  which  it  be- 
longs. Of  physical  appetites  the  first  and  principal  is 
the  tendency  of  every  being  to  maintain  its  own 
existence.  Of  this  appetite  we  have  already  spoken  in 
the  present  chapter. f  Secondly,  every  object  besides 
tending  to  maintain  itself  in  being  tends  also  to  the 
exercise  of  some  proper  and  necessary  operation— that 
is,  some  operation  that  not  only  accords  with,  but  is 
determined    by,    the    proper     nature    of    the    object. 

*  St.  Thomas'  word  "  naturalis  "  is  here  translated  by  "  physical." 
By  "  naturalis  "  St.  Thomas  means  here  not  what  accords  willi  or 
even  what  is  grounded  in  nature  but  what  springs  out  of  nature  without 
any  dependence  on  cognition.  This  we  prefer  to  express  by  the  word 
"  physical,"  in  order  to  avoid  the  ambiguities  attendant  on  the  word 
"  natural,"  which  is  so  often  used  in  this  work  in  its  more  connnon 
signification  of  "  according  with  "  or  "  being  grounded  in  nature." 
"  Physical  "  here  then,  does  not  mean  material,  but,  as  the  text  ex- 
plains, "any  natural  appelition  which  has  no  dependence  on  cog- 
nition." 

t  Several  appetites,  like  that  for  our  own  continued  existence, 
though  physical  and  present  even  in  unconscious  and  unorganised 
things,  may  yet  in  the  case  of  conscious  beings  take  on  a  conscious 
and  psychic  character  also.  We  seek  our  own  maintenance  not  only 
as  suDstantivc  Innings,  and  therefore  unconsciously,  but  also  us  rational 
beings  and  knowingly. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  107 

Minerals,  for  instance,  tend  to  assume  a  certain  form 
of  structure, .  to  possess  certain  chemical  affinities  to 
other  substances,  to  exhibit  a  certain  colour,  and 
(under  particular  conditions)  a  certain  weight  ;  plants 
tend  to  send  out  leaf  and  flower  ;  the  lungs  have  a 
necessary  tendency  to  breathe,  the  heart  to  beat,  the 
eye  to  see.*  The  vegetative  appetites  of  nutrition 
and  growth  are  also  physical.  Given  the  materials  of 
nutrition  and  growth  the  exercise  of  these  appetites 
must  follow,  and  independently  of  cognition. 

Of  psychical  appetites  there  are  two  kinds,  sensuous 
and  intellectual,  according  as  the  knowledge  from 
which  the  appetite  proceeds  is  sensuous  or  intellectual. 
In  animals  the  love  of  the  sexes,  the  desire  for  food  and 
for  the  preservation  of  offspring,  are  sensuous  psychic 
appetites.  In  man  these  same  appetites  are  radically 
sensuous,  but  these  sensuous  appetites  may  also  take 
on,  in  so  far  as  they  come  under  the  control  of  Reason, 
a  rational  character,  and  are,  properly  speaking,  rational 
appetites.  But  there  are  some  appetites  that  are  not 
radically  sensuous ;  for  instance,  the  appetite  for 
society,  t  which,  though  it  has  its  analogue  amongst 
certain  animal  tribes,  is  yet  itself  a  purely  rational 
appetite  ;  also  the  appetite  for  progress  in  knowledge, 
and  the  will's  desire  for  the  good-in-general. 

The  question  now  arises — Are  any  of  these  appetites 
natural  ^  That  the  ph3'sical  appetites  are  natural,  few 
indeed  would  be  disposed  to  doubt,  and,  therefore,  it 
will  not  be  necessary  to  give  them  any  special  promi- 
nence here.     The   physical  appetites  could  be  nothing 

•  The  tendency  of  the  eye  to  see  or  of  the  ear  to  hear  when  their 
proper  objects  are  presented  to  them  is  a  physical  appetite.  It  pre- 
cedes and  is  one  of  the  causes  of  knowledge — it  does  not  itself  depend 
on  knowledge.  Every  faculty,  whether  primarily  appetitive  or  not 
has  a  nisus  to  the  exercise  of  its  own  act,  which  nisus  or  appetite  is 
unconscious  in  every  case. 

t  By  human  society  we  mean  not  mere  gregarious  living  such  as 
many  animals  de.sire,  but  the  human  social  life  with  all  those  purely 
human  conditions  which  shall  be  described  later  in  our  chapter  on 
Society. 


io8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

else  than  natural,  since,  having  no  dependence  on  know- 
ledge, there  is  nothing  else  from  which  they  can  spring 
but  nature.  The  colour  of  gold,  the  texture  of  wood, 
the  cohesive  tendencies  of  atoms,  are  all  natural  pro- 
perties, and  tendencies  to  exhibit  these  properties  are 
all  natural  appetites.  Also  the  tendencies  of  plants  to 
grow,  of  the  lungs  to  breathe,  of  the  eye  to  see,  are 
natural.  They  spring  out  of  the  nature  of  the  human 
organism  since  there  is  nothing  else  by  which  they  could 
be  caused. 

Our  question,  therefore,  relates  principally  to  the 
psychical  appetites  which,  since  they  depend  on  know- 
ledge, may  give  rise  to  the  question  whether  they  could 
not,  like  the  thirst  for  alcohol,  have  grown  up  in  indi- 
viduals through  accidents  of  environment,  of  bodily  com- 
plexion, or  of  habit,  and  whether,  therefore,  they  are  not 
an  acquirement  rather  than  an  original  part  of  our 
natural  human  constitution.  It  is  fitting,  too,  that  we 
should  confine  our  enquiry  to  these  psychic  appetites, 
since  the  physical  appetites  are  not  in  the  control  of 
Reason,  and  consequently  they  cannot  give  rise  to 
distinctions  of  moral  good  and  evil. 

Proof  that  some  psychical  appetites  are  natural. 

(i)  Our  first  and  obvious  argument  is  that  there  are 
certain  objects  to  which  all  men  tend  in  common  (to 
some  of  these,  indeed,  they  tend  in  common  with  all 
animals) — e.g.,  there  is  the  appetite  for  life,  for  food, 
the  love  of  the  sexes,  the  appetite  for  knowledge  and 
for  society.  Now,  just  as  we  infer  that  a  certain  limb 
is  natural,  and  that  such  and  such  is  the  natural  organic 
form  of  anything  because  these  things  are  found  in  all 
the  individuals  of  a  species,  so  also  should  we  infer  that 
an  appetite  which  is  possessed  by  all  n)en,  more  particu- 
larly if  it  be  possessed  by  all  or  practically  all  animals 
also,  is  natural  to  man — that  is,  is  :m  original  part  of 
liJH   nafin"<'  and  conslilntjon,  and   in  in.st^parablc  from  his 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  109 

nature.     We    claim,     therefore,    that     some    psychical 
appetites  are  natural. 

Now,  some  persons  may  not  admit  the  premiss  which 
in  the  foregoing  argument  we  have  taken  for  granted  as 
self-evident — that  an  appetite  which  is  universal  is  also 
natural,  on  the  ground  that  appetites  which  are  inherited 
from  remote  ancestors  will  necessarily  be  universal,  even 
though  they  may  have  been  acquired  by  our  ancestors.* 
To  meet  this  objection  we  go  on  to  show  from  other 
arguments  that  certain  psychic  appetites  cannot  be 
accidental,  but  were  necessar}^  factors  of  our  constitu- 
tion from  the  beginning. 

'''  (2)  Certain  psychic  appetites,  like  some  of  those  men- 
tioned in  our  last  argument,  have  allied  to  them  certain 
specified  natural  organs,  which  organs,  though  mani- 
festly purposeful  in  the  order  of  nature,  could  not,  apart 
from  the  psychical  appetites  attached  to  them,  attain 
their  ends.  Thus  in  animals  (we  say  in  '  animals ' 
because  in  plants  strangely  enough  this  nutritive  organ 
is  able  to  obtain  the  means  of  sustenance  without  any 
psychic  appetite)  the  stomach  could  not  attain  its 
natural  object,  food,  unless  they  possessed  cognitive 
appetites  for  food.  The  organ,  therefore,  being  natural, 
nature  must  have  provided  the  appetite  by  which  alone 
the  organ  can  attain  its  end.  We  know,  of  course,  from 
experience  that  the  psychic  appetite  in  question  does 
actually  exist.  Our  present  point  is  that  it  is  natural — 
as  natural  as  the  organ  itself,  since  without  it  the  organ 
would  Jiave  no  purpose  or  meaning. '\ 


*  Constant  indulgence  in  any  particular  desire  would,  it  is  ex- 
plained, have  given  to  our  remote  ancestors  a  permanent  tendency 
towards  certain  objects,  which  tendency  would  through  long-continued 
transmission  come  to  be  felt  as  necessary  and  as  inseparable  from  the 
human  race.  But  the  point  arises — why  did  our  ancestors  indulge 
these  desires  so  widely  and  so  constantly  except  that  they  were  at- 
tached to  permanent  natural  appetites. 

t  The  same  reasoning  holds  for  other  psychic  appetites  besides 
that  for  food.  In  fact  in  the  sense-world  most  psychic  appetites 
are  attendant  on  and  are  the  natural  complement  of  some  organ, 
and  are  required  in  order  that  the  organ  may  attain  its  end. 


no  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

This  line  of  argument,  drawn  from  the  presence  of 
appetites  with  specified  organs,  not  only  makes  manifest 
the  existence  in  man  of  natural  appetites,  but  is  also  of 
great  value  in  enabling  us  to  specify  the  appetites  which 
we  hold  to  be  natural. 

(3)  Closely  allied  to  the  last  argument  is  another  the 
force  of  which  is  admitted  even  by  evolutionists,  that 
some  ps3^chic  appetites  are  so  inseparable  from  living 
things,  and  so  necessary  to  them  from  the  first  moment 
of  their  existence,  that  without  them  the  races  could  not 
have  continued  to  live.  As  Leslie  Stephen  remarks, 
without  certain  appetites  the  race  could  not  have  sur- 
vived a  generation.  Obvious  instances  are  the  appetite 
for  existence,  the  love  of  food  and  of  the  sexes,  and  the 
love  of  parents  for  their  offspring.  But  appetites  that 
are  so  necessary  that  without  them  existence  would 
have  been  impossible  must  be  part  of  our  constitution 
from  the  beginning.  Hence  some  psychic  appetites  are 
natural. 

(4)  The  psychic  appetites  considered  up  to  the  present 
are  for  the  most  part  sensuous  at  least  in  their  ground. 
But  some  psychic  appetites  are  purely  rational.  Of 
these  latter  we  shall  consider  two  here — that  for  society 
and  that  for  the  good-in-general,  or  the  will.  The 
appetite  for  society  is  natural  to  man  as  is  evident  from 
the  two  following  reasons — {a)  Man  is  naturally  pos- 
sessed of  a  limitless  capacity  for  development,  because 
there  is  no  end  to  his  powers  of  intellectual  cognition. 
But  without  a  natural  appetite  for  society  these  powers 
would  be  in  vain  ;  for,  without  a  natural  appetite  for 
society  it  is  impossible  *  that  we  should  continue  to  live 

•  For  proof  of  this  proposition  see  chapter  on  Society.  The  argu- 
ment given  in  the  text  for  the  necessity  of  a  natural  appetite  for 
society  as  a  means  to  dcvc-lopnicnt  is  not  wlidlly  a  priori,  for  vvc  find 
by  experience  (if  others  and  by  reflection  on  ourselves  that  man  is 
possessed  of  this  appetite,  and  the  only  ciueslion  here  treated  is  whether 
It  is  natural.  Our  reasfining  on  the  point  is  the  same  as  that  in  the 
second  argument  alx>ve — witiiout  a  psychical  appetite  for  society  a 
certain  intellectual  capacity  would  be  useless.  Hence  the  appetite  for 
locicty  is  natural. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  iii 

permanently  in  society,  and  unless  we  lived  per- 
manently in  society  we  could  not  possibly,  judging  from 
experience,  attain  to  more  than  the  mere  beginnings  of 
knowledge.  Hence  the  appetite  for  society  is  natural. 
{b)  Man  is  possessed  of  a  natural  faculty  *  of  speech, 
with  no  other  natural  purpose  than  the  social  purpose 
of  communicating  with  our  fellow  men  in  order  to  our 
human  welfare.  Hence  society  is  an  original  purpose  of 
nature,  and,  therefore,  our  appetite  for  it  is  natural. 

Again,  there  is  in  man  a  rational  faculty  of  will,  whose 
object  embraces  all  particular  goods  and  extends  to  the 
good  in  general.  Now,  this  faculty  of  will,  the  existence 
of  which  is  known  to  us  from  experience  and  from 
psychological  science,  is  shown  to  be  natural  from  the 
following  argument  from  St.  Thomas  Aquinas,  to  which 
we  invite  the  reader's  special  attention,  because  it  is 
the  argument  by  which  St.  Thomas  establishes  not 
merely  the  natural  character  of  the  will,  but  the  ex- 
istence in  man  of  natnral  appetites  generally,  and  it 
seems  to  excel  all  other  arguments  both  in  point  of 
comprehensiveness  and  of  logical  force.  Here,  however, 
we  shall  emphasise  its  relation  to  the  special  faculty  of 
will  only. 

Everything  in  the  world,  St.  Thomas  points  out,f  is 
possessed  of  appetites  which  vary  in  kind  and  degree  of 
perfection  with  the  nature  of  the  thing  to  which  they 
belong.  Minerals  tend  to  exhibit  certain  mineral  pro- 
perties.    Plants  tend  to  vegetative  effects,  to  assimila- 


♦  Every  faculty,  even  that  of  speech,  has  allied  to  it  a  certain  nisus 
towards,  and  therefore  an  appetite  for,  its  exercise. 

t  "  S.  Thcol.,"  I.,  Q.  LXXX.,  Art.  i.  St.  Thomas  in  this  article 
shows  that  there  are  in  man  special  psychical  appetites  by  which  he 
means  not  only  that  they  are  special,  but  that  as  special  these  appetites 
are  an  original  part  of  our  constitution.  His  treatise  de  homine  of 
the  "  S.  Theol."  is  an  enquiry  into  natural  faculties  and  powers  only. 

It  is  hardly  necessary  to  point  to  the  immense  and  far-reaching 
importance  of  St.  Thomas'  argument  here.  It  is  a  claim  that  to  every 
grade  of  being  besides  the  static  there  is  also  a  dynamic  or  conative 
side.  The  psychical  appetites  are  the  dynamic  side  of  our  cognitive 
nature. 


112  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

tion  and  growth.  These  appetites  are  physical  since 
they  have  no  dependence  on  cognition.  But  man  is 
b}'  nature  cognitive  as  well  as  vegetative,  and,  there- 
fore, since  every  "  form  "  or  nature  gives  rise  to  a  special 
appetite,  there  must  be  allied  to  our  cognitive  nature 
cognitive  appetites  also — that  is,  appetites  for  certain 
objects  as  perceived  and  known.  But  cognition  is 
rational  as  well  as  sensuous,  and,  as  rational,  man  can 
transcend  in  thought  all  particular  finite  things  and 
can  apprehend  being-in-general  and  truth-in-general  and 
the  infinite  itself.  Therefore  allied  to  our  nature  as 
intellectual  there  must  be  a  special  appetite  extending 
to  the  good  in  general.* 

The  foregoing  reasoning  based  on  the  fact  that  each 
grade  of  being  is  possessed  of  special  appetites  is  con- 
firmed by  two  other  arguments  which  also  establish  the 
natural  character  of  the  will.  The  first  is  that  the  end 
of  the  will  is  our  ultimate  end.  But  we  shall  see  later  f 
that  unless  the  desire  for  our  last  end  is  natural  no 
other  desire  would  be  possible  to  us.  Hence  the  will 
is  a  natural  appetite.  Our  second  argument  is  the 
following  :  whatever  is,  in  the  order  of  nature,  necessary 
for  the  realisation  of  a  natural  capacity,  is  itself  natural. 
If  flowering  is  necessary  for  fruit,  then  since  fruit  is 
natural  so  flowering  is  natural.  Now  man  is  possessed 
of  a  natural  capacity  for  endless  progres-^.  Therefore 
if  an  appetite  for  the  good-in-general  (by  which,  of  course, 
is  meant  the  will)  is  necessary  for  such  progress  such  an 
appetite  is  natural.  But  the  necessity  of  an  appetite 
that  transcends  all  particular  goods  and  reaches  out  to 
all  good  is  beyond  question.  For  progress  it  is  necessary 
to  direct  oneself  to  an  end  beyond  the  present,  to  form 
and  aim  at  ideals  higher  than  the  accomplished  facts, 

•  As  in  the  case  of  our  apjxititc  for  society,  tlie  above  arj^iimont 
is  not  wholly  a  priori.  Wc  know  from  other  .sources  than  mere  a 
priori  argument  tliat  we  are  capal^le  of  transcending  in  our  desires 
all  particular  finite  goods.  The  argument  in  the  text  merely  demon- 
strates that  the  appetite  is  natural. 

t  Page  2  J  7. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  113 

to  co-ordinate  one's  several  particular  aims,  to  control 
their  objects  so  as  to  attain  to  some  higher  object  above 
them  all.  For  this  there  is  necessary  an  appetite  that 
rises  above  all  particular  goods,  an  appetite  for  the 
universal  good,  or  bonum-in-gaicre.  Hence  the  appetite 
for  the  universal  good  or  the  will,  is  natural. 

We  may  remark,  in  conclusion  of  this  section,  and 
even  at  the  risk  of  seeming  to  anticipate  unnecessarily 
our  future  chapter  on  Law,  that  it  is  on  these  natural 
appetites  that  we  build  up  our  conception  of  the  natural 
law — each  appetite  giving  rise  to  a  particular  law.  But 
the  natural  laws  are  much  more  numerous  than  the 
natural  objects  of  the  appetites.  For  the  natural  law 
inculcates  not  merely  the  obtaining  of  these  natural 
objects  but  also  the  doing  of  what  is  necessary  for  their 
attainment.  Thus  even  had  we  no  natural  desire  for 
food,  we  should  nevertheless  deem  it  our  duty  to  eat, 
since  food  is  necessary  for  life,  and  every  living  sub- 
stance has  a  natural  appetite  for  life.  Again,  since  in 
man  there  is  a  natural  appetite  whose  one  purpose  is 
the  maintenance  and  propagation  of  the  race,  there  is 
involved  in  the  law  of  securing  this  good  *  another  law 
of  caring  and  maintaining  offspring,  and  of  marriage  also 
as  a  means  to  this,  since  nature  aims  not  at  the  mere 
existence  of  children  but  at  their  growth  and  con- 
tinuance, not  at  imperfect  but  at  perfect  men ;  and 
this  duty  would  be  binding  even  though  there  were 
no  special  appetite  in  mothers  for  the  care  of  their 
young. 

But  apart  from  the  question  of  how  many  laws  corre- 
spond to  the  separate  appetites,  our  point  here  is  that 
since  some  appetites  are  natural  some  laws  also  are 
natural.  Of  the  permanence  and  invariability  of  these 
laws,  and  the  related  question  whether  a  natural  appetite 
might  disappear,  or  whether,  if  it  did  disappear  the  law 

*  We  shall  afterwards  explain  that  the  law  of  securing  one's  own 
life  holds  for  each  individual,  the  law  of  maintaining  the  life  of  the 
race  holds  not  for  each  individual. 
Vol.  1—8 


114  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

also  should  disappear,  we  shall  speak  in  our  chapter  on 
Biological  Evolution. 


{d)  Consideration   of   Some   Theories   of  Positivist 

Morals 

Directly  opposed  to  the  theory  we  have  been  defining 
of  a  natural  distinction  between  good  and  evil  is  the 
theory  of  moral  positivism,  or  the  theory  that  good  and 
evil  depend  not  on  nature  but  on  positive  law  or  custom, 
or  on  some  mere  passing  and  accidental  desire.  This 
theory  has  many  forms,  only  a  few  of  which  can  be 
mentioned  here. 

Hobbes'  theory  is  that  in  the  so-called  state  of  nature, 
i.e.,  the  state  which  he  supposes  to  have  preceded  the 
formation  of  society,  the  good  was  merely  that  which 
any  man  desired.  Our  objection  is  two-fold.  First, 
the  theory  is  the  negation  of  natural  distinctions: 
second,  it  conveys  a  false  idea  of  the  "  good."  For  a 
man  might  at  any  particular  moment  desire  some- 
thing in  a  passing  way  which  yet  opposes  the  most  fun- 
damental appetites  of  his  being,  and  since  such  an  act, 
though  it  satisfies  the  mere  passing  desire,  is  neverthe- 
less at  variance  with  the  still  more  fundamental  desire  of 
the  natural  appetites,  it  is  impossible  to  speak  of  such  an 
act  as  simply  desired  by  us  or  as  an  object  of  appetite. 
On  the  contrary,  it  is  at  variance  with  our  appetites  con- 
sidered as  a  whole,  and  it  is,  therefore,  bad.  Hence, 
even  though  the  good  is  defined  by  us  *  as  the  object  of 
appetite,  such  a  definition  admits  of  a  distinction  be- 
tween good  and  evil  appotition.  To  define  the  good  as 
what  any  man  desires,  in  Hobbes'  sense,  is  to  rule  out 
the  distinction. 

Rousseau  reduces  all  distinctions  of  good  and  evil  to 
ordinances  of  the  State — that  is,  to  positive  law — and 
the  State  itself  he  regards  as  a  positive  institution,  a 

•  At  the  beginning  of  this  chapter  we  gave  some  account  of  llic 
•cholastic  rlofinition  of  the  good-  iJie  "  object  of  appetite." 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  115 

result  of  positive  compact  freely  entered  into  by  men. 
Of  Rousseau's  indebtedness  to  Hobbes  for  the  theory 
of  the  origin  of  society  we  shall  say  nothing.  But  it 
is  evident  that  the  theory  that  distinctions  of  good  and 
evil  originate  with  the  State  is  founded  on  Hobbes' 
view  given  above.  In  criticism  of  Rousseau's  view  we 
say  (i)  some  moral  distinctions  are  certainly  independent 
of  the  State,  e.g.,  that  between  caring  and  neglecting 
offspring  :  (2)  that  unless  the  State  were  itself  a  natural 
institution  it  would  have  no  moral  power  to  impose  on 
us  a  law  of  preference  between  good  and  evil  conduct : 
(3)  that  the  State  may  even  now  make  laws  which  yet 
we  regard  ourselves  as  free  to  disobey,  whereas  there 
are  certain  other  laws  which  we  do  not  regard  ourselves 
as  free  to  disobey.  In  other  words,  the  State  may 
itself  make  bad  laws  which  could  not  bind  in  conscience  ; 
consequently,  the  State  is  not  itself  the  source  of  moral 
distinctions:  (4)  that  if  men  did  ever  enter  into  a  com- 
pact to  form  the  State  they  made  such  compact  because 
the  State  was  necessary  to  the  attainment  of  certain 
necessary  ends.  But  the  existence  of  necessary  ends 
involves  a  natural  distinction  of  good  and  evil.  One 
end  contemplated  in  the  compact  theory  is  that  of 
peace  and  prosperity.  Therein  is  ground  for  much  moral 
distinction :  (3)  that  the  State  itself  is  a  natural 
institution,  and  consequently  certain  ends  are  naturally 
good  for  it.  This,  however,  we  shall  prove  in  a  later 
chapter.* 

Carneades  in  ancient  times,  and  M.  Levy-Bruhl  in 
modern,  ground  moral  distinctions  on  human  custom. 
Law,  they  maintain,  follows  practice — not  practice  law. 
Our  ancestors  did  not  first  formulate  the  laws  of  human 
conduct  and  then  obey  these  laws  in  practice.  On  the 
contrary,  laws  are  an  outgrowth  of  those  practices  which 
the  conditions  of  existence  most  favoured  in  bygone 
ages. 

*  Vol.  II.,  page  471. 


ii6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Now,  this  theory  is  also  false.  Men,  indeed,  are  cer- 
tainly creatures  of  custom,  but  custom  is  also  to  a  large 
extent  the  creation  of  natural  necessity.  It  needed  no 
custom  to  make  men  eat,  to  induce  them  to  protect 
their  offspring,  to  enter  society.  These  acts  spring  from 
an  inner  necessity  of  nature,  and  without  such  neces- 
sities of  nature  there  would  have  been  neither  Society 
nor  custom  on  which  to  ground  distinctions. 

Again,  in  no  part  of  nature  is  law  founded  on  mere 
practice  or  facts.*  On  the  contrary,  law  always  pre- 
cedes in  time,  and  is  the  principle  of  fact.  The  law  of 
gravitation  does  not  depend  on  the  fact  that  bodies 
fall  to  the  earth.  On  the  contrary,  bodies  fall  because 
of  the  law  of  gravitation.  The  law  that  makes  trees 
bloom  in  spring  did  not  arise  after  trees  had  bloomed 
many  successive  years.  On  the  contrary,  they  bloomed 
because  that  is  the  law  of  trees.  Now,  law  is  not 
differently  related  to  facts  or  to  practice  in  the  case  of 
men  and  in  the  case  of  lower  species.  And,  therefore, 
if  all  nations  have  followed  certain  courses  of  conduct 
that  fact  is  due  to  one  thing  only — viz.,  that  men  have 
toiiowed  a  felt  law  of  nature — a  law  that  was  vital  for 
them.  If,  at  the  beginning,  humanity  had  no  law  to 
follow — if,  therefore,  its  early  acts  were  done  at  random 
because  there  was  no  law  to  follow — it  would  have  dis- 
appeared as  quickly  as  would  a  race  of  animals  that  had 
no  guiding  instincts.  Moral  law  and  moral  distinctions 
then,  cannot  have  resulted  out  of  mere  custom.  From 
the  beginning  conduct  must  have  been  based  on  natural 
necessities. 

Besides,  there  was  no  time  since  history  began  at 
which  we  do  not  find  many  natural  needs  not  only  acted 
on,  but  actually  and  formally  recognised.  For  this 
reason  M.  L6vy-Bruhl  is  forced  to  push  back  the  period 
which  we  have  called  the  period  of  "  random  action  " 

•  "  There  arc  some  thinRS,"  says  Aristotle,  "  wliich  \vc  have  and 
put  in  practice — wc  do  not  come  to  luive  11i<'m  by  practice  "  {fxavm 
iXprfoafuOa  ov  xpri<j6tnvoi  taxontv).     Nicii.  l*i!i    II  ,  i,  .), 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  117 

into  prehistoric  times.  Now,  a  thing  that  is  possible 
and  likelv  rnay,  even  when  there  is  no  historic  evidence 
of  its  existence  as  a  fact,  be  represented  as  an  hypothesis 
on  which  to  ground  present  phenomena.  But  a  thing 
for  which  we  have  no  historic  evidence,  and  which  at 
the  same  time  offends  against  every  known  law  of 
nature,  cannot  be  regarded  as  an  admissible  hypothesis 
or  as  capable  of  accounting  for  any  present  phenomena. 
But  of  the  "  random  "  system,  out  of  which  customs  are 
said  to  have  proceeded,  we  have  no  historical  evidence. 
And,  on  the  other  hand,  every  known  fact  is  dead 
against  the  possibility  of  such  a  supposition.  Trees 
could  not  survive  without  water.  Animals  could  not 
survive  without  instincts.  Men  could  not  survive  had 
they  not  a  law  to  follow  from  the  beginning,  at  least,  as 
regards  the  essentials  of  the  life  of  individuals  and  of 
the  race. 

We  are  not  free,  therefore,  to  suppose,  as  cause  of 
our  present  moral  system,  that  at  one  period  of  our 
history  there  were  no  laws  of  human  conduct  and  no 
natural  appetites  ;  that  from  that  period  certain  courses 
survived  as  more  conducive  to  life  than  others,  and  that 
these  courses  came  thenceforward  to  be  looked  upon 
as  natural  and  as  enforced  by  natural  law.  "  Sur- 
vival "  may  be  a  factor  in  the  maintenance  of  certain 
species  ;  but  the  species  that  survive  are  those  that  act 
on  the  best  system  and  follow  the  best  law.  A  species 
that  lived  at  random,  that  had  no  natural  guiding  in- 
stincts, could  never  survive  the  struggle  for  existence  ; 
and  the  human  race  survives  because,  in  the  main,  men 
have  always  consulted  their  natural  appetites  and  needs. 

Nietzsche's  "  new  morality  "  is  built  upon  the  denial 
of  a  natural  distinction  of  good  and  evil.  The  laws  that 
at  present  rule  the  world  are,  according  to  Nietzsche, 
the  laws  of  the  slaves  who  for  a  time  have,  with  the  aid 
of  the  priests,  gained  the  mastery  over  the  aristocrats. 
This  is  the  law  of  pity,  of  mildness,  of  the  equality  of 
men.      To    this    law    must    succeed,    with    the    rise    of 


ii8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

another  aristocracy,  the  law  of  hardship  and  of  severest 
justice.  But  even  the  aristocrac}/  must  give  way  to 
another  order — that  of  the  "  Ubermensch,"  or  the 
Philosopher,  and  to  his  law  of  individualism,  of  inde- 
pendence from  all  things  except  himself,  "  independence 
of  Fatherland,  of  Pity,  of  Knowledge,  of  his  own  free- 
dom, of  virtue  itself,  of  all  except  himself  and  his 
sovereign  individuality."  * 

At  this  point  we  have  to  consider  only  Nietzsche's 
theory  that  the  present  law,  so  far  from  being  natural, 
is  grounded  on  deceit,  that  even  the  aristocracy  has  been 
tricked  into  accepting  a  law  as  natural  and  necessary 
which  yet  is  only  artificial  and  is  imposed  upon  them 
for  their  overthrow,  and  that  this  law  must  completely 
give  place  to  another.  Our  answer  is,  that  if  this 
"  Umwerthung  all  Werthen,"  this  heel  over  in  moralit\^ 
of  which  Nietzsche  speaks,  were  to  take  place,  if  our 
present  morality  were  to  yield  to  another,  man  could 
not  long  survive  the  change.  Just  as  no  man  could 
survive  a  change  in  his  bodily  functions — the  use,  for 
instance,  of  the  heart  for  breathing,  of  the  lungs  for 
some  other  function — so  human  nature  could  not  long 
survive  a  completely  new  departure  in  morals.  Func- 
tion is  to  the  body  what  end  and  law  are  to  conduct. 
And  as  the  present  law  of  the  body  is  its  only  law,  as 
one  member  could  not  be  tricked  into  accepting  a  func- 
tion f  which  did  not  naturally  belong  to  it,  so  the 
present  law  of  the  social  organism  is  its  only  natural 
law,  and  it  could  not  give  way  to  another.  The  positive 
law  may  change  with  change  of  circumstances,  but  there 
is  even  in  the  positive  law  a  groundwork  of  natural  law 
that  can  never  change.  Again,  it  is  impossible  that 
men  could  be  deceived  into  thinking  that  certain  rules 
of  morality  are  natural  and  necessary.     For,  as  we  shall 

*  Harlmann,  "  Ethischc  Studicn,"  page  55. 

t  In  saying  this  wc  are  not  unmindful  of  those  interchanges  of 
function  which  arc  considered  in  cerebral  Physiology.  These  latter 
arc  not  on  a  par  with  the  violent  and  complete  interchanges  con- 
sidered in  the  text  above. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  119 

see  later,  our  moral  beliefs  are  held  on  grounds  of 
Reason,  and  of  many  of  these  beliefs  even  the  plainest 
and  least  educated  of  men  could  give  a  rational  account. 
Paulsen  s  theory  that  every  condition  of  life  and 
every  country  have  their  own  proper  morality,  that 
the  morality  of  the  Englishman  is  not  that  of  the 
Chinaman,  the  morality  of  the  artist  not  that  of  the 
merchant,  or,  as  he  himself  expresses  it,  that  the  natural 
tendency  of  our  conscience  is  to  develop  special  ideals,* 
is  also  answered  by  pointing  out  that  even  though  in 
accidentals  the  duties  of  Englishmen  and  Chinam.en, 
artists  and  merchants,  may  differ,  in  essentials  they 
are  the  same.  There  is  no  condition  or  country  in 
which  stealing,  lying,  and  the  neglect  of  children  are 
the  natural  thing,  and  their  opposites  unnatural.  As 
all  men  have  essentially  the  same  bodily  construction, 
so  all  have  the  same  fundamental  appetites  and  needs. 
And  on  these  appetites  is  grounded  the  natural  moral 
law.  But,  just  as  in  Medicine  account  must  be  taken 
of  all  the  conditions,  normal  and  abnormal,  of  the  body 
and  generally  of  the  special  requirements  of  individuals, 
so  in  Morals  account  must  be  taken  of  the  individual 
circumstances,  and  it  is  from  these  circumstances  that 
the  differences  of  moral  law  for  different  individuals 
mainly  originate.  Every  man  must  pay  his  lawful 
debts,  -provided  he  is  able.  Every  man  must  abide  by 
the  conditions  of  his  contract,  hut  the  conditions  of  con- 
tract in  one  country  are  not  the  same  as  those  in  another. 
The  necessities  of  Art  and  of  Medicine  will  justify  some 
things  in  the  life  of  an  artist  or  of  a  physician  which 
would  not  be  regarded  as  justifiable  in  the  case  of  the 
merchant.  But  neither  artist  nor  physician  may  offend 
against  the  essentials  of  the  natural  law,  nor  may  they 
use  the  acknowledged  privileges  of  their  profession  ex- 
cept with  a  good  end  and  intention,  and  with  a  due 
sense  of  subordination  to  the  general  laws.     To  every 

f  "  System  of  Ethics,"  pages  19  and  370. 


120  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

privilege  Reason  sets  proper  limits,  and  the  limits  of 
privileges  arising  from  a  man's  status  or  profession  are 
easily  definable.  In  the  main,  then,  the  natural  duties 
of  aU  men  are  the  same.  Of  this  point  a  fuller  explana- 
tion will  be  given  in  the  next  chapter. 

Occam  and  many  others  ground  all  moral  distinctions 
on  the  free  will  of  God.  The  good  they  represent  as 
that  which  He  has  freely  commanded  us  to  do.  Now, 
this  theory  is  equally  positivistic  with  the  theory  of 
Hobbes  and  Carneades,  even  though  it  bases  morality 
on  God,  and,  like  the  theor}^  of  Carneades,  it  is  dis- 
proved by  all  that  we  have  said  on  the  existence  of 
natural  moral  distinctions.  God,  indeed,  need  not  have 
created  any  finite  nature,  but,  granted  that  natures  are 
created,  God  cannot  but  wish  for  and  command  the 
attainment  of  natural  ends. 

Though  not  belonging  to  the  theories  which  we  are  at 
present  discussing — theories,  namely,  that  represent  all 
morality  as  arbitrar}' — we  ma}'  nevertheless,  on  account 
of  their  connection  with  the  views  of  Occam  and  his 
followers,  be  allowed  to  say  something  here  on  the  two 
theories  of  "  Extrinsic  "  and  "  Independent  "  Moralit)^ 

A  larger  and  more  important  question  than  that  of 
the  freedom  of  God's  command  in  relation  to  the  natural 
law  is  the  question  of  Extrinsic  Morality — the  question, 
viz.,  whether  the  moral  distinctions,  instead  of  being 
intrinsic  in  things  and  inherent  in  their  very  nature, 
are,  on  the  contrary,  wholly  outside  of  acts,  and  spring 
exclusively  from  God's  command  (whether  necessary  or 
free)  to  do  or  to  avoid  them.  This  is  the  theory  that 
we  find  attributed  to  Scholastics  generally  by  Herbert 
Spencer.  "  Religious  creeds,"  he  writes,  "  established 
and  dissenting,  all  embody  the  belief  that  right  and 
wrong  are  right  and  wrong  simply  in  virtue  of  divine 
enactment."  * 

•The  theory  thtit  moral  distinctions  are  founded  exclusively  on 
God's  command  is  taught  by  Puffcndorf,  "  Law  of  Nature  and  Nations," 
11.3 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  121 

If  this  means,  as  it  seems  to  mean,  that  right  and 
wrong  are  not  properties  of  human  acts  themselves, 
then  the  statement  is  absolutely  and  demonstrably 
untrue.  There  is  no  commoner  axiom  to  be  found  in 
Scholastic  Ethics  than  the  well-known  "  quaedam  mala 
quia  prohibita  quaidam  prohibita  quia  mala."  The 
Ethical  theory,  therefore,  of  the  Schoolman  was  not  a 
theory  of  "  Extrinsic  Morality."  Even  the  smallest 
acquaintance  with  the  works  of  St.  Thomas  should 
convince  us  that  morality  is  on  his  theory  a  property 
of  acts  in  their  very  nature.  He  tells  us  that  good- 
ness means  fulness  of  being  in  an  act,  and  nothing 
could  be  more  intrinsic  to  an  act  than  its  own 
being. 

The  Church,  too,  condemns  the  theory  of  extrinsic 
Morality.  The  48th  and  49th  propositions  of  those 
condemned  by  Innocent  XI  in  1679  (^^^  Denzinger, 
pages  328,  329)  are  the  following  : — : 

"  Tam  clarum  videtur  fornicationem  secundum  se 
nuUam  involvere  malitiam  et  solum  esse  malam  quia 
interdictam,  ut  contrarium  omnino  rationi  dissonum 
vidoatur." 

"  Mollifies  jure  naturae  prohibita  non  est.  Unde  si 
Deus  eam  non  interdixisset  saepe  esset  bona,  et  ali- 
quando  obligatoria  sub  mortali." 

This  doctrine  of  "  Extrinsic  Morality  "  is  also  con- 
demned by  Saurez,  Lessius,  and  practically  all  the 
leading  Catholic  theologians. 

Suarez  writes  : — "  Haec  Dei  Voluntas  Prohibitio  aut 
Perceptio  non  est  tota  ratio  bonitatis  et  malitiae  quae 
est  in  observatione  vel  trangressione  Legis  Naturalis 
sed  supponit  in  ipsis  actibus  necessariam  quandam 
honestatem  vel  turpitudinem."  And  again  "  (mala) 
non  possunt  primam  malitiam  habere  a  Prohibitione  " 
("  De  Legibus  "). 

And  Lessius : — "  Ante  omnem  Prohibitionem  con- 
siderare  in  illis  (actibus)  quandam  malitiam  objectivam  " 
("  De  Perfectionibus  Divinis  Lib  XIII."). 


122  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

We  may  take  it,  then,  that  the  theory  of  "  Extrinsic 
Morality "  is  not  teaching  at  least  of  the  Catholic 
Church  (See  testimonies  in  Ward's  "  Nature  and 
Grace  "). 

But  if  Catholic  theologians  and  philosophers  ex- 
pressly oppose  the  theory  of  Extrinsic  IVIoralit}'  they  are 
equally  explicit  in  their  opposition  to  the  theory  known 
as  "  Independent  Morality."  * 

Independent  Morality  is  the  theory  that  moral  dis- 
tinctions have  no  dependence  on  God,  and  would  exist 
even  if  God  did  not  exist. 

Now  this  theory  we  repudiate  wholly.  It  is  manifest 
that  goodness  has  a  most  manifold  dependence  on 
God,  because  {a)  without  God  there  could  be  neither 
good  nor  evil,  nor  any  acts.  He  is  the  first  cause  of 
all  things,  (6)  because  the  "  good  "  and  the  "  natural " 
are  one,  and  our  natures  are  nothing  more  than  a 
certain  participation  in  the  Divine  nature.  Conse- 
quently, the  good  in  creatures  is  founded  on,  and  is 
a  reflection  of,  the  JDivine  nature,  (c)  because  good 
means  direction  to  the  final  end,f  and  God  is  the  final 
natural  end,  [d)  because  the  good  has  not  its  complete 
meaning  in  this  life.  "  Good  "  leads  naturally  to  the 
actual  possession  of  the  final  end,  evil  to  its  being  lost. 
These  things  are  of  the  essence  of  "  good  "  and  "  evil." 
We  have,  however,  seen  already  that  the  attainment  of 
our  final  end  lies  not  in  this  life.  Consequently  good 
has  not  its  ■  complete  meaning  in  this  life.  But  were 
moral  distinctions  independent  of  God,  "  good ''  and 
"  evil  "    would    be   fully    realised    and   completed   here 

*  There  arc  many  forms  of  this  theory.  That  which  we  now  refer 
to  is  the  cxtremest  of  these  forms.  "Other  forms  of  the  theory  will 
come  up  for  discussion  later. 

\  This  and  the  next  arRiimont  show  clearly  that  pood  and  evil 
have  a  closer  dependence  on  God  than  other  created  things  have.  All 
created  things  are  from  God.  lint  God  docs  not  enter  into  their 
definition.  As  the  last  end,  however,  He  enters  into  the  definition 
of  the  "  good."  From  argument  "  c  "  it  is  plain  that  every  morally 
bad  act  is  a  sin — that  is,  is  a  thcoloRical  cringe.  A  bad  act  is  a  turning 
fiway  (ron^  our  fm.-il  end 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  123 

below.     We  cannot,   therefore,   assert   that  morality  is 
independent  of  God,* 

♦  The  view  expressed  by  some  philosophers  and  at  least  insinuated 
by  others,  e.g.,  by  Harms  ("  Ethik,"  page  69)  that  if  morals  are  founded 
on  the  nature  of  things  themselves  (sometimes  spoken  of  as  the  theory 
of  "  Naturalism  ")  they  cannot  be  founded  on  God,  is  shown  to  be 
untrue  by  the  arguments  given  above.  Morals  are  founded  proximately 
on  man's  nature,  ultimately  on  the  nature  of  God,  from  whom  all 
creatures  with  their  natures  and  properties  proceed. 


CHAPTER  V 
THE  MORAL  CRITERIA 

MEANING   OF   CRITERION 

A  CRITERION  is  a  standard  or  test  of  anything.  There 
are  criteria  of  speed,  of  weight,  of  mental  abihty.  A 
moral  criterion  is  a  criterion  of  moral  good  and  evil. 

Now,  a  test  can  be  either  a  fact  or  a  principle.  The 
plumb-line  is  a  fact-criterion.  By  it  we  test  whether  a 
wall  is  perpendicular  or  not.  The  axioms  of  Geometry 
are  tests  in  the  sense  of  principles.  By  means  of  them 
we  test  the  truth  of  geometrical  propositions.  These 
two  classes  of  tests,  however,  are  not  exclusive  of  one 
another.  A  test  that  is  used  as  a  fact  can  (and  must 
when  we  would  reason  on  it)  be  always  formulated  as 
a  principle  also.  We  can  take  a  plumb-line  into  our 
hands  and  test  a  wall  by  it.  We  then  use  it  as  a  fact. 
Or  we  can  make  the  mental  assertion  "  the  wall  that  is 
plumb  is  perpendicular,"  and  we  have  then  formulated 
a  principle.  Ontologically,  it  is  plain,  the  fact  is 
primary.  Logically,  in  the  sense  of  helping  to  the 
formation  of  our  judgments  about  things,  the  principle 
is  primary.  But  as  a  rule  it  is  in  the  sense  of  "  facts  " 
that  we  speak  of  "  tests,"  and  it  is  in  this  latter  sense 
that  we  shall  speak  of  criteria  in  the  following  pages. 
Our  enquiry,  then,  is — by  what  fact  or  facts  shall  we, 
in  the  last  instance,*  test  the  moral  quality  of  actions  ? 

•  Wc  shall  sec  later  (paRC  135)  that  fli'.*  primary  criterion  docs  not' 
mean  that  criterion  which  is  api)lie(l  immediately  to  luiinan  acts  in 
order  to  test  their  morality,  hut  that  criterion  on  wliich  we  have 
ultimately  to  fall  back  in  our  arguments  in  order  to  test  the  morality 
of  acts  and  the  validity  of  the  principles.  Thus  in  treating  of  questions 
of  justice  wc  rarely  apply  the  primary  criterion  directly.  Hut  when 
in  defending  the  laws  of  justice  wc  arc  driven  finally  back  to  the 
enquiry — wliat  is  justice  or  what  arc  the  simple  natural  relations  of 
men  in  society  ? — it  is  then  that  wc  must  make  use  of  our  pritnary 
criterion. 

124 


h 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  125 

It  may  be  well  to  state  here  that  immediately  and 
directly  an  ethical  criterion  is  meant  to  tell  us  not 
whether  an  individual  is  formally  guilty  or  praise- 
worthy on  account  of  his  acts,  but  whether  objecti\ely 
and  in  itself  a  particular  act  or  course  of  conduct  is 
good — whether,  e.g.,  lying,  killing,  stealing  are  good 
or  bad.  But  though  this  is  true,  still  the  determination 
of  the  formal  morality  of  acts  depends  on  the  moral 
criteria  also,  since  the  individual  man  is  bound  to  con- 
form to  the  moral  criterion,  and  if  he  does  not  do  so  it 
is  only  ignorance .  that  can  excuse  him  from  formal 
guilt. 

DIVISION   OF   CRITERIA 

Criteria  may  be  divided  into — 

(i)  Primary  and  derivative. 

(2)  Proper  or  intrinsic,  and  accidental  or  extrinsic. 

A  primary  criterion  is  a  criterion  w^hich  is  original 
and  fundamental,  and  is  not  itself  dependent  on  or 
reducible  to  any  other  criteria — e.g.,  the  bronze  bar  in 
the  office  of  the  Exchequer  as  the  standard  of  length. 

A  derivative  criterion  is  one  which  is  dependent  on 
the  primary.  It  is  used  as  representative  of  the 
primary,  generally  in  cases  in  which  the  primary 
criterion  cannot  itself  be  conveniently  applied.  Such 
are  the  ordinary  weights  and  measures  used  in  com- 
mercial houses.  These  secondary  tests  are  necessar}^ 
for  to  test  in  all  cases  by  means  of  the  original  weights 
and  measures  would  be  out  of  the  question.  A  de- 
rivative criterion,  however,  is  not  alwa^'s,  as  in  the 
case  of  the  weights  and  measures,  a  repetition  of  the 
primary.  Any  effect  of  the  primary  criterion  could  be 
used  as  a  derivative  crite'rion  as  we  shall  see  later  on 
in  the  case  of  the  secondary  criteria  of  morals. 

An  intrinsic  or  proper  criterion  is  one  which  belongs 
to  the  same  category  of  being  as.  the  object  which 
the   criterion   is   meant    to   test — e.g.,  a  standard  tape- 


126  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

rule  as  measure  of  length,  a  plumb-line  as  test  of 
perpendicularity. 

An  extrinsic  or  accidental  criterion  is  one  which 
belongs  to  quite  a  different  category  of  being  from  that 
which  the  criterion  is  used  to  test,  but  is  so  connected 
with  the  quality  to  be  tested  as  to  be  a  good  sign  of  its 
presence — e.g.,  a  man's  dress  as  criterion  of  his  position 
in  society,  weight  as  a  test  of  quality. 

These  divisions  are  not  exclusive  of  one  another. 
The  weight  tests  might,  as  tests,  be  either  proper  or 
accidental.  They  are  a  proper  measure  of  weight,  but 
they  could  be  an  accidental  measure  of  quality  also,  if 
used — e.g.,  as  a  test  of  gold.  But,  as  primary,  a  criterion 
is  always  proper,  and  hence  we  shall  in  these  pages 
always  understand  by  a  primary  criterion  one  that  is  at 
the  same  time  primary  and  proper. 

NEED   OF  AN   ETHICAL  CRITERION 

All  sciences  need  criteria,  for  a  science  is  always  de 
igfwtis — and  to  make  known  that  which  is  unknown 
implies  the  use  of  criteria  of  truth.  But  in  Ethics  there 
is  a  special  need  of  criteria,  because,  whereas  light, 
sound,  heat,  mathematical  relations,  etc.,  can  be  per- 
ceived by  the  senses  or  the  intellect,  that  which  fonns 
the  subject-matter  of  moral  science — viz.,  direction  to 
the  fmal  end — is  not  immediately  perceivable  by  any 
faculty,  and  becomes  known  to  us  by  inference  only. 
Now,  all  mterence  requires  criteria.  Wc  need  no 
criterion  by  which  to  tell  whether  certain  roads  lead  to 
a  town  which  lies  under  our  very  eyes,  because  we  can 
see  whether  they  do  so.  But  if  we  do  not  see  the  town, 
if  we  merely  reason  that  it  musi  be  somewhere  near, 
then  we  have  to  use  criteria  like  sign-posts  or  the  state 
of  the  roads,  in  order  to  know  whether  a  certain  road 
leads  to  it.  In  Ethics  we  do  not  see  the  end  which 
primarily  concerns  us — ^viz.,  the  fmal  end  of  man.  We 
know    intellectually    in    what    that    fmal    end    consists. 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  127 

but  we  do  not  perceive  it  directly,  nor  do  we  see  always 
directly  what  acts  lead  to  it  ;  and,  therefore,  to  judge  of 
morahty  or  of  direction  to  the  final  end  we  need  criteria 
of  morality. 

We  shall  enquire,  then,  into — 

(a)  The  primary  criterion.* 

(6)  The  secondary  criteria. 

(c)  Certain  difficulties  to  our  doctrine  of  natural 
morals. 

(a)  The  Primary  Ethical  Criterion        ^ 

CONDITKWS   OF  THE   PRIMARY   CRITERION 

.r' 

Before  proceeding  to  discuss  directly  the  primary- 
Ethical  criterion  we  must  prepare  our  ground  by  ex- 
plaining from  the  meaning  and  function  of  a  primary 
moral  criterion  what  conditions  we  should  expect  it  to 
fulfil. 

(i)  The  primary  moral  criterion  must  be  absolutely 
tnie  and  reliable,  because  it  is  itself  the  final  measure  of 
moral  truth.  Unless  the  primary  criterion  be  above 
suspicion  there  could  be  no  ascertainable  moral  truth 
whatever. 

(2)  The  primary  criterion  must  be  stable  and  un- 
changeable ;  for  the  criterion  is  a  measure,  and  if  the 
measure  be  not  fixed  there  could  be  no  measurement. 
If,  for  instance,  the  original  measure  of  length  already 
spoken  of  were  capable  of  becoming  longer  or  shorter, 
or  at  least  of  changing  without  our  knowing  it,  or  being 
able  to  allow  for  such  change,  then  measurement  would 

*  We  seem  here  to  assume  that  the  primary  criterion  must  be  one. 
There  is  really  no  a  priori  reason  why  there  should  be  one  supreme 
primary  criterion.  The  primary  criterion  in  the  case  of  Geometry  is 
the  axiom,  and  axioms  arc  many  and  distinct.  So  we  might  expect 
a  priori  that  the  primary  criterion  of  morals  will  be  no;t  one  but  many. 
But  just  as  in  Geometry  there  is  in  a  certain  sense  only  one  criterion 
— viz.,  self-evident  geometrical  truth  (since  all  the  axioms  are  self- 
evident),  so  we  shall  find  that  the  primary  moral  criteria  all  reduce 
to  one — viz.,  to  something  which  is  common  to  the  various  individual 
Primary  criteria. 


128  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

become  absolutely  impossible.  So,  also,  if  there  is  to 
be  such  a  thing  as  testing  moral  truth,  the  final  test  of 
morals  must  be  unchangeable.  How  this  quality  of 
stability  in  the  criterion  may  be  consistent  with  develop- 
ment in  the  moral  code  we  shall  enquire  later.* 

(3)  The  moral  criterion  must  be  universal — that  is,  it 
must  hold  for  all  men.  The  reason  is  that,  since  all 
men  are  of  the  same  nature,  the  final  end  is  the  same 
for  all,  and  hence  the  final  test  of  direction  to  that  end 
must  be  the  same  for  all.  This  does  not  mean  that 
the  concrete  duty  of  one  man  will  be  the  same  as  that 
of  another.  It  means  that  the  duties  of  two  men 
situated  in  exactly  similar  circumstances  wij^be  the 
same. 

But,  besides  being  the  same  for  all,  the  primary  moral 
criterion  must  be  also  universal  in  the  sense  of  accessible 
to  all.  By  this  we  do  not  mean  that  all  men  must  have 
the  same  knowledge  of  it  or  be  able  to  analyse  it  to  the 
full,  but  that,  in  the  rough,  all  ordinary  men  should 
know  of  it.  The  reason  is  that  the  ordinary  man  must 
have  been  equipped  by  nature  with  some  means  of 
knowing  the  general  moral  law,  since  it  is  found  that 
the  rudest  savages,  even  apart  from  their  training, 
have  some  knowledge  of  morality.  Now,  such  know- 
ledge is  possible  for  those  only  who  have  some  access 
to  a  criterion  of  morals,  and  hence  the  criterion  must 
be  in  some  way  accessible  to  all. 

(4)  The  primary  criterion  must  be  practicable — i.e., 
applicable  to  reality.  If  the  criterion  be  not  applic- 
able to  real  human  life,  it  cannot  be  a  criterion  of  moral 
goodness  which  means  the  direction  of  the  living  indi- 
vidual man  to  his  last  end.f 


•  Pages  165  and  390. 

t  As  instance  of  a  criterion  eminently  unpractical  \vc  would  cilc 
Cardinal  Zigliara's  criterion  of  morality — objective  evidence.  I  am 
•Bleed,  for  instance,  how  one  is  to  know  whether  suicide  is  bad,  and  I 
answer  that  it  must  l)e  had  since  its  hadm-ss  is  objectively  evident. 
Now,  this  criterion  cannot  be  re^ardi'd  as  ]iracticabie  i)ecause  it  does 
not  give  the  information  required.     Jt  is  exactly  because  the  law  is 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  129 

These  are  the  four  main  conditions  of  the  primary 
moral  criterion. 


WHAT   IS    THE    PRIMARY   CRITERION    OF   MORAL   GOODNESS 
AND   BADNESS  ? 

We  go  on  now  to  enquire  into  the  nature  of  the 
primary  criterion.  An  act  is  morally  good  when  it  is 
directed  by  Reason  to  the  ultimate  end.  Now,  when 
does  an  act  tend  to  the  ultimate  end  ?  Unless  we  can 
find  some  link  between  "  act  "  and  "  final  end "  we 
could  not  answer  this  question,  for  we  have  no  direct 
knowledge  of  the  relation  between  act  and  final  end — 
i.e.,  we  do  not  see  the  end,  and  we  cannot  gather  from 
the  mere  conception  of  the  act  whether  it  is  directed  to 
the  final  end.  But  there  is  one  thing  that  we  shall 
have  no  difficulty  in  admitting  in  this  connection — viz., 
that  a  man  tends  to  the  ultimate  natural  end  when  he 
tends  to  the  immediate  natural  end  of  his  own  being  as 
man,  for  we  have  no  other  way  of  tending  to  the  final 
end  than  this.  What  tends  to  any  final  end  tends  to  it 
through  proximate  ends.  All  motion  is  a  motion  from 
proximate  to  final  end.  And  when  the  final  natural  end 
is  not  immediately  observed  we  know  that  we  tend  to 
it  when  we  know  that  we  move  towards  the  more 
proximate  natural  ends.* 

How,  then,  shall  we  determine  what  is  the  immediate 
end  of  man  ?  We  answer,  the  immediate  natural  end 
of  man  is  determined  in  exactly  the  same  way  as  we 
would  determine  the  immediate  end  of  any  other  natural 

not  evident  that  I  ask  what  is  the  law  ?  If  a  chemist  were  to  say — 
we  know  a  certain  gas  is  hydrogen  because  it  is  evident  it  is  hydrogen 
he  could  not  be  said  to  announce  a  practicable  criterion.  A  criterion 
is  a  test,  whereas  evidence  is  not  a  test.  What  is  evident  needs  no 
test.  But  when  a  chemist  tells  me  that  he  knows  a  gas  is  hydrogen 
by  the  colour  with  which  it  bums  he  has  then  indicated  a  practical 
test  and  a  criterion.     It  is  the  same  in  moral  matters. 

*  Besides,  we  should  mention  that  in  Ethics  we  determine  the  final 
end  by  determining  the  immediate  natural  ends  of  the  faculties.     This 
we  saw  in  our  chapter  on  the  Ends  of  Action. 
Vol.  1—9 


130  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

thing — such  as  a  tree  or  a  horse — for  the  mode  of  our 
knowledge  of  all  is  the  same.  Now,  the  immediate 
natural  end  of  any  being  depends  upon  the  ends  of  its 
various  faculties,  due  allowance  being  made  for  the 
natural  order  of  these  faculties.  For  example,  the 
immediate  natural  end  of  a  tree  is  determined  by  the 
ends  of  its  various  vegetative  functions.  Its  end  is  to 
grow  and  blossom  and  bear  fruit,  and  shed  its  seed. 
The  immediate  natural  end  of  man  is  determined  by  a 
consideration  of  the  ends  of  all  man's  functions — 
vegetative,  sensitive,  and  rational. 

The  question  arises,  therefore — How  are  we  to  deter- 
mine the  natural  ends  of  these  various  human  faculties 
and  appetites  ?  There  are  two  conceivable  ways  of 
learning  the  ends  or  objects  of  faculties,  capacities,  or 
appetites — either  a  posteriori,  i.e.,  by  experience,  or 
a  priori,  i.e.,  by  reasoning  from  the  nature  of  the  living 
thing  (nature  being  the  inner  principle  from  which  the 
faculties  or  appetites  of  a  thing  spring).  Now,  the 
second  of  these  alternatives  is  excluded  by  the  simple 
reflection  that  we  have  no  knowledge  of  this  inner 
nature  apart  from  the  operations  to  which  it  gives  rise 
and  the  ends  and  objects  of  these  operations.  We 
must,  then,  if  we  are  to  determine  the  ends  of  the 
faculties,  determine,  them  experhnentally — that  is,  by 
direct  observation  of  the  operations  of  these  faculties 
and  the  objects  of  these  operations.  It  would  seem, 
then,  that  we  determine  what  is  the  final  end  and  ^ 
whether  an  act  leads  to  it  by  determining  the  proper^.  1 
objects  of  the  natural  appetites.  And  since  these  ob-  \  \ 
jects  are  determined  not  a  priori  by  reasoning  from  any  N 
other  truths,  but  empirically  and  experimentally,  these 
objects  must  be  the  final  criterion  by  which  we  may 
know  whether  an  act  leads  to  our  ultimate  end  or  is 
good. 

In  the  foregoing  argument,  however,  we  are  certainly 
assuming  a  relation  to  exist  between  inner  nature,  on 
the  one  hand,  and  the  capacities  and  the  natural  ends 


# 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  131 

on  the   other,    on   which   we   think   some   remarks   aie 
necessary. 

In  general,  end  and  nature  defme  each  other.  Given 
the  natme  of  a  thing  we  can  predict  its  end.  Given 
the  end  we  may  infer  the  nature.  This  principle  we 
shall  most  easily  understand  by  taking  some  concrete 
examples.  Once  I  have  seen  the  materials,  the  form, 
and  the  inner  construction  of  a  boat-  that  is,  once  I 
come  to  know  its  nature — ^I  can  at  once  tell  with 
tolerable  certainty  the  end  it  is  meant  to  serve.  It 
is  from  the  nature  and  form  of  a  knife  that  I  infer  the 
object  it  is  meant  to  achieve.  So  from  the  nature  I 
may  infer  the  end.  On  the  other  hand,  given  the  end 
I  am  able  to  infer  what  the  nature  or  definition  is.  In 
ordinary  life  we  often  define  a  thing  by  the  end  it  is 
meant  to  serve.  A  boat  is  a  vessel  for  carrying  people 
or  merchandise  over  water.  A  watch  is  an  instrument 
for  telling  the  time.  And  not  only  do  we  infer  the 
general  definition,  but  we  are  able  to  go  into  details 
and  say  even  what  the  inner  structure  must  be  from  the 
mere  conception  of  the  end.  Did  I  know,  for  instance, 
the  end  of  a  camera — that  a  camera  was  meant  to  re- 
produce the  forms  or  surfaces  of  natural  objects — then, 
provided  I  knew  fully  the  laws  of  objects,  of  light,  and 
of  perspective,  I  should  be  able  to  tell  also  the  form 
which  the  camera  should  take  before  it  could  reproduce 
these  surfaces. 

These  examples  concern  artificial  objects.  But  the 
example  of  the  living  organism  is  even  better.  Had  I 
an  a  priori  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  a  tree  I  could 
also  tell  a  priori  what  is  the  natural  end  of  the  tree. 
If  I  could  see  its  inner  structure  and  the  laws  of  the 
fibres  I  could  tell  at  once  that  the  end  of  the  tree  was 
to  send  forth  leaves  and  to  blossom,  and  I  should  see 
that  these  ends  must  culminate  in  a  further  end,  the 
shedding  of  the  seed,  as  a  means  to  the  growth  of 
other  trees.  Also,  did  I  know  the  inner  nature  of  a 
bird,  I  should  be  able  at  once  to  predict  its  habits  and 


132  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  ends  it  would  attain.  On  the  other  hand,  given  the 
_^ends  to  be  achieved,  I  should  know  that  the  being  must 
'  /^>'*'*'^''*^d\  '^^  endowed  with  such  and  such  faculties  and  instincts 
^viv*^^^^*  — ^^^*  ^^'  ■'•  si^ould  be  able  to  tell  its  nature.  We  have 
pH  *'^"V^4a*W'  110  difficulty,  then,  in  accepting  the  general  Aristotelian 
"■y^Sajy^  principle  that  the  formal  and  final  principles  of  things 
"  define  each  other. 

Now,  which  of  these  two — nature  or  end — is,  de  facto, 
first  in  the  order  of  knowledge  ?  Do  we  first  know  the 
nature  of  a  thing,  and  from  that  determine  the  end  of 
its  capacities,  or  do  we  know  the  ends  of  things  by 
ordinary  observation,  and  from  the  consideration  of 
these  ends  determine  nature  ?  We  speak  here  of 
organised  beings  only,  for  in  Ethics  we  are  concerned 
only  with  the  end  and  nature  of  the  human  act.  We 
answer  as  before — first  in  the  order  of  knowledge  comes 
"  end  " — the  nature  of  the  agent  is  an  inference.  We 
know  nature  only  as  the  principle  of  certain  capacities 
in  the  agent,  and  capacities  are  known  through  acts, 
whilst  acts  in  their  turn  are  specified  by  ends  or  objects. 
Human  nature  is  that  principle  within  us  from  which 
spring  all  our  faculties— vegetative,  sensitive,  and 
rational.  And  we  know  that  we  are  possessed  of  these 
capacities  because  we  know  that  we  actually  feel  and 
think.  And  these  same  acts  of  feeling  and  thinking 
make  us  conscious  of,  and  put  us  into  relation  with, 
their  objects.  Hence  our  first  and  directest  knowledge 
is  that  of  the  objects  or  ends  of  action.  These  objects 
are  known  to  us  by  direct  examination  and  empirically, 
and  these  being  once  determined  we  can  safely  proceed 
to  specify  man's  faculties  and  nature. 

Through  the  objects  or  ends  of  our  various  faculties, 
therefore,  as  known  by  observation,  we  determine  the 
nature  of  man — not  vice  versa.  But,  as  we  have  already 
seen,  it  is  from  these  same  objects  or  ends  that  we  de- 
termine our  final  natural  end,  and  whether  an  action 
leads  to  it — that  is,  whether  an  action  is  morally  good 
or  evil. 


THESMORAL  CRITERIA  133 

Our  primary  criicrion,  therefore,  of  moral  goodness  is 
— the  natural  objects  or  ends  *  of  the  appetites.  Those 
objects  or  acts  to  which  we  are  dhected  by  natural 
appetites  are  good — they  lead  us  to  our  final  end,  and 
what  is  necessary  for  the  attainment  of  these  objects  is 
also  good.  Actions  that  oppose  our  natural  appetites 
and  their  objects  are  bad.  Whether  an  act  accords 
or  does  not  accord  with  the  natural  ends  of  the  faculties 
is  not,  indeed,  in  all  cases  determinable  with  the  same 
ease  or  accuracy.  Thus  it  is  possible,  from  a  single 
instance  or  even  without  instances  and  judging  by 
common  sense  only,  to  know  that  certain  actions  will 
not  promote  the  end  of  matrimony  which  is  the  con- 
tinuance of  the  race.  But  sometimes  we  have  to  use 
many  instances  before  we  can  come  to  a  definite  de- 
cision, as  in  the  case  of  marriage  between  persons  closely 
related  by  blood,  the '  evil  and  unnatural  character  of 
which  can  only  become  certain  after  many  instances 
have  been  examined.  But  in  so  far  as  certitude  is  ever 
found  these  ends  or  objects  of  our  natural  appetites 
are  the  primary  criterion  of  our  moral  judgments.f 

THE   PRIMARY   MORAL   CRITERION   APPLIED 

(i.)  We  must  now  give  instances  of  the  use  of  our 
primary  criterion.  The  first  and  most  obvious  instance 
of  the  use  of  the  primary  criterion  is  the  case  known  as 
the  natural  and  unnatural  use  of  a  faculty.X     A  faculty 

*  Briefly  we  may  say  that  "  the  natural  "  is  our  primary  criterion, 
since  the  natural  is  what  accords  with  our  natural  appetites,  wants  or 
needs.  Barter  or  exchange,  says  Aristotle  (Pol.  I.,  g,  6)  is  "  not  con- 
trary to  our  nature  since  it  is  needed  for  the  satisfaction  of  men's 
aatural  wants." 

f  "  Quia  vero  bonum  habet  rationem  finis  malum  autem  rationem 
contrarii,  inde  est  quod  omnia  ilia  ad  quae  homo  habet  naturalem 
inclinationem  ratio  naturaliter  apprehendit  ut  bona  et  per  consequens 
ut  opere  prosequenda,  et  contraria  eorum  ut  mala  et  vitanda  "  ("  S. 
Theol.,"  I.,  II.,  Q.  XCIV.,  Art.  2). 

X  This  teaching  does  not  involve  any  theory  as  to  the  distinction 
of  the  faculties  from  the  soul  itself.  It  merely  implies  that  we  have 
natural  capacities. 


134  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

is  used  naturally  when  it  is  used  in  such  a  way  as  is  con- 
«  ducive  to  the  realisation  of  its  own  end.     The  unnatural 

use  of  a  faculty  is  its  use  in  such  a  way  as  to  oppose  its 
own  end.  For  clearness'  sake  we  shall  confine  ourselves 
to  the  case  of  the  unnatural  use  of  a  faculty.  In  order 
that  a  faculty  be  used  unnaturally  two  conditions  must 
be  fulfilled,  viz.— (i)  the  faculty  itself  must  he  used,  and 
(2)  it  must  he  used  for  an  unnatural  end.  The  misuse  of 
a  faculty  is  not  the  same  thing,  then,  as  injuring  it  or 
rendering  it  useless.  Misuse  means  the  perverse  use  of 
the  faculty — its  being  made  to  perform  its  own  function 
specifically  and  directly,  but  in  opposition  to  the  pur- 
pose which  nature  intended  it  to  fulfil.  Thus,  to  use 
the  sexual  faculty  in  such  a  way  as  to  frustrate  its  end, 
which  is  the  continuance  of  the  race,  is  to  act  against 
the  natural  purpose  of  the  faculty  and  to  violate  one's 
own  nature  and  the  law  of  nature.* 

Again,  there  is  the  case  of  l^ang.  The  natural  end  of 
the  faculty  of  speech  is  the  expression  of  inner  convic- 
tion to  another,  f  But  if  speech  be  used  to  express  what 
i-^  we  believe  to  be  false,  the  faculty  is  used  unnaturally, 
and  the  act  is  morally  bad.  And  as  every  lie  involves 
[40  this  perverse  use  of  speech,  the  lie  is  intrinsically  wrong 
and  unjustifiable. 

Again,  there  is  the  case  of  suicide.  In  suicide  the 
whole  appetent  nature  of  man  with  all  his  faculties  is 
used  unnaturally.  For  every  appetite  and  capacity  in 
man  tends  mediately  or  immediately  to  the  maintenance 
and  perfection  of  the  agent, J  whilst  suicide  is  the  use 
of  the  will  and  other  capacities  to  the  destruction  of 
the  agent.  The  natural  end,  then,  of  man's  appetitive 
nature  is  here,  as  in  the  other  instances  given,  our  test 
of  good  and  evil. 


•The  case  of  sterility  is  quite  different  from  this.  There  the  im- 
possibility of  realising  nature's  end  is  not  due  to  the  individual  in 
question,  but  to  certain  conditions  over  which  jhtsous  have  no  control. 

f  This  wc  shall  prove  in  the  second  part  of  the  present  work. 

X  Sco  11,  52  for  proof  of  tliis  proposition. 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  135 

These  examples  will  show  what  is  meant  by  the  un- 
natural use  of  a  faculty.  It  means,  not  injury  to  the 
faculty  from  outside,  as  when  one  man  hurts  another 
so  that  a  faculty  cannot  be  exercised,  but  "  violation 
from  within  " — i.e.,  the  use  of  the  faculty  for  an  un- 
natural end. 

This  is  the  first  and  most  obvious  example  of  the  use 
of  our  primary  criterion.  The  rule  not  to  use  a  faculty 
in  such  a  way  as  to  oppose  the  realisation  of  its  natural 
end  is  universally  and  absolutely  valid.  There  is  not  a 
single  exception  to  it.  To  use  a  faculty  in  such  a  way 
as  to  make  its  natural  end  impossible  of  realisation  is 
intrinsically  unnatural  and  bad.  There  could  be  no 
more  direct  and  imequivocal  \iolation  of  nature  than 
this.  It  is  the  complete  perversion  ot  nature's  purposes 
and  needs. 


RANGE   OF   APPLICATION    OF  THIS   CRITERION 

The  reading  of  the  cases  just  mentioned  will  at  once  raise 
the  enquiry  to  what  kinds  of  moral  problem  the  use  of  our 
primary  criterion  extends — whether  it  is  used  only  in  con- 
nection with  problems  like  those  just  given,  which,  after 
all,  rarely  arise  for  discussion,  or  whether  it  is  also  used  in 
connection  with  the  more  ordinary  difficulties  which  confront 
us  in  our  daily  lives.  The  question  is  important,  and  we 
may  treat  it  here  before  passing  to  the  second  portion  of 
our  discussion  on  the  primary  criterion.  Our  answer  is  : — 
the  fundamental  criterion  will  naturally  be  most  used  in 
the  discussion  of  the  fundamental  problems  of  Ethics — other 
moral  discussions  necessitate  as  a  rule  no  appeal  to  this 
criterion.  Thus  there  are  innumerable  problems  arising  on 
the  duties  of  parents  to  each  other  and  to  their  children 
which  necessitate  no  appeal  to  the  fundamental  criterion. 
But  should  the  most  fundamental  of  all  such  problems  be 
raised,  viz.,  why  marriage  and  the  family  are  necessary, 
then  we  must  appeal  to  the  primary  criterion,  the  natural 
end  of  the  sexual  powers.  Again,  problems  relating  to  the 
duties  of  citizens  may  involve  no  further  question  than  the 
meaning  of  a  particular  law  or  whether  sovereignty  resides 
in  this  person  or  in  that.  But  should  the  fundamental 
question  be  raised  why  there  is  such  a  thing  as  political 


136  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

authority  at  all,  or  why  the  State  is  necessary,  we  must  then 
make  appeal  to  our  human  faculties  and  their  objects,  and 
show  that  the  State  is  necessary  for  the  full  development 
of  man  within  the  range  of  the  natural  faculties. 

A  word  will  here  be  necessary  on  the  special  question  of 
justice  which  will  so  largely  occupy  our  attention  in  the  do- 
main of  Applied  Ethics.  For  the  most  part  problems  in 
justice  necessitate  no  appeal  to  the  primary  criterion.  Often 
the  question  involved  is  one  of  mere  fact,  e.g.,  whether  goods 
have  been  justly  acquired,  and  often  there  is  question  of 
some  mere  derived  principle,  e.g.,  whether  goods  lost  may  be 
retained  by  the  finder,  or  whether  the  seller  of  goods  should 
manifest  hidden  defects.  In  these  cases  the  criterion  followed 
will  consist,  in  the  first  case,  of  the  evidence  adduced,  and,  in 
the  second,  of  whatever  principles  are  advanced  to  elucidate 
the  problem  under  review.  It  is  only  in  discussions  con- 
cerning the  ultimate  problems  of  justice,  viz.,  why  there 
is  such  a  thing  as  commutative  justice  at  all,  or  why  I  should 
give  to  every  man  his  own,  or  why  I  may  not  treat  men  as  I 
wish,  that  appeal  is  made  to  the  objects  of  the  natural 
faculties.  For  the  first  problem  of  justice  consists  in  showing, 
that  men  are  by  nature  equal,  that  they  are  never  mere 
means  to  one  another,  and  cannot  be  used  merely  for  one 
another's  pleasure.  And  since  this  relation  of  equality  is 
based  on  the  fact  that  all  men  have  the  same  faculties, 
subtending  the  same  objects  and  the  same  final  end,*  it  is 
clear  that  justice  like  all  other  departments  of  Ethics,  is  in 
the  last  resort  made  to  rest  upon  the  primary  criterion.  In 
general  then  it  may  be  stated  that  the  primary  criterion 
relates  immediately  to  the  primary  problems  only — mediately, 
of  course,  and  indirectly  it  covers  the  rest  as  well. 

The  range  of  application  of  the  primary  criterion 
being  thus  explained  we  now  go  on  to  a  fuller  determina- 
tion of  the  use  of  this  criterion.  Up  to  the  present  we 
have  spoken  as  if  the  use  of  the  primary  criterion  con- 
sisted simply  in  determining  the  ends  of  particular 
faculties.  But  there  are  problems  in  Ethics  that  de- 
pend rather  on  the  relation  between  the  objects  of 
faculties  than  on  the*  objects  themselves,  and  these 
problems  it  will  be  necessary  to  illustrate  here.     They 

•  &•<•  Vol    11  ,  jvi-to  8a, 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA      ^  137 

form  a  second  class  of  instances  of  the  use  of  our  primary 
criterion. 

(II.)  The  natural  order  of  the  j acuities  depends  on  the 
natural  order  of  their  objects.  Each  faculty  has  its 
natural  object,  and  between  the  objects  of  the  faculties 
there  is  a  certain  natural  order.  This  natural  order  is 
one  of  the  greater  or  less — i.e.,  of  greater  or  less  breadth 
of  object  subtended  by  the  faculty.*  Thus  the  object 
of  the  vegetative  faculty  is  a  comparatively  narrow  one 
— it  is,  as  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  terms  it,  corpus  pro- 
prium.  The  object  of  the  sensitive  faculties  is  much 
wider  ;  it  embraces  as  much  of  the  sensitive  world  ^s 
is  materially  present  to  us  and  knowable.  Wider  still 
is  the  object  of  intellect,  which  embraces  the  whole 
world,  present,  past,  and  future,  material  and  im- 
material. "  Intellectus  fit  omnia  "  is  Aristotle's  trite 
description  of  it.  This  difference  in  breadth  of  object 
subtended  by  the  faculties  establishes  between  these 
faculties  certain  relations  of  supremacy  and  inferiority, 
and  makes  of  them  a  hierarchical  order  corresponding 
to  the  natural  hierarchy  of  ends  they  serve.  Amongst 
appetites  in  particular  (for  they  are  the  faculties  with 
which  we  are  particularly  concerned  in  Ethics)  the 
lowest  appetite  will  be  the  vegetative  ;  the  next  is  the 
sensitive  appetite  ;  the  highest,  or  the  master  appetite 
(that  which  depends  on  Reason,  and  whose  object  em- 
braces the  objects  of  all  the  appetites)  is  the  "  will."  It 
will  easily  be  seen,  too,  that  in  man  the  higher  of  these 
faculties  is  built  upon  the  lower — the  sensitive  upon  the 
vegetative  and  the  rational  upon  the  sensitive — just  as 
a  house  is  built  upon  its  foundations  and  the  higher 
storey  upon  the  lower.  And  as  the  foundations  may 
be  regarded  as  means  and  the  house  as  end,  so  the  lower 
faculty  may  be  regarded  as  means  to  the  higher.  But 
this   order  of   subordination  between  the   faculties   de- 

*  "  Genera  vero  potcntiarum  animae  distinguuntur  secundum 
objecta  :  quanto  enim  potentia  est  altior  tanto  respicit  universalius 
objectum  "  ("  S.  TheoL,"  I.,  Q.  LXXVIII.,  Art.  i). 


138  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

pends  upon  the  relative  width  of  objects  which  they 
subtend,  and,  therefore,  the  width  of  objects  subtended 
by  the  faculties  is  the  norm  by  which  problems  are 
solved  which  depend  upon  the  relations  of  the  faculties. 

Now  it  might  be  thought  that  problems  of  the  kind, 
and  they  are  many,  must  necessarily  be  very  difficult 
and  abstruse,  since  plainly  it  would  be  no  easy  matter 
to  determine  mathematically  the  exact  difference  in 
width  of  objects  which  are  subtended  by  any  pair  of 
faculties.  But  this  is  not  the  case.  For  in  such  prob- 
lems as  arise  in  Ethics  it  is  not  necessary  to  determine 
the  exact  number  of  objects  subtended  by  a  faculty, 
much  less  to  determine  differences  between  the  various 
faculties  singly.  It  is  necessary  only  to  deal  with 
groups  of  faculties,  and  the  differences  between  the 
groups,  as  will  be  seen  from  the  following  examples, 
are  easily  determined.  We  do  not,  e.g.,  require  to  com- 
pare one  sensitive  appetite  with  another.  We  compare 
the  whole  group  of  vegetative  with  the  whole  group  of 
sensitive,  and  these  again  with  Reason,  and  our  claim  is 
that  a  group  of  lesser  width  is  naturally  subordinate  to 
one  of  greater  width,  while  all  the  faculties,  whatever 
their  objects  may  be,  are  subordinate  to  the  interests 
of  the  whole  man. 

As,  therefore,  in  any  organism  each  part  has  its  own 
end  distinct  from  that  of  other  parts,  yet  serves  certain 
other  parts,  and  as  the  end  of  each  part  is  subordinated 
to  the  end  of  the  whole,  so  every  faculty  in  us  has  its 
own  end  or  object,  but  is  subordinate  to  the  \\ider 
faculty  which  contains  it  and  to  the  whole  organism, 
since  the  end  of  the  whole  organism  includes  the  end  of 
each  part.  From  these  relations  we  derive  the  laws  of 
organisms.  And  these  laws  give  rise  to  moral  precepts. 
For,  just  as  in  a  machine,  it  would  be  irrational  to  use  a 
screw  to  the  detriment  of  the  shaft  which  the  screw  is 
meant  to  maintain  in  its  place,  so  also  it  would  be  un- 
natural to  use  a  vegetative  or  sensitive  faculty  to  the 
destruction  of  intellect,  or  to  blot  out  the  intellect  for 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  139 

the  sake  of  administering  to  those  lower  faculties  some 
momentary  enjoyment.  So  drunkenness  is  unlawful, 
since  in  it  the  intellect  is  suspended  or  obscured  *  for 
the  sake  of  securing  an  unnecessary  momentary  organic 
pleasure.  But  it  would  be  quite  lawful  to  obscure  or 
suspend  the  intellect  temporarily  either  for  some  per- 
maihnt  good  accruing  to  the  sensitive  or  material  parts, 
or  more  especially  for  some  good  accruing  to  the  whole 
man,  for  each  part  has  its  own  value,  and  the  end  of 
the  whole  man  includes  the  ends  of  the  parts.  It  would 
be  natural  and  lawful,  for  instance,  violently  to  be  made 
unconscious,  either  by  means  of  ether  or  alcohol,  in 
order  to  get  relief  from  great  physical  pain  or  to  get  a 
limb  cut  off  which  endangers  life,  for  in  such  an  act 
the  natural  order  is  observed.  Nay,  it  would  be  lawful 
to  suspend  consciousness  for  the  mere  purpose  of  re- 
moving some  bodily  disfigurement  however  small,  for, 
though  the  lower  part  is  subjected  to  a  higher,  yet 
the  lower  parts  have  their  own  value,  and  a  temporary 
suspension  of  a  higher  faculty  in  order  to  secure  a  per- 
manent good  in  a  lower  is  quite  in  accordance  with  the 
order  and  requirements  of  nature.  Briefly,  part  may 
be  means  to  the  whole,  yet  part  has  its  own  value,  too, 
and  its  value  must  be  taken  account  of  in  estimating 
the  order  of  our  faculties  and  their  subjection  to  one 
another.  But  in  all  these  cases  the  criterion  on  which 
we  build  our  moral  judgment  is  none  other  than  the 
,  objects  of  the  faculties  concerned,  and  their  natural 
relations  to  one  another. 

In  the  second  part  of  our  work  we  shall  consider  this 
subject  of  the  primary  criterion  and  its  applications  more 
closel}'  than  is  now  possible  for  us. 


*  In  sleep  the  suspension  of  our  intellects  is  itself  natural  and 
necessary  for  life.  The  suspension  of  Reason  spoken  of  in  the  text 
is  the  violent  and  unnatural  blotting  out  of  Reason  effected  by  ether 
or  alcohol.  St.  Thomas  gives  another  explanation  of  the  wrongfulness 
of  drunkenness.  "  Drunkenness,"  he  saj's,  "  in  blotting  out  Reason, 
thereby  subjects  us  to  the  risk  of  sin,  Reason  being  our  guiding 
faculty." — See  vol.  II,  p.  62. 


140  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

{b)  The  Secondary  or  Derivative  Criteria 

As  we  have  already  explained,  a  derivative  criterion 
is  dependent  on  the  primary  criterion,  and  is  applied 
in  place  of  the  primary  when  the  primary  criterion  itself 
cannot  be  used.  For  sometimes,  on  account  of  the  com- 
plicated reasoning  involved,  we  are  not  able  merely  by 
considering  the  ends  or  objects  of  our  faculties  to  say 
whether  a  particular  act  is  natural  or  unnatural,  good  or 
bad.  In  such  cases  we  can  often  have  recourse  to  other 
criteria  which  tell  us  indirectly  whether  an  act  is  natural 
or  unnatural,  from  a  consideration,  namely,  of  some 
necessary  consequence  or  concomitant  of  natural  or  un- 
natural action — something  which  a  natural  act  either 
involves  or  excludes.  Some  of  those  criteria  are  soi 
intimately  connected  with  the  primary  that  the  cer- 
tainty they  afford  is  practically  equal  to  that  given  by 
the  primary  criterion  itself.  Others  are  connected  with 
it  less  closel}^  and  these  either  give  us  a  low  degree  of 
certainty  or  only  a  high  degree  of  probability.  But 
they  are  genuine  criteria  if  they  yield  us  anything  ap- 
proaching certainty  on  the  moral  quality  of  actions. 

(l)    FIRST  derivative  CRITERION — GENERAI   INJURY  WITH 
GENERAL   OBSERVANCE 

The  first  of  these  derivative  criteria  is  that  known  as 
the  principle  of  "  general  injury  with  general  observ- 
ance," and  its  opposite  "  general  utility  with  general 
observance."  That  act  is  good,  we  say,  which,  if  it 
were  raised  to  a  general  line  of  conduct,  should  neces- 
sarily work  out  happily  for  the  race  ;  that  act  is  morally 
evil  which,  if  it  were  raised  to  a  general  line  of  conduct, 
should  necessarily  prove  injurious  to  the  race. 

The  value  of  this  criterion  will  be  evident  if  we  con- 
sider that  it  results  from  a  far-reaching  mctaphj'sica! 
truth — the  truth,  namely,  that  "  nature  never  tends  to 
its  own  destruction."     We  may  regard  this  principle  as 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  141 

almost  a  truism  and  as  borne  out  both  by  Reason  and 
by  common  experience.  Let  the  parts  of  a  machine  all 
work  together  according  to  the  manner  of  their  original 
design,  let  them  not  be  worn  out  or  displaced,  and  the 
machine  will  work  easily,  smoothly,  and  well.  Let  all 
the  conditions  of  nature  be  observed  in  eating,  let  no 
organ  be  put  to  a  work  which  is  not  naturally  its  own, 
and  let  each  organ  perform  its  normal  and  natural 
functions,  and  then  only  one  effect  can  follow — viz., 
health  and  well-being.  Under  such  conditions  as  these 
injury  or  decay  becomes  impossible.  But  let  any  organ 
be  put  to  work  under  conditions  that  are  not  natural  to 
it,  and  the  result  is  destruction.  And  as  we  thus  reason 
about  a  machine  or  the  physical  functions  of  the  human 
body,  so  we  can  reason  similarly  about  the  exercise  of 
our  other  natural  faculties.  Let  a  man  use  his  faculties 
as  nature  intends  they  should  be  used,  and  it  is  impos- 
sible that  their  exercise  should  not  promote  his  welfare. 
And  the  welfare  of  which  we  are  now  speaking  is  not 
the  welfare  that  will  follow  upon  the  attainment  of  the 
ultimate  end,  but  our  physical  and  mental,  as  well  as 
our  social  welfare  here  below.  To  work  naturally, 
therefore,  is  to  work  well ;  to  work  unnaturally  is  to 
work  to  destruction. 

Any  course  of  conduct,  therefore,  that  works  destruc-\\^ 
tion  generally,  cannot  he  the  course  of  nature.  We  say  ' 
"  generally,"  for  from  a  single  act  and  its  consequences 
it  would  be  impossible  to  say  whether  an  act  is  natural 
or  unnatural.  In  individual  acts  there  are  always  acci- 
dents and  unessential  circumstances,  and  the  good  and 
evil  in  such  cases  may  be  the  result  not  of  the  act  itself 
as  such,  but  of  the  accidents  or  circumstances  incident 
to  its  performance.  And,  therefore,  it  would  be  wrong 
to  conclude  that  because  a  particular  kind  of  action  in 
a  particular  case  was  attended  by  evil  consequences, 
that  kind  of  action  must  be  unnatural.  But  humanity 
at  large  is  subject  to  no  accidents,  and  effects  that 
follow  upon  a  certain  kind  of  action  at  all  times  and 


142  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

in  all  circumstances  must  follow  not  from  the  circum 
stances  but  from  the  act  considered  in  itself.  And 
hence  an  act  that  always  works  ill — i.e.,  an  act  which, \ 
when  made  a  general  line  of  conduct,  must  injure  man-' 
kind — ^must  be  discordant  with  human  nature  and  with 
the  ends  of  nature.  We  should  remark,  however,  that 
'  injury  "  is  a  surer  criterion  of  evil  than  "  benefit  " 
s  of  good ;  it  is  evident  that  nature  reacts  more  surely 
and  more  promptly  on  the  unnatural  than  it  responds  to 
the  natural.  A  little  poison  will  injure  a  man,  whereas 
much  good  food  may  not  increase  his  health.  And 
hence  we  prefer  to  give  as  our  expression  of  this  present 
criterion  the  negative  formula  that  "  what  brings  injury 
to  the  race  when  raised  to  a  general  Hne  of  conduct  is 
bad."  In  order,  then,  to  make  prominent  the  negative 
which,  as  we  have  seen,  is  also  the  stronger  side,  we  shall 
call  our  criterion,  for  want  of  a  better  name,  the  principle 
of  "  general  injury  with  general  observance." 

This  is  the  first  of  the  derivative  criteria,  and  as  a  .. 
criterion  it  is  absolutely  incontrovertible,  for  it  rests  on  | 
a  fundamental  truth  of  Metaphysics — ^viz.,  that  nature 
tends  to  maintain  itself,  and  that,  consequently,  what- 
ever tends  to  general  destruction,  and  tends  to  it  irre- 
spective of  particular  circumstances,  is  unnatural. 

The  question  arises — is  this  criterion  intrinsic  or  ex- 
trinsic ?  We  reply — sometimes  the  effects  of  an  action 
are  coincident  with  its  natural  end  or  object,  and  then 
the  criterion  is  not  only  intrinsic,  but  is,  properly 
speaking,  an  application  of  the  primary  criterion.  Thus 
marriages  between  persons  not  related  by  blood  are, 
other  conditions  being  fulfilled,  natural,  because  by 
them  are  secured  the  maintenance  and  welfare  of  the 
race.  On  the  other  hand,  marriages  between  blood- 
relations  arc  unnatural  because,  instead  of  promoting 
the  ends  of  matrimony,  they  bring  injury  to  the  race. 
But  here  the  good  and  the  bad  effects  are  respectively 
coincident  with  the  natural  end  or  object  of  matrimony 
and  its  opposite,  and  hence  in  arguing  from  the  effects 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  143 

we  are  arguing  from  the  end  itself — that  is,  we  are 
making  use  of  the  primary  criterion.  But  in  the  case 
of  drunkenness,  whereas  the  intrinsic  evil  of  the  act 
consists  in  the  fact  that  Reason  is  temporarily  suspended 
for  no  just  purpose,  the  evil  effects  of  drunkenness  on 
the  race  at  large  are  rather  an  evil  of  body  than  of  mind, 
or,  at  all  events,  they  are  different  in  character  from  the 
evil  which  makes  of  drunkenness  a  specific  sin  ;  and, 
therefore,  though  we  might  use  these  effects  as  a 
secondary  criterion  in  order  to  determine  whether 
drunkenness  is  a  sin,  they  could  never  be  more  than  an 
extrinsic  criterion. 

In  general,  then,  this  secondary  criterion,  though  most 
reliable  as  a  criterion,  is  extrinsic. 

Conditions  of  Application  of  this  Criterion. 

The  general  condition  of  application  of  the  present 
criterion  is  that  any  evil  consequences  which  serve  as 
the  criterion  of  the  inherent  evil  of  an  act  must  be  such 
as  spring  from  the  act  itself  specifically  and  necessarily, 
and  not  as  a  result  of  some  adjunct  to  or  circumstance 
of  the  act.  This  general  condition  includes  the  follow- 
ing three : — 

(i)  The  bad  effects  from  which  we  judge  must  not  '| 
depend  upon  free  will.     They  must  follow  as  a  necessary    ' 
consequence  of  the  act  itself.     For  instance,  it  might  be  \^ 
argued  that  mixed  education  is  intrinsically  unnatural   ^ 
because  social  ruin  would  be  sure  to  follow  were  the   ^, 
sexes  educated  together  generally.     But  this  is  not  an  J 
application  of  our  present  criterion,  because  the  evils 
that  follow  in  the  case  result,  not  from  the  fact  that  the 
sexes   are   educated   together,    but   from   the   fact   that 
people  would  of  their  own  free  will  and  through  weak- 
ness take   advantage  of  the  relations  thus  established 
for  perverse  purposes.     The  system,  therefore,  of  mixed 
education,  though  it  may  be  condemned  on  other  scores, 
cannot  be  condemned  on  the  ground  that  it  is  intrinsi- 


144  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

caUy  unnatural.  And  not  being  intrinsically  unnatural, 
it  is  not  intrinsically  bad,  and  can  be  allowed  in  certain 
circumstances  and  with  certain  precautions.  Other  ex- 
amples of  this  first  condition  will  readily  suggest  them- 
selves. 

{:^)  The  evij  effects  must  be  the  result  of  the  act  itself 
and  not  of  the  absence  of  that  which  the  act  replaces. 
The  following  is  an  interesting  example  of  this  dis- 
tinction :  If  all  men  were  to  become  pawnbrokers  social 
life  would  necessarily  decay.  Is,  therefore,  pawn- 
broking  unnatural  ?  Certainly  not,  because  in  a  society 
in  which  all  men  have  become  pawnbrokers  the  decay 
that  ensues  is  explained,  not  by  the  fact  that  all  men 
have  become  pawnbrokers,  but  by  the  fact  that  there 
are  now  no  other  trades  in  existence — by  the  fact, 
namely,  that  there  are  no  grocers,  no  merchants,  no 
bakers.  If,  however,  all  men  became  pawnbrokers,  and 
at  the  same  time  carried  on  some  other  business,  then 
there  is  no  reason  why  the  evils  suggested  above  should 
arise.  The  evil  effects  when  they  do  arise  spring,  not 
from  pawnbroking,  but  from  the  absence  of  those  trades 
which  universal  pawnbroking  would  replace. 

(3)  The  evil  effect  must  not  be  the  result  of  too  much 
or  too  little  in  the  action,  but  of  the  act  itself  as  such.  ;| 
Thus,  if  all  men  were  to  drink  whiskey  at  all  hours  and 
in  unlimited  quantities,  the  race  would  soon  disappear 
from  the  earth.  But  the  use  of  whiskey  is  not  thereby 
unnatural.  For  the  effect  is  due  to  the  intemperate  use 
not  to  the  use  of  whiskey.  If  all  men  drank  moderately 
no  evil  effects  need  follow. 

We  have  drawn  out  these  conditions  separately  be- 
cause of  their  importance,  though  in  reality  they  are 
all  contained  in  the  one  condition — that  the  evils  must 
follow  from  the  act  itself  specifically.  Fully  announced, 
therefore,  the  principle  takes  some  such  form  as  this — ' 
"  Any  act  which  when  raised  to  a  general  line  of  conduct 
will,  owing  to  its  specific  character,  injure  humanity,  is 
intrinsically  unnatural  and  bad." 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  145 

The  present  criterion  manifestative  only,  not  constitu- 
tive of  morality. 

Now,  as  the  one  function  of  the  criterion  in  question 
is  to  help  us  to  know  whether  a  human  act  is  natural  or 
unnatural,  it  will  be  easily  seen  that  the  criterion  as 
such  is  only  manifestative  of  morality  not  constitutive  of 
it — in  other  words,  that  an  act  is  bad  not  because  on 
being  raised  to  a  general  line  of  conduct  it  works  destruc- 
tion, but  if  and  in  case  that  on  being  raised  to  a  general 
line  of  conduct  it  works  destruction — that  is,  we  know 
that  an  act  which  brings  about  evil  consequences  must 
be  unnatural  and  intrinsically  bad,  but  it  is  not  intrin- 
sically bad  because  of  these  consequences.  No  doubt  it 
is  intrinsically  wrong  to  inflict  injury  on  humanity,  and 
one  of  our  special  duties  is  to  avoid  such  injury.  But  at 
present  we  have  nothing  to  do  with  any  special  dut}-. 
We  are  asking  what  it  is  that  reveals  the  moral  badness 
of  acts  in  general  ?  And  we  say  that  an  act  is  bad 
because  it  is  unnatural  and  because  it  does  not  lead  the 
will  that  performs  it  to  the  ultimate  end  ;  but  we  know 
that  an  act  is  unnatural  through  its  effects,  and,  there- 
fore, this  criterion  manifests  to  us  the  moral  character 
action  ;  but  it  does  not  constitute  the  moral  character 
i.e.,  it  does  not  make  an  act  good  or  bad. 

From  this  a  most  important  conclusion  follows — ^viz., 
that  an  act  which,  if  raised  to  a  general  line  of  conduct, 
would  work  evil  for  the  race  is  bad,  not  merely  when  it 
is  generally  adopted  and  when  it  does  actually  work  evil 
but  in  each  particular  case  in  which  it  is  performed,  and 
whether  evil  effects  actually  follow  in  the  particular  case 
or  do  not.  The  importance  of  this  conclusion  cannot 
be  over-rated.  And  the  reason  of  it  is  very  plain. 
The  criterion  is  manifestative  of,  not  constitutive  of, 
morality.  The  act  is  bad  not  because  it  works  evil 
effects  on  the  race,  but  because  it  is  unnatural,  and 
leads  away  from  the  ultimate  end.  Were  it  bad  because 
it  affects  the  race  prejudicially,  then  it  would  be  evil 
when  such  evil  effects  do  actually  follow,  and  in  no  other 

Vol.  I — lo 


re- 

-I 


146  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

case.  Where,  however,  the  injurious  effect  is  only  a 
sign  of  moral  badness,  the  act  will  still  remain  bad  even 
in  cases  in  which  for  some  reason  or  other  the  effect 
does  not  happen  to  follow,  for  the  badness  does  not 
depend  upon  and  is  not  constituted  by  the  effect.  We 
can  find  plenty  of  suggestive  examples  of  such  a  distinc- 
tion even  in  the  physical  sciences.  We  know  that  a 
certain  substance  is  poisonous  by  the  fact  that  if  a 
sufficient  dose  of  it  be  taken  it  kills.  But  once  we  have 
established  that  fact  we  may  still  maintain  that  this  is 
a  poisonous  substance  even  though  we  should  meet 
cases  in  which  for  some  reason  or  other  {v.g.,  because 
the  patient  by  careful  dosing  has  rendered  his  system 
poison-proof  to  this  substance)  the  bad  effect  does  not 
actually  follow.  Again,  to  alter  the  class  of  example, 
we  know  that  the  waves  of  the  sea  must  have  a  certain 
intrinsic  energy  because  of  the  ravages  they  effect  on 
the  coast.  Should,  however,  we  see  a  coast  that,  on 
account  of  its  position,  is  proof  against  the  waves,  we 
still  may  attribute  to  the  waves  the  same  intrinsic 
energy  as  before.  In  these  two  cases  the  effects  are 
only  manifestative  of  a  certain  quality,  and,  therefore, 
once  by  means  of  the  effects  we  have  established  the 
certain  existence  of  this  quality  or  nature,  we  must 
still  assert  this  quality  or  nature  even  though  the  effect 
does  not  happen  to  follow  in  a  particular  case. 

So  also  in  the  case  of  moral  science,  we  know  that 
stealing  is  bad  intrinsically  and  always,  and  one*  of 
our  reasons  for  thinking  so  is  that  social  life  would  be- 
pome  absolutely  impossible  were  stealing  made  generally 
allowable.  For  a  similar  reason  we  know  that  a  lie  is 
bad.  But  once  it  has  been  made  evident  to  us  through 
these  effects  that  stealing  and  lying  are  intrinsically 
bad  acts  we  need  not  afterwards  in  individual  cases 


•  The  reader  must  not  conclude,  because  \vc  apply  to  a  particular 
class  of  conduct  one  of  tin;  secondary  ciitcria  tliut  llicreforc  wo  arc 
unable  tc  u»c  the  j)rimary.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  both  stealing,'  ami 
lying  are  most  interesting  illustrationH  of  the  primary  ethical  criterion. 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  147 

set  ourselves  to  consider  the  actual  effects  in  particular 
circumstances  ;  for  the  bad  effects  that  we  observed 
were  merely  an  extrinsic  test  of  the  intrinsic  evil  of  these 
acts,  they  were  not  themselves  part  of  the  intrinsic  evil 
of  these  acts  ;  had  any  other  test  presented  itself  we 
need  not  have  considered  these  effects  at  all.  Hence 
the  lie  remains  bad  always,  even  though  in  a  particular 
case  no  evil  results  ensue  either  for  the  race  or  for  the 
individual.  So  also  we  know  that  nature  forbids  matri- 
mony amongst  people  closely  related  by  blood,  and  we 
know  this  by  the  fact  that  marriages  largely  entered 
into  amongst  blood  relations  are  followed  by  racial  de- 
generation. But  once  we  have  established  this  law  of 
the  evil  of  such  marriages  we  know  that  they  are  in- 
trinsically unnatural,  and  that,  therefore,  they  are  for- 
bidden in  every  case.*  Briefly,  the  present  criterion  is 
manifestative  of  morality,  not  constitutive  of  it,  and, 
therefore,  any  moral  truths  that  are  derived  from  a  con- 
sideration of  the  evil  consequences  hold  good  even 
when,  through  some  accidental  condition  which  may  or 
may  not  be  known  to  us,  the  effects  happen  not  to 
follow. 

It  occurs  to  us  that  from  the  beginning  of  the  present 
section  readers  may  possibly  have  been  exercised  about 
the  question  how  this  criterion  of  morality  drawn  from 
the  consequences  of  action  stands  related  to  another 
theory  which  we  shall  have  occasion  to  speak  of  later — 
namely,  the  theory  of  Utilitarianism,  This  question  we 
are  now  in  a  position  to  answer.  Utilitarians,  like  our- 
selves, insist  that  the  consequences  of  an  act  are  a 
criterion  of  right  and  wrong  in  human  action.  But  the 
two  theories  are  nevertheless  radically  distinct  and 
opposed,  as  will  be  seen  from  the  following  brief  com- 
parison.    In  the  first  place,  utilitarians  insist  that  the 


•  We  do  not  here  enter  fully  into  the  question  of  consanguinity 
and  the  natural  law.  We  are  at  present  only  illustrating  a  principle, 
and  therefore  we  speak  without  any  attempt  at  great  scientific  or 
even  ethical  precision  on  this  question.     See,  however,  Vol.  II.  p.  443. 


148  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

1/  happiness  or  weU-being  of  the  race  is  the  final  natural 
I  end  of  good  action  as  well  as  its  criterion.  We  claim 
that  the  happiness  of  the  race  is  only  a  criterion. 
Secondly,  in  the  utilitarian  theory  the  consequences  of 
an  act  constitute  its  goodness,  in  ours  they  merely  mani- 
fest the  same.  Thirdly,  in  the  utilitarian  theory  the 
consequences  are  the  primary  and  fundamental  criterion  ; 
we  regard  them  as  affording  a  secondary  and  derivative 
criterion  only.  Fourthly,  utilitarians  believe  that  if  a 
particular  act  itself  brings  unhappiness  to  the  race,  it  is 
bad.  We  claim  merely  that  if  an  act  should  necessarily 
injure  the  race  on  being  raised  to  a  general  line  of  conduct 
it  must  be  bad.  These  points  of  difference  are  essential 
and  render  the  two  theories  not  only  distinct  but  radically 
opposed. 

NOTE  ON  ETHICAL  OPTIMISM 

From  what  we  have  said  it  will  be  plain  that  there  is 
between  morality  and  the  general  welfare  a  very  intimate 
connection — that,  therefore,  there  was  good  ground  for  St. 
Augustine's  well-known  principle,  "  Necesse  est  ut  homo  sit 
beatus  unde  sit  bonus,"  and  that  Kant  was  near  the  truth 
when  he  declared  that  a  good  act  was  one  that  could  be 
made  a  universal  law  of  action  for  men. 

Although  this  question  does  not  come  within  the  scope  of 
Ethical  Enquiry  in  its  strictly  limited  sense,  it  will  be  well  to 
say  a  word  here  on  the  general  theory  of  "  Ethical  Optimism  " 
— the  theory,  viz.,  that  "  virtue  alone  is  happiness  below,"  or 
that  the  good  and  happiness  must  be  proportionate  to  one 
another.  This  question  would  not  arise  at  all  except  for, 
first,  a  seemingly  ineradicable  conviction  on  the  part  of  men 
in  general  that  virtue  and  happiness  ought  to  be  propor- 
tionate ;  and,  secondly,  a  conviction  born  of  experience,  that 
to  a  very  large  extent  they  are  not  proportionate.  Plato 
attempts  to  prove  the  theory  of  optimism  by  sliowing  that 
such  pleasures  as  do  not  spring  from  virtue  are  unreal,  and 
that,  therefore,  the  parallelism  between  virtue  and  real 
pleasure  must  be  complete.  J^ut  this  theory  is  very  unsatis- 
fying to  the  practical  man  for  whom  felt  pleasures  and  pains 
(whether  real  or  unreal)  arc  everything.  Not  more  satisfying 
is  the  thfiory  offered  by  some  Aristotelians  that,  according 
to  Aristotle,  conlfiihncnt  ensues  on  the  attainment  of  good 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  149 

and  that  good  and  contentment  must,  therefore,  correspond. 
This  theory  is  purely  a  priori,  and  takes  no  account  of  the 
fact  that  often  good  men  are  unhappy.  But  to  cope  with 
the  facts,  whatever  may  be  our  general  theory  of  happiness, 
it  will  be  necessary  to  proceed  not  a  priori  but  empirically. 
We  must  see  how,  in  the  actual  experience  of  men,  happiness 
stands  related  to  goodness,  whether  they  are  proportionate 
or  not,  and  what  are  the  causes  of  the  disproportion  if  they 
be  found  to  be  disproportionate.  The  following  propositions 
will,  we  think,  represent  with  tolerable  accuracy  the  relation 
of  happiness  to  virtue  in  so  far  as  tliis  relation  is  known  from 
experience  : — 

(a)  The  virtues  and  happiness  generally.  We  cannot  claim 
that  there  is  an  ahsohite  proportion  between  the  virtuous  life 
and  happiness.  The  most  virtuous  man  is  often  unhappy 
here  below.  And  even  if  this  unhappiness  is  to  be  made  up 
for  hereafter,  yet  present  sufferings  remain  as  an  element  of 
disproportion  and  as  disproving  the  theory  of  an  absolute 
correspondence  between  virtue  and  happiness.  Coming  more 
to  particulars,  we  shall  consider,  first,  the  general  happiness, 
secondly,  the  individual  happiness. 

{b)  On  the  universal  welfare  we  would  assert  the  following 
general  propositions  : — 

(i)  That  it  would  be  impossible  for  humanity  at  large  to 
be  happy  or  prosperous  with  no  leaven  of  good  in  it — i.e., 
with  every  man  a  liar,  a  fornicator,  a  thief,  &c.  Universal 
vice,  with  no  good,  should  soon  bring  its  o\vn  terrible  retri- 
bution, and  make  it  clear  that  the  wages  of  sin  is  death. 

(2)  Next — to  take  the  case  of  a  world  partly  good  and 
partly  evil — we  claim  that  a  nation  with  absolutely  no  social 
virtues  like  justice,  the  marriage  virtues,  truth,  &c.,  must 
forthwith  decay.  These  virtues  are  the  natural  fastenings  to 
which  a  nation  owes  most  of  its  strength.  Without  them  it 
could  not  exist  any  length  of  time.  Also,  in  the  case  in 
which  these  virtues  are  not  wholly  wanting,  a  nation  will 
still,  other  things  being  equal,  be  weaker  in  proportion  to  the 
deficiency. 

(3)  A  nation  in  which  the  social  virtues  (those,  viz.,  which 
affect  not  the  personal  good,  but  the  relations  of  men  with 
one  another)  are  cultivated  may  still  be  as  a  nation  strong 
and  prosperous,  even  though  the  private  virtues  be  almost 
wholly  wanting.  An  utter  or  a  grave  absence  of  private 
virtue  must,  indeed,  soon  react  upon  the  public  life  and 


150  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

prove  detrimental  to  it,  but  formally  and  directly  the  private 
virtues  affect  the  private  welfare  only. 

The  public  or  universal  welfare,  therefore,  varies  with 
the  degree  of  public  morality  which  is  attained. 

(c)  The  individual  welfare.  The  relation  between  the 
individual  welfare  and  morality  may  be  inferred  from  the 
three  following  considerations  :  (i)  Speaking  generally,  no 
act  is  pain-producing  by  being  natural  and  good,  or  pleasur- 
able so  far  as  it  is  unnatural  and  bad.  On  the  contrary,  if 
a  bad  act  produces  pleasure  it  is  the  natural  or  good  element 
which  inheres  in  every  evil  act  that  is  the  source  of  the 
pleasure.*  Thus,  if  a  man  steals  money,  the  good  effects 
that  accrue  to  him  arise  not  from  the  fact  that  the  money 
is  stolen,  but  from  the  fact  that  he  has  come  by  money — a 
good  thing  viewed  in  itself.  (The  sweetness  of  stolen  fruits 
does  not  contradict  this  view.  Their  pleasure  is  born  not 
of  the  dishonour  of  them,  but  of  the  excitement  and  the 
novelty  in  the  mode  of  getting  them.)  So  also  a  sin  of  un- 
chastity  brings  pleasure  to  the  individual  not  from  the  fact 
that  a  faculty  is  exercised  unnaturally,  but  from  the  fact 
that  it  is  exercised  at  all,  and  in  part  naturally. 

(2)  What  is  called  the  moral  good  is  not  necessarily  to  be 
regarded  as  proportionate  to  happiness,  the  reason  being 
that  the  moral  good  or  virtue  is  not  the  whole  of  "  good." 
Happiness  and  the  "  good  "  are  really  proportional  to  one 
another.  But  "  good  "  and  "  evil "  are  of  two  kinds — 
physical  and  moral — and  happiness  and  misery  depend  upon 
the  two  kinds.  We  suffer  something  from  a  morally  bad 
act  in  so  far  as  it  is  unnatural  (from  some  acts  more,  from 
some  less),  and  we  suffer  from  physical  evil  also — for  instance, 
from  a  broken  leg  or  from  poverty.  Hence  for  perfect 
individual  happiness  a  man  should  be  subject  to  no  evil 
whatsoever,  either  physical  or  moral,  either  in  himself  or 
his  surroundings.  To  this  latter  source  of  unhappiness, 
that,  viz.,  of  a  morally  bad  surrounding,  more  than  to  the 
others  is  to  be  attributed  the  disproportion  that  exists  be- 
tween pleasure  and  goodness,  for  goodness  prospers  only  in 
good  surroundings.  Thus  justice  as  such  brings  happiness. 
But  a  single  injustice  will  upset  the  moral  equilibrium  of  a 
whole  community,  and  then  even  justice  may  cause  misery. 
It  is  a  pain  to  pay  my  debts  when  others  do  not  pay  me.  To 
sum  up — "  virtue  "  (or  moral  good)  and  individual  happiness 
may  not  fully  correspond,  but  happiness  fully  corresponds 

•  "  A  man   receives  pleasure   from   what  is  natural   to   him  " — 
Aristotle  ("  Politics,"  VIII.,  7). 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  151 

with  the  "  good  "  if  we  include  in  the  "  good  "  both  physical 
and  moral  goodness  ;  good  in  ourselves  and  in  our  sur- 
roundings. 

(3)  The  "  good,"  though  proportional  to  happiness,  is  not 
necessarily  proportional  to  happiness  here  below.  To  a  large 
extent  they  must  be  proportional  even  here  below,  but  there 
is  no  absolute  correspondence  between  them,  and  to  expect 
such  a  correspondence  would  be  to  take  a  very  narrow  view 
of  the  laws  and  resources  of  nature.  Even  in  the  physical 
world  the  fruits  of  good  are  not  always  to  be  reaped  im- 
mediately. The  reaping  always  follows  the  sowing  in  time. 
The  good  management  of  a  tree  is  rewarded,  not  now  when 
we  dig  it  around  and  manure  it,  but  later — viz.,  in  the  fruit- 
ing season.  The  moral  good  has  also  its  natural  and  necessary 
reward,  hut  the  fruits  of  our  good  acts  cannot  always  mature 
here,  but  only  in  another  season  and  another  place. 

The  foregoing  propositions  might  be  brought  together  as 
follows  :  {a)  the  public  happiness  is  proportionate  to  public 
good  ;  {h)  individual  happiness  is  never  promoted  by  evil  cis 
such  but  only  by  the  good  element  in  action.  But  in  esti- 
mating goodness  we  must  take  account  of  physical  and  moral 
goodness  and  also  goodness  in  one's  self  and  in  surroundings  ; 
whilst  in  estimating  happiness  we  should  not  confine  our  view 
to  what  is  to  be  attained  here.  But  even  between  goodness 
and  happiness  here  there  must  be  some  proportion. 

Two  corollaries  force  themselves  on  our  attention.  One  is 
that  happiness  in  this  world  is  to  be  found  not  in  the  avoid- 
ance of  action,  in  the  Nirvana,  as  Schopenhauer  said,  but  in 
the  active  pursuit  of  good.  The  second  is  that  happiness 
and  prosperity  are  found,  not  as  Tolstoi  seems  to  hold  {e.g., 
in  essay  "  The  First  Step  ")  in  the  labour  of  an  uncultivated 
life,  but  rather  in  the  fully  developed  life.  For  the  natural 
is  happiness-bringing,  and  nature  is  at  its  best  when  our 
powers  are  used  to  produce  their  highest  effects. 

Happiness,  then,  and  virtue  are  harmonised  in  the  concep- 
tion of  the  good  end  or  the  natural  end.  Many  and  curious 
are  the  solutions  of  this  problem  of  harmony  which  have  been 
proposed  by  writers  on  Ethics.  We  will  give  a  few  of  them, 
and  leave  them  to  the  consideration  of  the  reader,  (i)  It  is 
said  that  there  is  in  nature  a  law  of  reciprocity  which  must 
bring  about  even  here  below  the  restoration  of  an  Ethical 
order  which  we  at  present  miss  in  the  world.  Also  (2)  that 
a  good  conscience  is  its  own  reward,  that  the  happiness  it 
gives  neutralises  the  pain  of  good  action  (Hartmann).  (3) 
According  to  the  Evolutionary  school  the  laws  of  evolution 


152  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

make  it  certain  that  some  day,  even  here  below,  virtue,  and 
happiness  must  coincide,  that  the  whole  world  is  working 
out  into  harmony,  that  the  pain  of  virtue  is  nothing  more 
than  the  unresolved  chord  of  our  moral  life.  The  evolution- 
ary solution  lays  particular  stress  upon  the  effect  of  Altruism 
in  the  bringing  about  of  moral  happiness.  "  Altruism," 
writes  Spencer,  "  of  a  social  kind  may  be  expected  to  attain 
a  level  at  which  it  will  be  like  parental  altruism  in  spontaneity, 
a  level  such  that  ministration  to  others'  happiness  will  become 
a  daily  need."  (4)  Dr.  Simmel  ("  Einleitung  ")  suggests  this 
method  of  conciliation  amongst  others  : — Whether  naturally 
virtue  and  happiness  would  or  would  not  tend  to  coincide, 
we  can  by  believing  that  they  will  harmonise  actually  bring 
about  their  reconciliation,  just  as  sick  people,  by  believing 
they  will  recover,  often  do  recover  in  point  of  fact.  (5)  For 
theories  reconciling  virtue  (in  sense  of  altruism)  with  Happi- 
ness see  Chapter  on  Utilitarianism  (Appendix). 

On  the  evolutionary  theory  of  reconciliation  in  particular, 
ve  would  make  three  brief  suggestions  : — 

i)  Development,  or  the  tendency  upward  to  the  good,  if 
:WCh  a  tendency  actually  exists,  must  make  for  happiness. 
And  we  are  inclined  to  think  that  such  a  tendency  does  exist, 
that  man  must  develop  with  time,  consequently  his  happiness 
must  increase  with  time.  But  can  it  on  the  Evolutionary 
hypothesis  so  increase  as  to  correspond  absolutely  with 
virtue  ?  Certainly  not — in  this  world  there  will  still  always 
remain  the  possibility  of  physical  pain  and  its  attendant 
sorrow. 

(2)  Much  of  the  fruit  of  virtue  is,  as  we  saw,  to  be  looked 
for  in  another  world.  Were  there  no  other  world,  did  the 
"  far-off  interest  of  tears  "  belong  to  this  world  only,  we 
should  have  very  little  hope  of  any  such  "  interest  "  ever 
realising  itself.  All  the  essentials  of  unhappiness  seem 
bound  to  remain  in  this  world  even  for  developed  mankind. 
and  for  our  part  we  can  only  diminish  and  restrain  them. 
Were  there  no  hereafter  we  should  agree,  not  with  Spencer's 
theory  as  given  above,  but  with  Leslie  Stephen's,  who 
writes  : — "  The  attempt  to  establish  an  absolute  coincidence 
between  virtue  and  happiness  is,  in  Ethics,  what  the  attempt- 
ing to  square  the  circle  or  to  discover  perpetual  motion  is  in 
Geometry  and  Mechanics  "  (Science  of  Ethics). 

(3)  Some  Evolutionist  Ethicians  give  as  proof  of  the 
coincidence  of  virtue  and  haj^piness  the  existence  in  each 
of  us  of  an  irresistible  impulse  to  hope  for  their  future 
coincidence.      Now  whether  this  "  postulate  of  reason,"  as 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  153 

i^  is  called,  exists  in  us  or  not  we  cannot  at  present  say. 
But  we  wish  to  point  out  that  if  it  does  exist  it  is  opposed 
in  its  intimations  to  the  Evolutionist  theory.  For  Evolu- 
tionists claim  that  virtue  and  happiness  will  coincide,  not 
in  the  case  of  present,  but  only  of  future  men  whilst  the 
postulate  of  Reason  to  which  they  make  appeal,  if  it  exists  at 
all,  makes  promise  of  the  happiness  of  virtue  to  each  human 
heart. 

These  three  points  should  be  attended  to  in  criticising  the 
evolutionary  theory  on  happiness  and  virtue. 


{2)       THE      SECOND      DERIVATIVE      CRITERION — "  COMMON 
HUMAN    CONVICTIONS  " 

We  do  not  intend  to  discuss  in  the  present  chapter 
the  "  common  consent  "  theorj'^  connected  with  the 
name  of  De  Lamenais  and  others,  the  theory,  namely, 
that  the  common  human  convictions  are  the  primary 
criterion  of  morals.  The.  theory  is  so  absurd  on  the 
face  of  it  that  it  does  not  require  discussion.  If  there 
be  such  a  thing  as  a  real  distinction  between  good  and 
evil,  and  if  men  in  general  believe  that  certain  acts  are 
good  and  others  evil,  they  must  have  some  reason  for 
their  belief.  That  reason  will  be  our  reason  also  and 
our  criterion.  We  now,  however,  proceed  to  prove  that 
although  the  common  human  convictions  cannot  be  ac- 
cepted  as   the   fundamental   and   primary   criterion   of 

/  morals  they  have  real  value  as  a  derivative  criterion. 
And  their  value  consists  in  the  fact  that  ancient  and 
widely-spread  human  convictions  on  good  and  evil  are 
as  a  rule  based  upon  a  certain  intimacy  with  human 
nature  and  its  needs,  an  intimacy  which  is  as  deep  and 
broad  as  it  is  long-continued.  Humanity,  like  indi- 
viduals, must  have  its  standard  of  good  and  evil,  for 
good  and  evil  are  not  always  known  intuitively  ;    and 

.  that  standard  is  nature.  Mankind,  with  the  collective 
wisdom  and  knowledge  of  ages,  matured  and  seasoned 
as  its  wisdom  is  by  experience,  has  seen  very  deeply 
into  human  nature  and  its  needs  ;    for  its  convictions 


154  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

have  been  built  up  through  many  turns  and  vicissitudes 
of  human  history,  and  they  express,  therefore,  just 
what  is  broad  and  substantive  in  human  nature — not 
what  belongs  to  one  time  or  one  set  of  circumstances, 
or  is  accidental.  These  convictions  are  written  deep 
down  in  the  brain  of  the  race.  They  express  what 
man  ought  to  be,  what  becomes  him  and  will  do  him 
good  ;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  what  is  unsafe  and  un- 
suitable for  him,  and  what  will  certainly  do  him  harm — 
what  is  lasting,  as  in  accordance  with  the  abiding 
principles  within  his,  and  what  is  only  caprice  and 
fashion  and  dependent  upon  mere  circumstances.* 
The  strength  of  this  criterion,  then,  lies  in  that  ac- 
quaintance with  human  needs  which  the  race  has 
gained  from  its  almost  endless  experience  of  human 
nature.  And  since  human  nature  or  our  natural  ends 
are  the  primary  criterion  of  morals,  this  secondary 
criterion  depends  upon  the  primary.  We  may  or  may 
not  be  able  to  apply  the  primary  criterion  in  a  particular 
case  ;  but,  if  we  can  find  a  conviction  upon  any  point 
from  which  mankind  has  never  receded,  we  may  trust 
to  that  conviction  as  a  criterion  of  what  is  natural  to 
man  and  apply  it  as  a  substitute  for  the  primary 
criterion,  A  practical  example  would  be  the  ever- 
abiding  conviction  of  the  human  race  of  the  necessity 
of  marriage  for  mankind — as  opposed  to  promiscuous 
relationship. 

But,  reliable  as  this  criterion  is,  it  has  not  the  strength 
of  the  first  of  our  derivative  criteria,  for  between  human 
convictions  and  nature  there  is  no  deep-set  metaphysical 
relation  such  as  exists  between  nature  and  the  general 
well-being  of  the  race.  This  criterion,  like  that  depend- 
ing on  the  consequences,  does  not  belong  to  the  same 
sphere  of  being  as  the  action  whose  morality  we  judge 

•"Let  us  remember,"  writes  Aristotle  ("Politics,"  II.,  5,  ifi), 
"  that  we  should  not  disregard  the  cxpcric  icc  of  ages  ;  in  the  multitude 
of  years  these  things,  if  they  were  good,  would  certainly  not  have 
been  unknown."     He  is  speaking  of  community  of  goods. 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  155 

by  means  of  it.     In  other  words,  the  present  criterion 
is  extrinsic*     It  is  clearly  also  subjective. 


(3)    THE     THIRD     DERIVATIVE     CRITERION — "  THE     MORAL 
FEELINGS  " 

The  last  of  the  derivative  criteria  of  which  we  shall 
take  account  is  that  of  moral  feeling,  or  the  feeling  of 
rightness.  We  shall  see  later  on  that  these  feelings 
cannot  be  the  ultimate  criterion  of  Ethics,  Still,  the 
moral  feelings  are  sometimes  a  guide  to  right  moral 
action  and  a  criterion  of  the  same.  There  are  large 
departments  of  human  conduct  where  the  unsupported 
conscience  or  intellectual  judgment  would  be  slow  to 
carry  on  the  mass  of  men  to  ac  tion,  even  where  action 
is  necessary  for  human  life  ;  and  in  such  cases  we  are 
often  helped  on  by  the  approval  of  our  moral  feelings, 
which  are  then  to  some  extent  a  criterion  of  good  and 
evil.  People  do  often  experience  these  indefinable 
feelings,  particularly  when  their  nature  is  not  blunted 
by  habitual  crime.  Persistence  in  crime  makes  our 
conscience  coarse  and  irresponsive,  whereas  the  very 
suggestion  of  certain  acts  frightens  good  people  and 
excites  in  them  feelings  of  disapproval,  even  though 
the  Reason  cannot  say  why  the  act  which  is  done  is 
wrong.  These  feelings  may  generally  be  trusted  as 
true,  for,  being  excited  in  us  immediately  by  acts  either 
directly  witnessed  or  directly  imagined,  they  are  quite 
as  likely  to  answer  to  the  true  objective  moral  quality 
inherent  in  those  acts,  the  quality  which  calls  the 
feelings  into  existence,  as  would  a  formal  judgment 
resulting  from  reasoning  and  analysis.  Our  reasonings 
are  largely  under  our  own  control  and  they  are  liable 

*  If  these  convictions  were  accompanied  by  reasons,  then  these 
reasons  would  be  our  criterion,  and  we  should  have  no  need  to  regard 
the  convictions  of  the  race  as  themselves  a  criterion  ;  but  since  the 
seasons,  are,  as  a  rule,  not  formally  given  with  the  conviction,  and 
rince  the  convictions  are  still  there  to  be  appealed  to,  we  have  every 
right  to  call  these  convictions  a  criterion,  though  secondary. 


156  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

sometimes  to  be  coloured  and  prompted  by  a  sense  of 
our  own  interests  rather  than  by  the  simple  appreciation 
of  truth.  But  the  feelings  which  we  use  as  criteria  of 
morality  are  not  properly  speaking  under  our  control. 
They  are  therefore  all  the  more  likely  to  be  disinterested. 

Still,  we  must  be  careful  not  to  value  these  feelings 
too  highly  as  criteria.  For,  first,  their  want  of  definition 
and  their  unstable  character  make  their  application  as  a 
rule  uncertain.  Again,  these  feelings  often  relate  not  to 
the  lawfulness  but  rather  to  the  indelicacy  of  acts.  But 
not  all  acts  that  are  indelicate  or  coarse  are  unlawful. 
For  instance,  the  more  delicate  natures  sometimes  recoil 
from  vivisection  and  hunting,  but  on  sesthetic  grounds 
only,  or,  at  all  events,  on  grounds  other  than  moral. 
Again,  these  feelings  are  often  the  result  of  judgments 
already  made — judgments,  viz.,  in  which  the  other  moral 
criteria  are  applied  roughly  and  quickl}',  and,  therefore, 
these  feelings,  being  themselves  the  result  of  moral 
judgments,  cannot  serve  as  the  criteria  on  which  to 
form  our  judgments.  Again,  where  the  issues  are  very 
complicated,  as  is  often  the  case  with  questions  of 
justice,  such  feeUngs  may  be  the  result  of  a  certiiin 
tenderness  of  conscience  which  recoils  from  what  ap- 
proaches even  remotely  to  sin  and  tends  generally  to 
be  on  the  side  which  is  morally  safest.  In  these  cases 
a  man  should  rely  as  far  as  possible  on  the  "  sicca  lux 
intellectus,"  without  any  reference  to  inner  feelings  of 
approbation  or  blame. 

We  should,  therefore,  be  careful  not  to  exaggerate  the 
importance  of  these  moral  feelings  as  moral  standards. 
Yet  they  have  some  value,  and  are  sometimes  a  real 
help  to  us  in  forming  our  moral  judgments.  ]\Ien 
sometimes  say :  "I  cannot  see  why  such  an  act  is 
unlawful,  but  I  don't  like  the  look  of  it,"  and  in  many 
cases  we  may  trust  such  natural  feelings.  With  these 
limitations  we  admit  the  feelings  amongst  our  secondary 
criteria.  Manifestly  they  can  only  be  secondary  and 
extrinsic,   and   tlio   certainty   they   yield  is   not   easily 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  157 

determinable — in  general  it  is  not  above  a  high  degree 
of  probability.  This  criterion,  like  the  common  con- 
victions, is,  we  need  not  say,  purely  subjective. 

SOME    GENERAL    REMARKS    ON    THE    CRITERIA 

We  have  now  shown  that  there  is  but  one  primary 
and  fundamental  moral  criterion,  and  that  there  are 
many  secondary  criteria,  and  that  the  business  of  these 
latter  is  to  help  us  to  know  good  and  evil  when  the 
application  of  the  primary  criterion  is  impossible  or 
inconvenient. 

There  may  be  other  criteria  of  morals  besides  those 
we  have  enumerated.  But  the  certitude  attaching  to 
them,  if  any  such  exist,  cannot  be  of  a  high  order,  and, 
therefore,  we  shall  not  deal  with  them. 

It  will  be  noticed  that  in  our  list  of  criteria  we  sub- 
scribe to  a  very  large  extent  to  s^-stems  that  are  usually 
regarded  as  quite  irreconcilable.  We  have  found  a 
place  for  many  points  in  such  opposing  theories,  as 
those  of  Aristotle,  Mill,*  De  Lamenais,  Cumberland, f 
Shaftesbury, J  Adam  Smith, §  Kant,l!  ^^^^  Martineau.^ 
And  we  have  done  so,  not  through  any  desire  to  recon- 
cile these  theories,  but  simply  because  we  are  persuaded 
that  there  is  some  truth  in  these  systems.  They  are 
all  partial  systems  presenting  to  us  one  or  more  aspects 
of  human  nature.  What  each  one  of  the  writers  men- 
tioned regards  as  the  fundamental  criterion  is,  to  a 
large  extent,  at  least  a  criterion.  But  it  is  not  the 
fundamental  criterion,  because  it  does  not  represent 
what  is  essential  in  natural  goodness.  But  it  is  worthy 
of  remark  that  it  is  because  there  is  some  truth,  and 

*  Hedonistic  Utilitarianism. 

f  Utilitarian  theory  based  on  psychology  of  the  faculties. 

X  /Esthetic  Ethics — the  good  is  the  beautiful  or  the  orderly.  See 
section  "  III."  of  primary  criterion. 

§  Theory  of  feelings  as  moral  criterion. 

II  Act  good,  which  is  possible  for  all  humanity.  Compare  first 
derivative  criterion. 

H  Theory  of  hierarchy  of  impulses.  Compare  section  "  III."  of 
primary  criterion. 


158  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

often  a  good  deal  of  truth,  in  these  opposing  systems 
that  there  is  so  much  agreement  in  the  moral  codes 
with  which  they  severally  supply  us.  This  practical 
agreement  amongst  Ethicians,  in  spite  of  theoretical 
differences,  is  not  to  be  explained  as  a  result  of  dis- 
honest "  squaring."  No  doubt,  there  has  been  some 
unconscious  forcing  done,  so  as  to  get  these  various 
systems  into  harmony  with  the  code  that  already  ob- 
tains in  the  world.  But  we  believe  that  there  is  a  good 
deal  of  genuine  truth  in  all  of  them,  and  our  reason  is 
that  many  of  these  criteria  are  to  a  large  extent  valid 
as  standards  of  morality.  We  cannot,  therefore,  at  all 
subscribe  to  that  charge  of  wholesale  dishonesty  which 
we  find  at  least  insinuated  in  Mr.  Balfour's  "  Founda- 
tions of  Belief  "  *  :  "  This  unanimity  (in  the  moral 
code),  familiar  though  it  be,  is,"  he  writes,  "  surely 
very  remarkable,  and  it  is  the  more  remarkable  because 
the  unanimity  prevails  only  as  to  conclusions  and  is 
accompanied  by  the  widest  divergence  of  opinion  with 
regard  to  the  premisses  on  which  these  conclusions  are 
supposed  to  be  founded.  Nothing  but  habit  could 
blind  us  to  the  strangeness  of  the  fact  that  the  man 
who  believed  that  morality  is  based  on  a  priori  prin- 
ciples and  the  man  who  believes  it  to  be  based  on  the 
commands  of  God,  the  transcendentalist,  the  theologian, 
the  mj'stic  and  the  evolutionist,  should  be  pretty  well 
at  one  both  as  to  what  morality  teaches  and  as  to  the 
sentiments  with  which  its  teaching  should  be  regarded. 
It  is  not  my  business  in  this  place  to  examine  the 
Philosophy  of  morals  or  to  fnd  an  answer  to  the 
charge  which  this  suspicious  harmony  of  opinion  among 
various  schools  of  moralists  appears  to  suggest — namely, 
that  in  their  speculations  they  have  taken  current 
morality  for  granted,  and  have  squared  their  proofs  to 
their  conclusions,  and  not  their  conclusions  to  their 
proofs." 

•  Page  14  (oinl)tli  edition).     We  liave  already  referred  briefly  to 
this  passf.ge  in  Chapter  1. 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  159 

This,  as  we  have  said  in  the  opening  chapter,  is  a 
serious  charge,  and  one  that  ought  not  to  be  made 
without  serious  consideration.  We  find  it  hard  to 
imagine  the  great  leading  intellects  of  the  world  lend- 
ing themselves  to  the  unprincipled  method  of  squaring 
proofs  and  principles  to  conclusions — conclusions  that, 
so  far  as  these  ethicians  are  concerned,  have  nothing 
else  to  recommend  them,  Mr.  Balfour  tells  us,  than  that 
they  represent  the  moral  code  that  now  most  widely 
obtains  in  the  world.  No  doubt,  men  may  be  deluded 
into  imagining  here  and  tnere  a  connection  between 
principle  and  conclusion  that  really  does  not  exist.  But 
delusion  cannot  be  universal,  and  dishonest  squaring  is 
not  to  be  thought  of.  Nor  is  there  any  need  for  sus- 
pecting either  one  or  the  other.  Criteria  the  most 
divergent  may  be,  and  in  fact  are  often,  true  together. 
Amongst  our  secondary  or  derivative  criteria  we  have 
found  room  for  widely  divergent  standards,  for  the 
simple  reason  that  human  nature,  which  is  our  funda- 
mental standard  of  morals,  is  many-sided,  and,  there- 
fore, can  be  tested  in  many  ways.  The  several  criteria 
offered  by  various  writers  as  primary  will  be  found  to 
be  false  in  many  details,  but  their  principal  defect  Ues 
in  this — that  they  are  represented  by  ethicians  as  funda- 
mental criteria  instead  of  as  derivative — and  the  systems 
founded  on  them  as  adequate  systems  of  morality  instead 
of  as  parts  of  one  whole.* 

*  At  the  conclusion  of  the  chapter  on  the  moral  criteria  we  desire 
to  say  a  word  regarding  a  supposed  criterion  of  morality.  Some  have 
regarded  the  golden  mean  as  a  criterion  of  morality.  But  it  is  not, 
we  claim,  a  distinct  criterion,  and  we  have,  therefore,  deferred  the 
treatment  of  it  to  a  later  chapter — that,  viz.,  on  the  Virtues.  The 
golden  mean  is  in  one  sense  a  quality  of  all  moral  action.  For  all 
virtue  lies  between  extremes.  Justice  is  a  mean  between  excess  and 
defect  in  giving  each  his  own.  Temperance  is  a  mean  between  over- 
indulgence in  pleasure  and  a  too  rigid  asceticism.  But  in  these  cases 
the  mean  is  not  a  criterion  of  morality,  because  it  does  not  tell  us  what 
acts  are  good  or  just  or  temperate.  It  supposes  the  moral  judgment 
already  made,  for,  it  being  once  determined  that  a  certain  act  is  good, 
we  can  then  go  on  to  show  that  this  act  is  a  mean — that  is,  that  vice 
lies  on  either  side  of  it.  It  is  when  we  have  already  found  the  right 
road  to  a  town  that  we  conclude  that  this  road  is  the  mean,  or,  in  other 


i6o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(c)  Some     Difficulties     Against     the     Theory     of 
Natural  Morals  Considered 

(i)  The  theory  that  nature,  or  natural  end,  is  the 
primary  standard  of  morals  is  reviewed  by  Sidgwick  in 
his  "  Methods  of  Ethics  "  ;  and  we  take  it  that  the 
criticism  that  he  there  gives  represents  fairly  well  the 
mind  of  English  ethicians  generally  on  this  subject  of 
Natural  Morals,  first,  because  of  the  weight  which 
attaches  in  England  to  any  view  of  Sidgwick,  and, 
secondly,  because  in  his  attack  on  the  theory  of  Natural 
Morals  he  gives  prominence  to  the  very  ditliculty  which 
we  should  expect  Englishmen  to  emphasise — namely, 
the  practical  difficulty  in  our  theory  of  distinguishing 
between  the  natural  and  non-natural  in  human  action. 

The  theory  of  Natural  Morals,  he  tells  us,  presupposes 
design  in  nature,  and  by  nature  in  the  present  instance 
he  means  the  system  of  natural  human  impulses.  From 
a  consideration  of  these  natural  impulses  the  theory  of 
Natural  Morals  claims,  he  says,  to  be  able  to  establish 
the  various  duties  imposed  by  the  moral  law  on  men,  a 
claim  which  Sidgwick  regards  as  impossible  and  even 
contradictory.  "  In  fact,"  he  writes,*  "  those  who  use 
'  natural '  as  an  ethical  notion  do  commonly  suppose 
that  by  contemplating  the  actual  play  of  human  im- 
pulses or  the  physical  constitution  of  man  or  his  social 
relations  we  may  find  principles  for  determining  posi- 
tively and  completely  the  kind  of  life  he  was  designed 
to  live.  I  think,  however,  that  every  attempt  thus  to 
derive  '  what  ought  to  be  '  from  '  what  is  '  palpably 
fails  the  moment  it  is  freed  from  fundamental  con- 
words,  that  to  move  any  other  way  will  lead  us  astray.  In  one  sense, 
however,  we  can  look  on  the  golden  mean  as  a  criterion,  but  as  a 
criterion  it  falls  in  with  the  primary  criterion  given  in  the  present 
chapter — viz.,  the  criterion  of  "  man — an  ordered  hierarchy  of  im- 
pulses." In  that  sdnse  the  golden  mean  signifies  the  maintenance  of 
organic  equilibrium  in  man — the  not  allowing  one  part  of  the  organism 
to  run  away  with  all,  or  unduly  to  obscure  any  other  part.  Not  being 
•  distinct  criterion,  therefore,  the  golden  mean  cannot  be  specially 
considered  in  the  present  chapter. 

•  "  Methods,"  page  8i. 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  i6i 

fusions  of  thought."  Sidgwick  then  proceeds  to  explain 
further  why  this  attempt  to  deduce  "  what  ought  to 
be  "  from  the  play  of  human  impulses  palpably  fails  in 
the  theory  of  Natural  Morals.     The  difficulty  is  twofold  : 

(a)  first,  that  when  impulses  are  in  conflict  we  cannot 
tell  which  impulse  is  natural  and  which  is  not.  Some, 
he  says,  regard  those  impulses  as  natural  which  are 
common  to  all  men — a  view  which  appears  to  Sidgwick 
absurd  since  there  is  no  evidence  that  "  Nature  abhors 
the  exceptional."  Others  regard  those  impulses  as 
natural  which  are  original  and  underived — a  position 
which,  according  to  Sidgwick,  seems  equally  irrational 
with  the  first,  since  there  is  no  evidence  to  show  that 
Nature    "  prefers    the    earlier    in    time    to    the    later." 

(b)  Secondly,  the  attempt  to  deduce  "  what  ought  to 
be  "  from  the  consideration  of  natural  impulses  assumes 
what  is  false — namely,  that  "  Nature  eschews  as  un- 
natural and  opposed  to  the  Divine  design"  all  such 
impulses  as  are  produced  in  us  by  the  "  institutions  of 
Society  by  our  use  of  human  arrangements  and  con- 
trivances, or  that  result  in  any  way  from  the  deliberate 
action  of  our  fellow-men." 

Our  answer  to  Sidgwick's  difficulty  will  consist  in 
showing  (i.)  that  there  is  a  genuine  distinction  between 
"  natural  "  and  "  unnatural,"  a  distinction  which  is 
implicitl}^  questioned  in  his  argument  ;  (ii.)  secondl}', 
taking  up  the  two  express  points  of  the  difficulty  given 
above,  we  shall  show  [a)  that  there  is  no  a  priori  diffi- 
culty such  as  is  conceived  by  Sidgwick  against  our  dis- 
tinguishing in  practice  between  natural  and  unnatural 
impulses  ;  and  (b)  that  the  unwarrantable  assumption 
which  Sidgwick  attributes  to  us,  viz.,  that  "  Nature 
eschews  as  opposed  to  the  Divine  design  "  all  institu- 
tions of  Society,  ^-c,  is  quite  imaginary,  and  is  no  part 
of  the  theory  of  Natural  Morals. 

(i.)  Many  Ethicians  expressly  deny  what  Sidgwick 
implicitly  calls  in  question — namely,  the  existence  in 
the  Universe  of  any  such  distinction  as  that  of 
Vol.  1— u 


i62  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

"  natural "  and  "  unnatural."  According  to  these 
Ethicians  everything  is  natural,  since  everything  is  both 
a  part  of  nature  and  brought  into  being  by  natural 
causes.  Thus,  a  fallen  tree  is  quite  as  natural,  they 
contend,  as  a  living  tree  ;  a  sick  animal  as  natural  as 
a  healthy  one  ;  an  earthquake  and  all  its  evil  conse- 
quences as  natural  as  the  motion  of  the  earth^  on  its 
axis  ;  the  decay  of  winter  as  natural  as  the  growth  of 
spring.  How,  then,  they  ask,  can  anything  be  called 
imnatural  ?  Our  reply  is,  that  in  one  sense  it  is  true 
that  everything  is  natural  since  everything  (speaking 
according  to  Reason)  is  both  a  part  of  nature  and  is  a 
result  of  natural  causes.  But  things  may  be  natural  as 
being  the  effect  of  natural  efficient  causes,  and  yet  be 
unnatural  in  another  sense — namely,  as  failing  to  reach 
their  final  natural  end  or  cause.  For  all  living  things 
have  natural  functions  to  perform,  and,  therefore,  a 
natural  end  to  which  they  progress,  and  if  they  fail  to 
reach  this  end  they  have  fallen  short  of  the  standard  of 
nature,  and  are  to  that  extent  unnatural.  Thus,  a 
diseased  heart  is  unnatural,  not  in  the  sense  that  the 
disease  is  not  due  to  natural  efficient  causes,  but  in  the 
sense  that  a  bad  heart  falls  short  of  nature's  standard, 
inasmuch  as  it  cannot  perform  the  natural  functions  of 
a  heart.  It  is  in  this  sense  that  we  speak  of  "  un- 
natural "  in  Ethics,  and  in  this  sense  some  human  acts 
are  unnatural — namely,  those  that  fall  short  of  the 
standard  of  human  nature  by  opposing  our  natural 
end. 

(II.)  (a)  Sidgwick's  main  difficulty,  however,  docs  not 
lie  in  the  admission  of  a  real  distinction  between  natural 
and  unnatural,  but  rather  in  determining  which  of  our 
impulses  are  natural  and  which  are  unnatural.  And 
the  difficulty  turns,  in  the  first  place,  on  the  question 
how  one  is  to  distinguish  "  natural  "  from  "  unnatural," 
considering  that  even  the  most  abnormal  and  excep- 
tional of  impulses  may  be  as  natural  as  the  common  and 
normal — "  Nature    does    not    abhor    exceptions."     Our 


I 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  163 

answer  to  this  first  point  is  as  follows  :  We  determine 
natural  impulses  in  Ethics  just  as  the  physiologist  de- 
termines natural  bodily  functions — that  is,  by  in- 
ductively examining  the  impulses  and  functions,  and 
discovering  what  is  permanent  and  necessary  in  them. 
The  physiologist  determines  the  functions  of  the  several 
organs  by  examining  the  organs  when  actually  at  work, 
and  discovering  their  necessary  and  inseparable 
activities,  and  the  ends  of  these  activities.  He  knows, 
for  instance,  that  all  varieties  of  hearts  have  one  action 
in  common — namely,  to  send  blood  through  veins,  that 
all  lungs  inhale  and  exhale — and  from  this  he  concludes 
that  such  and  such  are  the  natural  functions  of  these 
organs.  Moreover  he  can  mark  off  certain  functions  as 
natural  to  heart  and  lungs  even  though  he  knows  that 
in  the  case  of  some  hearts  and  lungs  these  activities 
and  functions  are  not  properly  exercised  ;  that  is  to 
say,  that  some  hearts  and  lungs  are  abnormal  and  ex- 
ceptional. So,  also,  it  is  not  right  to  argue  in  the  sphere 
of  morals  that  because  in  nature  there  are  to  be  found 
abnormalities  and  exceptions,  because  nature  does  not 
abhor  exceptions,  therefore  the  distinction  between 
natural  and  unnatural  acts  cannot  be  accepted. 

Again,  it  is  urged  by  Sidgwick  that  distinctions  of 
'  earlier  '  and  *  later  '  furnish  no  clue  to  distinctions  of 
natural  and  unnatural  since  nature  does  not  prefer  the 
earlier  in  time  to  the  later.  Now  we  have  not  claimed 
that  nature  prefers  the  earlier  to  the  later,  but  only  that 
in  living  things  there  are  certain  original  and  inseparable 
functions,  and  that  all  action  must  harmonise  with  these 
functions.  Nature  may  not,  indeed,  prefer  the  earlier 
to  the  later  ;  but  we  insist  that  she  does  prefer  the 
original  to  the  artificial,  and  our  claim  that  certain  im- 
pulses are  primary  and  natural  merely  means  that  they 
are  original  in  our  constitution,  just  as  flowering  and 
shedding  seed,  though  later  activities  in  the  plant,  are 
original  possibilities  of  the  plant,  and  natural.  The 
natural,   even  though  it  should  manifest  itself  later  in 


i64  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

history,  is  always  original  in  this  sense.  Nature,  then, 
may  not  prefer  the  earlier,  but  she  prefers  those  acts 
which  do  not  oppose  the  original  or  natural  purpose  of 
our  capacities. 

(6)  As  to  Sidgwick's  second  point,  our  claim  is  that 
the  theory  of  Natural  Morals  does  not  "  eschew  as  un- 
natural and  opposed  to  the  Divine  design "  all  im- 
pulses that  have  been  produced  by  society  or  by  human 
arrangement.  For,  according  to  the  theory  of  Natural 
Morals,  not  only  the  natural  but  also  the  State  law  has 
a  moral  value — that  is,  its  precepts  are  of  moral  obliga- 
tion ;  and,  therefore,  the  theory  of  Natural  Morals 
recognises  many  things  as  good  and  in  accordance  with 
the  original  design  of  things  which  3'et  are  wholly  the 
result  of  human  institution. 

We  shaU  be  asked,  however,  if  the  theory  of  Natural 
Morals  accepts  the  institutions  of  society  as  according 
with  Divine  design,  why  does  it  avoid  all  mention  of 
them  in  its  enumeration  of  natural  goods.  We  answer 
— institutions  of  Society  are  indeed  natural,  but  only 
in  the  sense  of  according  with  the  laws  of  nature.  Now 
it  should  be  remembered  that  even  though  a  natural 
appetite  might  be  satisfied  with  a  certain  object  or  end, 
yet  it  is  only  what  is  fundamental  in  the  appetite  that  is 
given  as  natural.  The  fundamental  object  of  hunger  is 
food,  not  bread  or  fruit,  and  consequently,  in  the  science 
of  Physiology,  food  is  the  only  object  that  is  guaranteed 
to  be  a  natural  object  without  further  question.  It  is 
the  same  in  Ethics.  Just  like  particular  kinds  of  food, 
80  also  the  institutions  of  society  must  be  shown  to  be 
natural  by  rational  proof,  else  we  have  no  guarantee 
that  they  arc  good.  It  is  through  ignoring  this  obvious 
distinction  that  Sidgwick  fell  into  the  mistake  of  sup- 
posing that  because  in  Ethics  we  do  not  mention  the 
social  institutions  as  evident  instances  of  natural  good 
that,  therefore,  Natural  Morality  eschews  as  unnatural 
all  that  has  been  brought  into  being  by  Society. 

(2)  A  aecond  objection  to  the  theory  of  Natural  Morals 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  165 

is  that  human  nature  is  not  permanent,  but  is  subject 
to  development,  and,  therefore,  that  it  could  not  give 
rise  to  those  permanent  laws  \\hich  are  inculcated  by 
Natural  Morals. 

To  this  objection  we  reply — The  theory  of  Natural 
Morals  does  not  claim  that  everything  that  belongs  to 
man  by  nature  is  unchangeable.  The  theory  of  Natural 
Morals  is  consistent  with  the  view  that  nature  may 
change  considerably  under  the  influence  of  environment 
— for  instance,  that  natural  organs  may  change.  The 
only  claim  of  the  theory  of  Natural  Morals  in  respect  of 
permanence  is  that  just  as  certain  chemical  elements 
have  an  unchangeable  affinity  for  others,  and  just  as  a 
plant  has  certain  permanent  and  unchangeable  needs — 
for  instance,  the  need  of  moisture — and  animals  certain 
permanent  conscious  movements  to  certain  objects — for 
instance,  the  desire  for  food — so  also  in  man  there  are 
certain  permanent  appetites,  some  of  which  are  common 
to  all  substances,  some  to  all  animals,  whilst  others  are 
proper  to  man  himself.  This  claim,  we  think,  it  is 
scarcely  possible  seriously  to  dispute.  The  theory  of 
Natural  Morals  does,  of  course,  allow  that  many  of  our 
stable  desires  arise  through  the  influence  of  certain 
artificial  conditions — for  instance,  the  desire  for  cooked 
food  or  for  alcohol.  But,  then,  the  desire  for  cooked 
food  presupposes  a  natural  appetite  for  food,  and  the 
thirst  for  alcohol  presupposes  a  natural  appetite  for 
drink,  and  without  such  natural  appetites  such  of  our 
desires  as  are  accidental  could  not  arise.  Without  them 
also,  as  Leslie  Stephen  testifies,  the  race  could  not  sur- 
vive a  generation.  There  are,  then,  in  man  permanent 
natural  appetites,  and  to  that  extent,  at  least,  we  are 
justified  in  assuming  the  permanence  of  nature. 

(3)  Another  common  and  obvious  objection  is  that 
the  moral  beliefs  of  man  are  variable,  and  that  they 
differ  with  different  people,  whereas  if  Morals  be  natural 
our  beliefs  should  be  both  invariable  and  maintained 
bv  all. 


i66  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Now,  this  objection  it  is  by  no  means  easy  to  under- 
stand, for  it  does  not  say  why,  in  a  theory  of  natural 
morals,  beliefs  should  be  invariable  and  maintained  by 
aU.  If  it  means  that  on  this  theory  beliefs  are  innate, 
and,  therefore,  common  to  all  and  invariable,  then  it 
assumes  what  is  not  true,  for  the  theory  of  Natural 
Morals  does  not  mean  that  we  have  natural  innate 
moral  beliefs,  but  that  there  exist  certain  natural  moral 
laws  founded  on  natural  appetites.  On  the  other  hand, 
if  the  point  of  the  objection  is  that  on  a  question  of 
natural  law  there  is  no  room  for  uncertainty  or  error  or 
difference  of  view,  then  the  supposition  is  negatived  by 
the  physical  sciences.  For  these  deal  with  natural  laws, 
and  yet  our  knowledge  of  these  laws  is  subject  to  varia- 
tion and  difference  of  view.  In  the  same  way,  there 
may  be  differences  concerning  morals,  even  though  the 
moral  law  is  natural.  We  claim,  however,  that  on  the 
primary  moral  principles,  opinions  cannot  and  do  not 
vary,  and  this  claim  is  borne  out  by  Anthropology,  as 
will  be  shown  in  a  later  chapter. 

One  important  modification  of  the  present  argument 
— that  is,  the  argument  which  concerns  the  divergence 
of  human  opinion  on  moral  matters — must  be  noticed — 
namely,  M.  Levy-Bruhl's  contention  that  that  portion 
of  the  moral  law  on  which  all  are  agreed  consists  almost 
exclusively  of  empty  formulae  without  content  or 
practical  significance,  whereas  that  in  which  they  differ 
embraces  the  whole  practical  content  of  the  moral  law. 
Thus,  the  law  or  formula  "  neminem  laede,  suum 
cuique "  was  the  same,  according  to  M.  Levy-Bruhl, 
in  the  days  of  the  most  ancient  civilisations — Egyptian, 
Assyrian,  Babylonian — as  it  is  to-day.  But  the  content 
of  that  law  is  not  the  same,  since  the  "  suum  "  and  the 
"  neminem  "  vary  from  age  to  age  ;  for,  first,  the  rights 
of  one  time  are  not  the  rights  of  another,  and,  secondly, 
there  was  a  time  when  some  men  had  no  rights,  whereas 
to-day  every  man  has  rights. 
Our  reply  is,  first,  tliat  even  if  the  content  and  appli- 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  167 

cation  of  the  law  were  wholly  changed,  the  law  itself, 
"  neminem  laede — suum  cuique,"  is  not  an  empty- 
formula  any  more  than  the  general  laws  of  gravitation 
and  of  electricity  are  empty  formulae.  No  law  is  empty 
merely  because  it  is  general.  If  the  general  laws  were 
all  empty  formulae  there  could  be  no  science,  since  in 
the  case  of  the  deductive  sciences  general  laws  are  the 
principles,  and  in  the  case  of  the  inductive  sciences  they 
are  the  end  of  the  reasoning  process.  If,  therefore,  the 
general  laws  are  empty  formulae  all  science  is  either 
impossible  or  useless.  Secondly,  to  a  large  extent  these 
general  moral  laws  are  exactly  the  same  now  in  their 
content  and  application  that  they  always  were.  Thus, 
the  "  suum  "  of  Justice  has  not  wholly  changed — for 
instance,  from  age  to  age  and  at  all  times  the  child  has 
a  right  to  support  and  training.  Also,  it  is  not  true 
that  at  one  time  certain  human  beings  had  no  rights. 
The  "  neminem  "  of  the  law  of  justice  means  now  and 
always  that  "  no  snail's  rights  can  be  ignored."  Thirdly, 
it  would  be  absurd  to  expect  that  the  content  of  the 
moral  laws  should  continue  always  the  same,  considering 
that  the  moral  natural  laws,  and  particularly  the  law  of 
Justice,  are  subject  to  many  varying  conditions  ;  and  if 
varying  conditions  can  alter  the  effects  of  the  natural 
laws  of  Physics,  and,  so,  give  these  laws  a  new  and 
varying  content  at  different,  ages,  it  is  to  be  expected 
that  the  content  of  the  moral  laws  will  vary  also. 
Again,  as  in  Physics,  so  also  in  Ethics,  the  particular 
conclusions  that  flow  from  the  general  principles  are 
such  that  it  is  not  impossible  men  should  err  in  their 
judgments  about  them.  It  is,  therefore,  no  disproof  of 
the  theory  of  natural  Morals  that  the  content  of  the 
general  moral  laws  varies  to  some  extent  with  conditions 
of  time  and  place. 

(4)  Another  objection  which  we  take  from  M.  Levy- 
Bruhl  is  that  the  theory  of  Natural  Morals  is  only  an 
instance  of  that  tendency  of  the  human  mind  which 
has  been  so  fruitful  of  error  in  the  domain  of  Physics, 


i68  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

and  which,  we  may  suppose,  must  also  mislead  us  in 
the  case  of  Morals — namely,  the  tendency  to  anthropo- 
centrism,  or  the  desire  to  regard  man  as  the  centre  of 
the  universe  and  everything  else  in  the  universe  as 
directed  to  man.  "  Moral  Anthropocentrism,"  M.  Levy- 
Bruhl  defines  *  as  a  "  spontaneous  need  (of  the  mind) 
whereby  we  tend  to  arrange  the  facts  and  laws  of  the 
world  around  the  human  conscience  as  their  centre, 
and  to  explain  these  facts  and  laws  by  means  of  con- 
science "  instead  of  regarding  the  facts  and  laws  of  the 
world  as  the  centre  and  the  rule  of  action,  and  regulating 
our  consciences  by  means  of  them. 

We  reply  that,  as  applied  to  the  theory  of  Natural 
Morals,  the  expression  "  moral  anthropocentrism  "  is 
entirely  without  foundation,  f  Anthropocentrism  in 
Morals  means  that  the  facts  and  laws  of  life  are  made 
dependent  on  man.  In  the  theory  of  Natural  Morals, 
on  the  contrary,  we  claim  that  man  is  dependent  on 
objective  laws  and  ends,  that  conscience  is  formed  by 
an  investigation  of  our  natural  appetites  and  their 
objects,  and  the  laws  the}^  impose,  that,  therefore,  these 
laws  are  as  independent  of  our  consciences  as  the  laws 
of  medicine  are  independent  of  the  medical  practitioner. 
The  natural  appetites,  then,  are  the  rule  of  action,  and 
they  are  prior  to  our  consciences  and  moral  beliefs.  The 
appetites  define  our  final  end,  and  the  final  end,  and  not 
man,  is  the  centre  to  which  man  converges  and  on  which 
he  depends.  "  Put  aside,"  says  M.  L6vy-Bruhl,  "  the 
theory  of  Moral  Anthropocentrism  and  you  at  once  get 
rid  of  the  postulate  of  final  causes."  On  the  contrary, 
we  claim — put  aside  the  theory  of  Moral  Anthropocen- 
trism and  you  in  that  very  act  assume  the  existence  of 

•  "  La  Morale  ct  la  Science  des  Moeurs,"  page  204. 

I  M.  L^vy-BruliI  makes  the  mistake  of  supposing  that  in  the 
theory  of  Natural  Morals  and  natural  law  our  consciences  and  moral 
beliefs  are  ^iven  ready-made  by  nature,  and  that  we  do  not  require 
to  invcstJKate  in  order  to  arrive  at  a  knowledge  of  good  and  evil. 
"  Cc  mot  (morale  naturelle)  si^nilie  pour  nous  que  toutc  conscience 
humaine  rc(;oit  par  ccla  seul  qu'clle  est  humainc  une  lumifcre  sp6ciale 
qui  hii  d6couvro  la  distinction  du  bicn  et  du  mal  "  (page  200). 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  169 

final  causes,  for  if  man  be  not  the  centre  of  the  world 
of  moral  relations,  the  centre  or  point  of  convergence  of 
all  human  activity  must  be  found  in  some  end  beyond 
man  to  which  his  appetites  direct  him.  The  theory  of 
Natural  Morals,  then,  since  it  admits  a  final  natural  end 
outside  of  and  beyond  man,  is  not  a  theory  of  "  Mora! 
Anthropocentrism . ' ' 

(5)  Another  difficulty  is  that  "  natural  morality " 
cannot  account  for  differences  in  our  individual  duties. 
For  since  nature  is  that  portion  of  our  constitution 
which  is  common  to  all,  pure  natural  morality  must 
necessitate  a  code  of  duty  which  is  common  to  all. 
But,  it  is  contended,  the  duty  of  one  man  is  not  the 
duty  of  another.  Duty  varies  with  circumstances  of 
time,  place,  and  person ;  and  consequently  morality 
cannot  be  founded  ultimately  on  nature  or  natural 
appetites. 

Reply — Natural  morality  is,  as  we  have  already 
abundantly  proved,  common  to  all  as  regards  a  very 
large  portion  of  its  precepts  or  duties,  particularly  the 
negative  precepts.  But  though  this  is  true  we  still 
claim  that  natural  morality  not  only  is  compatible  with, 
but  even  necessitates  differences  of  moral  obligation  de- 
pending on  circumstances  of  time,  place,  person,  &c. 
The  causes  of  many  of  these  differences  are  the  follow- 
ing :  [a)  Natural  morality  obliges  to  the  fulfilment  of 
certain  natural  appetites  which  are  common  to  all ; 
but  the  conditions  of  the  fulfilment  of  appetites  are 
different  with  different  persons.  (6)  Many  natural  re- 
lations on  which  are  founded  natural  duties  are  not 
realised  in  the  case  of  all  men,  but  only  in  some,  (c) 
The  natural  law  itself  which,  were  the  circumstances 
the  same  for  all,  would  impose  the  same  duty  on  all, 
often  makes  express  provision  for  circumstances  which, 
being  contingent,  are  not  the  same  in  all.  [d]  Natural 
laws  are  often  applied  in  circumstances  which  entail  a 
conflict  of  duties,  and  in  these  cases  duty  must  vary 
with  the  circumstances. 


170  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Thus  (a)  all  men  must  satisfy  their  appetite  for 
eating,  but  the  necessary  quantity  and  quality  of  food 
vary  with  the  individual.  Again,  all  men  are  naturally 
bound  to  avoid  drunkenness,  but  what  will  intoxicate 
one  man  will  not  intoxicate  another. 

(6)  The  relations  of  husband  to  wife,  of  father  to  child, 
of  ruler  to  subject,  of  buyer  to  seller,  from  all  of  which 
spring  certain  natural  relations  with  corresponding 
duties,  are  realised  only  in  the  case  of  some  individuals, 
and  hence  duty  is  not  the  same  in  all. 

(c)  The  natural  law  of  justice  "  give  everyone  his 
own  "  makes  the  obvious  condition  "  provided  you  are 
able  "  a  proviso  which  gives  rise  to  great  differences  in 
individual  duty.  The  solvent  man  and  the  bankrupt 
are  very  differently  situated  in  regard  to  the  require- 
ments of  natural  justice.  Again,  the  natural  law  "  be 
loyal  to  authority  "  supposes  the  condition  "  as  long  as 
authority  can  be  maintained,"  an  addition  that  may 
have  different  moral  effects  in  time  of  war  and  in  time 
of  peace,  in  the  case  of  a  competent  ruler  and  in  the 
case  of  a  fool. 

{d)  The  natural  duty  of  a  subject  to  obey  may  often, 
in  the  case  of  unjust  or  tyrannical  government,  come 
into  conflict  with  a  man's  natural  right  to  property  or 
with  his  duty  towards  his  family,  and  in  these  cases 
there  is  room  for  wide  differences  in  the  resultant  duty 
of  different  individuals. 

In  general,  then,  the  laws  of  nature,  though  common 
to  all,  do  not  lead  to  the  same  duty  in  all.  For  our 
natural  appetites,  though  common  to  all,  exist  and  work 
in  concrete  circumstances,  and  the  natural  laws  have 
to  be  applied  in  concrete  circumstances  ;  and,  therefore, 
just  as  the  requirements  of  the  human  body  vary 
with  the  circumstances,  though  in  all  men  the  natural 
functions  of  the  several  organs  arc  the  same,  so  also  the 
moral  requirements  of  individuals  and  of  society  may 
vary  with  individuals  though  our  specific  appetites  and 
nature  be  the  same. 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  171 

HISTORICAL   NOTE 

In  his  lectures  on  Kant,*  Professor  Simmel  has  some 
interesting  historical  remarks  on  the  question  raised  by 
this  last  difficulty — namely,  the  place  of  the  individual  duty 
in  our  ethical  systems.  The  deepest  and  most  important 
problem  of  modern  Ethics  is,  he  tells  us,  that  of  finding 
an  adequate  formula,  if  formula  it  might  be  called,  for  the 
rich  and  varied  morality  of  the  individual  life.  Of  modern 
philosophers,  according  to  Professor  Simmel,  the  first  to 
lay  stress  on  the  dignity  and  value  of  individual  morality 
was  Kant,  who,  in  his  theory  of  the  Autonomy  of  Reason, 
gave  as  the  ultimate  source  of  morality  for  each  man  not 
a  common  law  outside  of  individuals  but  the  individual 
conscience  itself.  However,  he  remarks  that  the  individual 
of  which  Kant  spoke  in  his  theory  of  Autonomy  was  not  the 
individual  of  the  concrete  world,  with  all  its  differentiating 
marks  and  habits,  but  the  "  man,"  the  individual "  humanity," 
"  das  reine  Ich,"  which,  being  the  same  in  all,  gave  rise  to  a 
similar  law  for  all.  Each  man's  good  was,  on  the  Kantian 
theory,  that  which  all  men  could  desire,  and  each  man's  right 
was  that  portion  of  the  universal  field  of  liberty  which  was 
left  to  each  when  all  liberties  were  equally  provided  for.  It 
was  a  theory  of  the  absolute  equality  of  men,  a  theory  of 
Liberalism  in  its  purest  and  most  unmodified  form. 

In  the  individualistic  philosophies  of  the  nineteenth  cen- 
tury which  followed — those,  namely,  of  Goethe,  Schleier- 
macher  and  the  Romanticists — a  new  and  still  fuller  con- 
ception was  given  of  individual  law  and  individual  ideals. 
To  bring  all  individuals,  these  philosophers  explained,  under 
a  common  life-formula,  to  oblige  them  to  the  pursuit  of  a 
common  ideal,  was  to  attempt  the  impossible.  For,  with 
tlieir  different  talents,  needs,  and  opportunities,  men  could 
not  in  all  things  follow  a  common  law  or  fulfil  the  same 
ideal,  and  to  expect  them  to  do  so  would  mean  the  suppres- 
sion in  them  of  much  that  was  good  and  great — namely, 
their  individual  perfections. 

The  Romanticist  principle,  then,  though  historically  an 
outcome  of  Kant's  individualism,  led,  according  to  Professor 
Simmel,  to  a  very  different  conception  of  the  rights  and 
duties  of  individuals  from  that  of  Kant.  For  in  the  Roman- 
ticist principle  provision  was  made  for  moral  differences 
depending  on  individual  requirements  and  individual  talents, 

*  "  Kant — Sechzehn  Vorlesungen  gehalten  an  der  Berliner  Uni- 
versitat,"  von  Georg  Simmel. 


172  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

that  is,  provision  was  made  for  individual  privileges,  whereas 
Kant's  theory  of  the  equal  freedom  of  all  men  excluded 
privilege.  The  one  recognised  the  necessity  of  division  of 
labour  according  to  innate  differences  of  talent  and  power, 
the  other  was  a  system  of  free  and  open  competition  among 
men  of  equal  initial  rights. 

The  individualising  movement  of  the  Romanticists  reached 
its  culminating  point  in  Nietzsche.  For  Nietzsche  the  indi- 
vidual was  supreme,  and  society  was  but  a  means  to  the 
individual.  Its  one  function  was  to  bring  out  the  highest 
worth  of  the  individual  personality,  to  make  the  highest 
exemplars  sovereign  in  the  State.  But,  for  Nietzsche,  the 
higher  nature  consisted  not  in  works  and  their  effects  but  in 
the  dignity  of  position  and  of  political  power  (Rang-Distanz). 

These  two  individualising  systems — that  of  Kant  in  the 
eighteenth  century  and  of  the  Romanticists  in  the  nineteenth 
— Professor  Simmel  distinguishes  by  the  names  "  quantita- 
tive "  and  "  qualitative  "  individualism.  "  Each  em- 
phasises," he  says,  "  a  particular  ideal,  and  it  almost  seems 
as  if  the  deepest  life-work  of  this  century  will  be  the  synthesis 
of  these  two." 

We  maintain,  however,  in  opposition  to  Professor  Simmel, 
that  the  synthesis  of  the  common  law  of  humanity  with 
individual  requirements  has  already  been  effected  in  the 
philosoph}^  of  Aristotle  and  St.  Thomas  Aquinas,  and  that 
the  formulae  which  Professor  Simmel  hopes  to  see  soon  syn- 
thesised — that  of  Kant  and  that  of  the  Romanticists — are 
both  merely  one-sided  exaggerations  of  the  view  we  have 
been  following  in  this  volume,  and  which  we  have  taken 
from  Aristotle — namely,  that  the  moral  law,  though  grounded 
in  nature,  is  yet  not  the  same  for  all,  since  the  natural  func- 
tions depend  largely  upon  individual  circumstances.  Still,  it 
is  as  "  men  "  that  we  are  moral,  and,  therefore,  the  radical 
requirements  or  appetites  on  which  morality  depends,  and 
the  primary  moral  principles  that  arise  out  of  them,  must  be 
the  same  for  all. 

(6)  Finally,  there  is  the  difficulty  which  wc  can 
scarcely  do  more  than  notice  here,  that  modern  science 
has  so  enlarged  and  enriched  our  views  of  nature  that 
our  theory  of  Natural  Morals,  which,  it  must  be  con- 
fessed, has  come  down  to  us  comparatively  unchanged 
from  the  Greek  philosophers,  must,  like  so  many  other 
ancient  conceptions,  be  discarded  as  naive  .ind  primitive 


THE  MORAL  CRITERIA  173 

and  as  unsuited  to  our  present  complex  view  of  nature, 
whether  of  the  material  world  or  of  human  relations. 
This  growing  complexity  of  our  view  of  Nature  has  been 
described  b^-  Professor  W.  H.  Fairbrother  in  "  Mind  "  * 
as  follows  : — 

"  The  conception  of  nature,  however,  in  the  mind  of 
the  modern  thinker  has  lost  the  simplicity  which  it 
possessed  in  the  early  philosophy.  Nature  is  still  a 
cosmos,  an  interrelated  whole  ;  perfection  is  still  con- 
ceived as  an  equilibrium  produced  by  proper  perform- 
ance of  function  by  each  part,  but  the  equilibrium  is  no 
longer  a  definite  state  which,  once  reached,  is  to  last 
for  ever.  .  .  .  The  equilibrium  is  a  moving  one.  Pro- 
gress consists  not  only  in  the  tendency  towards  a  state 
of  harmonious  balance  of  forces,  but  also  towards  higher 
stages  of  these  successive  rhythmic  wholes.  .  .  .  We 
can  now  see  the  inadequacy  of  the  Greek  conception  of 
the  Ethical  problem.     Man  is  dynamic  not  static,"  &c. 

Reply — We  insist  that  any  progress  that  has  been 
made  in  our  knowledge  of  the  practical  requirements  of 
the  several  natural  appetites  must  certainly  be  taken 
account  of  in  the  system  of  Natural  Morals.  We  are 
not  aware,  however,  that  the  new  and  larger  views  of 
modern  philosophers  on  the  extent  and  complexity  of 
the  natural  relations  have  added  much  to  our  know- 
ledge of  the  appetites  and  their  objects,  or  given  ua 
ground  for  change  in  our  moral  beliefs.  For,  in  the 
first  place,  most  of  our  knowledge  about  nature  has 
nothing  whatsoever  to  do  with  the  ethical  problem. 
Our  newly-acquired  knowledge  of  the  chemistry  of  the 
stars  has  nothing  to  do  with  our  theory  of  the  "  good  " 
and  of  duty.  For  the  "  good  "  and  duty  have  to  do 
with  human  nature  only,  not  with  nature  in  general, 
and  consequently  the  only  study  that  has  power  to  alter 
or  determine  an  ethical  view  is  the  stud}-  of  human 
nature. 

And  not  everything  in  human  nature  is  of  importance 
*  N.  S.,  Vol.  13,  page  38. 


174  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  Ethics,  but  only  the  natural  appetites.  Our  view, 
for  instance,  of  the  good  is  not  affected  by  our  theoi}^ 
of  the  relation  of  imagination  to  sense  or  of  the  place  of 
certain  arteries  and  bones  in  the  bodily  system.  And 
even  in  regard  to  the  natural  appetites  themselves  much 
of  our  knowledge  has  no  bearing  on  Ethics.  Ethics  is 
a  practical  science,  and,  therefore,  a  man  might  obtain 
much  speculative  knowledge  about  the  origin  of  the 
appetites  and  their  relation  to  knowledge,  without  in  the 
least  adding  to  his  store  of  ethical  knowledge,  just  as  the 
new  Physiology  has  not  added  to  our  knowledge  of  how 
to  satisfy  hunger,  nor  eradicated  the  old  view  of  the 
necessity  of  eating  and  drinking.  For  its  first  principles 
Ethics  has  to  do  with  only  the  practical  requirements 
of  the  natural  appetites  and  with  the  laws  of  their 
satisfaction.  But  science  has  added  little  to  our  know- 
ledge in  these  respects  ;  the  natural  appetites  are  all 
strongly-marked  definite  inclinations,  which  were  as 
well  known  to  the  ancient  Greeks  as  they  are  to  us, 
and  that  is  why  the  fundamental  laws  of  Ethics  were 
the  same  in  Greek  Philosophy  as  in  ours. 

But  to  contend  that  in  order  to  be  able  to  determine 
morality  we  should  first  determine  the  totality  of  the 
relations  that  hold  between  our  act  and  the  rest  of 
human  nature,  would  be  like  maintaining  that  an  athlete 
in  order  to  run  well  should  possess  a  perfect  knowledge 
of  the  laws  of  Dynamics.  Our  growing  knowledge  of 
Dynamics  has  not  made  us  better  runners  than  the 
Greeks  were.  There  is  no  a  priori  reason  why  every 
addition  to  our  knowledge  of  human  nature  should 
give  us  a  more  perfect  knowledge  of  our  rights  and 
duties.* 

•  The  reader  may  ask  why  "  right  Reason  "  has  not  been  enumerated 
as  one  of  the  moral  criteria,  considering  that  Aristotle  and  St.  Tiiomas 
make  appeal  to  it  so  frequently,  as  determining  "  good  "  and  "  evil." 
The  reason  is  that  "  right  Reason  "  could  not  be  used  by  itself  as  a 
criterion  of  goodness,  for  we  can  know  that  Reason  is  right  only  by 
comparing  it  with  the  appetites  and  their  objects  which  therefore,  and 
not  "  right  Reason,"  arc  the  criteria  by  wliicli  we  finally  judge  of  right 
and  wrong.     Let  us  suppose  for  a  uiomunt  that  "  right  Reason  "  were 


CHAPTER  VI 
FREEDOM  AND   MORALITY 

"  Ibi  incipit  genus  maris  ubi  primo  dominium  voluntatis  invenitur." 
St.  Thomas  Aquinas  2,  dist,  21,  q.  3,  a.  2. 

In  the  course  of  the  present  chapter  we  shall  treat  of  the 
following  points  :  {a)  What  is  freedom  ?  {h)  What  is 
the  ground  of  freedom  ?  or  how  is  the  will  free  ?  (c)  Of 
the  extent  of  freedom  ;  {d)  The  consequences  of  free- 
dom ;    [e)  Other  views  of  the  nature  of  freedom. 

{a)  What  is  freedom,  or,  to  make  the  question  more 
specific  still,  what  do  we  mean  when  we  say  that  the 
will  is  free  ?  The  popular  answer  would  be — the  will  is 
free  when  it  is  not  determined  to  any  one  course  of 
action,  or  when  it  is  antecedently  {i.e.,  prior  to  its  act) 
indifferent  to  many  courses.  And  for  the  general  pur- 
poses of  Ethics  such  a  definition  might  well  suffice — it 
is  certainly  true  so  far  as  it  goes.  But  the  problems 
raised  by  modern  ethicians  make  it  incumbent  on  us  to 
look  a  little  more  deeply  still  into  the  meaning  of  free- 
dom. In  the  conception  of  freedom  there  are  two 
distinct  moments  or  stages — one  negative,  the  other 
positive.     The    n&gaiive    moment    is    that    of    indeter- 

a  criterion.  The  question  would  then  most  obviously  arise — but  when 
is  Reason  right  ?  To  this  question  we  have  Aristotle's  answer : 
"  The  function,"  he  writes  (N.  E.,  VI.  2)  "  of  the  practical  Reason  is 
the  apprehension  of  truth  in  agreement  with  right  desire  {tov  M  irpaKTiKoD 
Kal  SiavorjTiKou  r]  dX-qdeia  o/noXdryuv  ^x"""'*  ''~U  <5pfs"  '''V  op^v)-  Right  desire 
therefore  is  the  ultimate  criterion.  In  his  commentary  on  the  fore- 
going passage  St.  Thomas  finely  explains  that  the  end  of  action  is 
detennined  by  nature,  but  the  means  to  it  are  discovered  by 
Reason  ;  and  therefore,  though  the  practical  Reason  is  a  rule  of  action, 
in  so  far  as  it  tells  us  what  means  will  lead  to  a  certain  end,  still  the 
means  are  not  right,  and  the  practical  Reason  which  recommends 
them  is  not  right,  imless  the  end  to  which  the  means  lead  is  right, 
"  from  which  it  follows,"  writes  St.  Thomas,  "  that  in  regard  to  the 
end,  rightness  of  appetite  is  the  criterion  by  which  we  judge  of  rightness 
in  the  practical  Reason." 

175 


176  THE  SCIE^XE  OF  ETHICS 

minateness — antecedent  indeterminateness  of  the  will 
both  from  within  and  from  without.  These  terms  we 
must  explain.  Indeterminateness  from  within  means 
that  the  will  is  n^t  determined  hy  its  nature  to  any  act. 
Indeterminateness  from  without  means  that  no  object 
outside  the  will  compels  the  will.  The  first  of  these 
really  reduces  to  the  second,  because,  since  the  will 
must  always  wish  for  ends  or  objects  beyond  itself,  to 
be  determined  by  its  own  inner  nature,  means  to  be 
compelled  by  nature  to  desire  some  known  object,  If, 
therefore,  the  will  is  determined  by  nature,  it  is  the 
object,  properl}^  speaking,  that  overcomes  the  will, 
but  it  overcomes  the  will  from  the  very  nature  of  the 
will.  Indeterminateness  of  will,  therefore,  means  in 
general  that  it  cannot  he  compelled  by  any  object.  This 
is  negative  freedom.  The  positive  moment  is  that  of 
self-determination  or  a  power  inherent  in  the  w'ill  to 
direct  itself  to  any  end. 

Let  us  take  these  two  moments  separately.  Negative 
freedom  means  antecedent  indetermination  [of  the  will]. 
Any  object  may  exert  an  attractive  influence  on  the 
will,  but  none  can  finally  overmaster  the  will.  Between 
exerting  an  attractive  influence  on  the  will  and  irre- 
sistibly moving  it  to  action  there  is  a  very  great  dif- 
ference. Thus,  I  suggest  to  a  friend  to  walk  out  into 
the  sunshine.  The  prospect  pleases  him,  attracts  him  ; 
yet  hiH  will  may  remain  quite  undetermined.  And  it 
may  remain  undetermined  as  long  as  the  person  wishes 
to  be  undetermined.  The  motion  or  determination  of 
a  will  which  is  antecedently  undetermined  follows  on  ^^|i 
the  issuing  to  itself  of  the  final  fiat,  and  that  fiat  can  be 
withheld  for  any  length  of  time  and  against  anj^  object. 
The  v^ill  must,  of  course,  move  to  objects  of  some  kind, 
but  in  the  case  of  freedom  it  is  the  will  itself  that  de- 
termines the  object  that  is  finally  to  prevail.  Now, 
rBesides  the  human  will  there  are  other  things  also  that 
can  resist  the  influence  of  outer  forces.  They  have 
what  we  call  inertia,  which  is  nothing  else  than  the 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  177 

power  to  offer  resistance  to  any  force  that  results,  or 
tends  to  result,  in  change.  But  there  is  all  the  difference 
in  the  world  between  the  inertia  of  material  bodies  and 
t^  indeterminateness  of  the  will.  For,  in  the  first 
place,  the  force  that  moves  a  body  must  reach  a  certain 
degree  of  strength  before  motion  becomes  possible, 
whereas  any  object  can  move  the  will  (though  not  irre- 
sistibly), no  matter  how  insignificant,  provided  only  it 
rises  above  the  threshold  of  our  consciousness.  Secondly, 
the  force  that  tends  to  move  a  body,  but  cannot  succeed 
in  doing  so,  bears  at  least  some  proportion  to  that 
force  which  will  finally  succeed  in  effecting  the  required 
movement.  It  is  (and  this  could  be  said  even  ante- 
cedently to  the  effect)  a  third  or  a  fourth  part  or  some 
other  fraction  of  the  force  that  will  finally  be  able  to 
overcome  the  inertia  of  and  move  the  body.  It  is  a 
part,  therefore,  of  the  force  that  will  of  necessity  result 
in  action,  and  it  has  consequently  only  to  be  increased 
sufficiently  in  order  to  produce  the  required  effect.  In 
the  case  of  the  will,  on  the  other  hand,  though  particular 
motives  may  exert  their  influence,  they  neither  move 
the  will  irresistibly  to  action,  nor  do  they  bear  any 
proportion  to  the  force  that  must  of  necessity  overcome 
the  will.  They  may  be  increased  to  any  extent,  and 
may  still  be  resisted  by  the  will.  A  motive  and  an 
irresistible  motive  are  not  the  same.  That  which  the 
will  desires  is  always  a  motive  urging  to  action.  But  a 
particular  motive  cannot  prove  irresistible  to  a  free 
will.  Indeterminateness,  then,  means  that  no  particular 
object,  no  matter  how  great,  can  prove  irresistible  to 
the  will. 

But  though  the  will  is  not  determined  by  any  par- 
ticular '  good  '  it  must  choose  some  '  good,'  and  what- 
ever it  chooses  it  must  choose  it  under  the  aspect  of  a 
good.  The  will  therefore  though  free  in  regard  to  par- 
ticular goods  is  determined  in  regard  to  its  final  object, 
the  good-in-general  and  the  infinite,  which  comprises  in 
itself  the  w^hole  content  of  the  good-in-general.  We 
Vol.  I— 12 


178  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

\  thus  see  that  the  freedom  of  the  will  extends  only  to 
the  choice  of  means  leading  to  the  final  end — it  is  de- 
termined in  regard  to  the  final  end. 

The  positive  moment  in  freedom  is  that  of  self-deter- 
mination. It  is  the  will  that  finally  determines  itself 
to  select  this  or  that  particular  means  as  leading  to  the 
final  end.  And  in  this  connection  the  question  arises 
of  the  manner  in  which  the  \yill  determines  jtself,  or — 
what  IS  the  psychological  mechanism  empoye3.  We 
rnswer — the  will   can   determine  itself  by   determining 

/  the  practical  judgments  of  the  intellect,  which  in  turn 
act  upon  the  will  and  move  it  to  action.  We  act,  in 
the  case  of  deliberate  movement,   only  in  response  to 

—  the  practical  judgment  of  our  own  intellect  telling  us 
"  this  is  the  thing  to  be  done."  And  as  it  is  the  free 
will  that  determines  the  intellect  to  elicit  this  judgment 
(how,  we  shall  presently  enquire)  the  free  wiU,  in  de- 
termining the  practical  judgment  of  the  intellect,  is 
properly  speaking,  the  cause  also  of  its  own  act — it  is 
self-caused,*  and  self-determined.  "  Liberum,"  says  St. 
Thomas,  "  Qst_id  quod  est  causa,.j8ui-"  The  will  is  free 
when  it  is  the  cause  of  its  own  action.  This  is  the 
positive  moment  in  the  conception  of  freedom. 

Now,  some  philosophers  have  maintained  that  to  be 
antecedently  determined  to  an  action  by  inner  nature — 
to  be  necessitated  by  our  inner  nature — is  to  be  deter- 
mined by  ourselves,  and,  therefore,  to  be  free.  But  our 
contention  is  that  to  be  the  cause  of  our  own  act — that 
is,  to  be  free — and  to  be  determined  to  an  action  by 
inner  nature  are  contradictory  conceptions.  For  a 
natural  tendency,  or  a  tendency  that  arises  out  of  inner 
nature,  that  follows  of  necessity'  from  nature,  must  be 
present  in  a  subject  from  the  moment  that  that  subject 
begins  to  exist,  and  consequently  such  a  tendency 
cannot  be  set  up  within  the  subject  by  the  subject  itself, 
or  in  the  case  of  the  will  b}-  the  will  itself,  but  is  placed 
there  by  whatever  agency  produced  the  subject  or  the 
*  In  the  sonBO  that  the  act  of  ths  will  is  caused  by  the  will  itself. 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  179 

will,  and  ^ave  to  it  its  nature.  And  as  no  finite  thing 
can  be  the  cause  of  its  own  nature;  so  nothing  can  be 
the  cause  of  its  own  natural  or  necessary  desires.  To 
be  free  we  must  be,  as  Aristotle  says,  "  masters  of  our 
own  acts  from  beginning  to  end  "  {(Itt'  u/^x^l^  m«XP'  toitcAoi-s 
Kvpioi).  And  again,  a  free  act  must  proceed  from  no 
other    source    than    those    that    depend    on    ourselves 

(uv      .       .      .      £is   dAAa?   dpx<'-'i   Trapa    ra-;    €(/>'    771111', — Nich.    Eth. 

III.  5.)- 

To  be  free,  then,  it  is  not  sufficient  that  a  movement 
comes  from  within  our  wills  or  that  it  be  psychological. 
To  be  free  a  movement  must  he  placed  within  the  will  by 
the  agency  of  the  will  itself,  and  not  by  causes  other  than 
the  will,  e.g.,  by  nature.  The  work  done  by  an  explod- 
ing shell  proceeds,  indeed,  from  within  the  shell.  Still, 
the  shell  is  not  a  free  agent,  because  the  energy  that  it 
sends  forth  was  previously  "  given  "  in  its  chemical^ 
and  these  chemicals  were  not  placed  there  by  the  agency 
of  the  shell  itself,  but  by  another  who  made  it. 

Freedom,  therefore,  or  the  causation  of  our  own  act, 
supposes  antecedent  indeterminateness  of  the  will,  which! 
excludes,    first,    negatively,    previous   determination   by  \ 
object,    secondly,   previous   determination   by   the  very  \ 
nature  of  the  will  or  by  any  quality  or  disposition  of 
nature  not  controlled  by  will,  both  of  which  conditions 
may  be  expressed  by  saying  that  the  sum  of  the  exist- 
ing conditions  at   any  particular  moment  does  not  of 
necessity  imply  the  action  of  the  next.     Freedom  also 
supposes,   positivel}^  that  the  will  can  bring  about  its 
own  states  or   desires  independent  1}-   of   previous   con- 
ditions. 


CRITICISM   OF    SOME   OTHER   VIEWS 

{a)  Freedom  is  not  the  same  as  "  psychologically  deter- 
mined action,  or  the  power  to  act  in  accordance  with  the 
considered  choice  of  ends  "  (Wundt).  In  the  working  out  of 
this  view  Wundt  maintains  that  in  order  to  establish  the 
freedom  of  the  will  {in  his  sense)  it  is  enough  to  show  that 


i8o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

actions  of  the  will  depend  not  upon  physiological  but  upon 
psychological  conditions — that  is,  upon  knowledge — and 
that  consequently  every  psychologically  determined  action  is 
free.  But  there  can  be  acts  psychologically  conditioned 
which  yet  are  not  free — for  instance,  the  desire  for  happiness. 
Freedom  entails  more  than  mere  knowledge  or  will.  For 
freedom  an  act  must  be  antecedently  undetermined  whether 
from  within  or  from  without ;  and  the  will  must  cause  its 
own  desire. 

{h)  Freedom  is  not  the  same  as  "  causal  energy  of  the 
will  "  (Calderwood).  For,  freedom  contains  more  than  mere 
causation.  The  will  could  be  causal  without  being  self- 
caused  in  the  sense  of  determining  itself  to  its  acts,  just  as 
the  stone  thrown  at  the  window  is  causal  in  reference  to 
the  breaking  of  the  glass,  whilst  at  the  same  time  it  does 
not  determine  itself  to  that  effect.  Freedom  is  Sd'//-causation, 
in  sense  of  self-determination  to  action. 

(c)  Neither  is  freedom  "  motiveless  volition  "  (Hamilton), 
or,  as  Kant  defines  it,  the  "  utter  abnegation  of  every  desire  " 
— i.e.,  of  every  end  outside  the  will.  No  act  of  the  will  is 
motiveless.  Every  act  of  the  will  is  a  desire  for  some  end, 
and  freedom  is  the  capacity  of  the  will  to  follow  from  itself 
alone  any  motive  that  may  come  before  it  rather  than  any 
other.  To  will  without  following  some  motive  or  object 
would  be  like  walking  without  a  direction. 

{d)  Freedom  is  not  "  the  inactive  influence  of  motives  " 
(Reid).  A  motive,  according  to  Reid,  may  influence  the 
will  to  act  but  does  not  itself  act.  But,  that  motives  are 
themselves  active,  even  in  cases  in  which  we  are  usually 
accounted  free,  is  evident  from  the  fact  that  the  will  has 
often  to  resist  the  motives  of  action  in  order  to  set  them  aside. 

{e)  Freedom  is  not  "  causeless  volition  "  *  (Wundt).  A 
free  act,  in  sense  of  self-determination  is  caused  both  finally 
and  efficiently — finally,  since  the  will  must  choose  from 
amongst  the  many  ends  or  motives  acting  on  it,  and 
efficiently  because  the  will  is  itself  the  efficient  cause  of  its 
own  act. 

(/)  Freedom  is  not  "  a  purely  negative  contentless  con- 
cept "    (Hartmann),    for   besides    the   negative    moment    of 


•  Gimpare  this  with  (a)  above.  Wundt  argues  that  froodom,  in  our 
sense  of  antccodcntly  indiUiTiniiicd  action,  is  a  causeless  volition,  and, 
therefore,  an  impossible  conception.  The  proper  sense  of  freedom  is, 
he  maintains,  that  of  an  act  psychologically  determined,  in  which 
sense  it  is  a  genuine  property  of  will.  We  show  above  that  freedom  of 
the  will  is  neither  psychological  determination  nor  causeless  volition. 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY       i8i 

freedom — the  moment,  namely,  of  indeterminability  by  par- 
ticular ends — there  is  also  the  positive  moment  of  "  self- 
determination,"  the  power  of  the  will  to  control  and  rnle 
itself,  to  direct  itself  to  the  pursuit  of  any  end. 


(6)  The  Proof  and  Ground  of  Freedom 

The  proof  of  freedom  belongs,  properly  speaking,  to 
Psychology.*  We  shall  here  adduce  but  one  argument 
for  freedom — namely,  that  argument  which,  besides 
being  proof,  gives  also  the  psychological  ground  of 
freedom. 

First,  as  regards  the  negative  side  of  freedom.  The 
will  is  undetermined  in  respect  of  particular  objects 
because  no  particular  good  can  bg  regarded  as  indis- 
pensable to  the  will.  The  natural  end  of  the  will  is  the 
good-in-general,  and  that  end  is  present  to  the  will  in 
every  particular  desire.  Hence,  let  any  particular  object 
come  up  before  the  will  as  end,  there  are  always  other 
rival  objects  there,  contained  under  this  general  con- 
ception of  the  good-in-general,  and  these  rival  objects 
make  the  original  object  or  objects  dispensable  and  un- 
necessary. Thus,  to  take  an  example  of  a  particular 
object,  a  man  may  think  of  goin^  into  the  country. 
He  is  drawn  on  to  do  so  by  the  attractive  power  of 
fresh  air,  health,  and  amusement.  Were  going  to  the 
country  the  only  idea  before  the  will,  the  will  should, 
perhaps,  be  overmastered  and  determined  by  that 
idea.  But  this  is  only  one  of  the  many  goods  contained 
under  the  more  general  end — "  the  good  or  the  pleasant- 
in-general  " — which  is  the  proper  and  adequate  object 
of  the  will,  and  which  is  present  to  the  will  in  every  act. 


♦  The  proof  given  here  consists  in  showing  that  in  the  will  the  con-. 
ditions  and  machinery,  or  what  we  call  the  ground  of  freedom,  are 
present.  The  arguments  from  introspection  and  common  consent, 
on  which  some  philosophers  rely  exclusively  for  their  proof  of  freedom, 
are  seen  to  have  great  weight,  at  least  when  taken  in  conjunction 
with  the  above. 


i82  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

and  the  possibility  of  following  out  any  one  of  these 
many  rival  ends  removes  the  indispensabilit}'  of  the 
original  desire.  Except,  therefore,  the  infinite  good 
there  is,  no  single  object  or  desire  which  can  completel}^ 
overmaster  the  human  will,  and  this  indeterminateness 
is  what  we  mean  by  negative  freedom. 

Again,  the  will  must  in  every  action  desire  the 
"  good."  It  cannot  wish  evil  or  defect  as  such — this 
is  its  only  natural  limitation.  Now,  the  only  object 
that  presents  to  the  will  no  element  of  defect  is  the 
Infinite  Good,  and  bonum  in  universali,  and,  therefore, 
the  Infinite  cannot  be  resisted  by  our  wills.  But  every 
finite  object  embodies  either  what  is  or  what  the  will 
may  regard  as  a  defect — the  defect,  namely,  of  ex- 
cluding some  good — and  since  the  will  can  just  fix  the 
attention  of  the  intellect  upon  that  defect,  and  regard 
the  object  just  in  that  aspect  of  excluding  a  good,  it 
follows  that  a  finite  object  may  always  be  rejected  by 
the  will  as  evil.  Hence  no  finite  object  can  determine 
the  will. 

--  The  positive  moment  of  freedom  has  as  its  ground  the 
■  control  by  the  will  of  the  practical  judgments  of  the 
intellect.  The  will  is  able  to  reverse  or  accept  any  of 
the  particular  practical  judgments,  and  to  determine  by 
what  judgment  it  itself  is  finally  to  be  moved.  This  is 
positive  freedom.  Now,  the  order  obtaining  between 
intellect  and  will  in  reference  to  our  action  is,  as  we 
know  from  experience,  the  following  :  (i)  The  forma- 
tion by  the  intellect  of  a  practical,  which,  as  we  have 
seen,  is  also  a  contingent,  judgment.  (2)  Reflection  by 
intellect  on  the  contingency  of  this  judgment  and  an 
intimation  given  to  the  will  that  it  is  good  or  bad  to 
sustain  and  follow  this  judgment,  or  to  upset  it,  and 
substitute  a  new  judgment  for  it.  (3)  Selection  by  the 
will  of  one  particular  practical  judgment  at  its  own 
choice. 

Let  us  now  examine  these  steps  in  greater  detail  nnd 
see  how  they  stand  in  relation  to  intellect  and  will. 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALiiY  183 

We  will  take  our  previous  example — tlic  judgment  "  I 
must   go   to   the   country."     To   faculi'       '■' ■    "^*- '      t 

and  will,  that  have  as  their  constant :i- 

general  and  the  good-in-general,  this  jiKl^mQnt^JjjjPlpwst 
go  to  the  country  "  at  once  suggests  the  other — "  I 
must  not  go  to  the  country,"  or  "  I  must  stay  at  home." 
This  is  the  first  step  in  the  human  act.  Now,  neither  of 
these  two  judgments—"  I  must  go  "  or  "I  must  stay  " 
— is  a  necessary  judgment,  because  in  the  practical 
sphere  the  only  absolutely  necessary  judgment  is  "  that 
the  good  is  to  be  done,"  which  judgment  embodies  as 
subject  the  "  good "  or  the  good-in-general,  which  is 
the  only  adequate  object  of  the  will.  Since,  therefore, 
neither  of  the  other  particular  judgments — "  I  must  go  " 
or  "  I  must  stay  " — is  an  adequate  object  for  the  will, 
the  intellect  is  not  over-borne  or  determined  by  them, 
and  remains  in  regard  to  them  in  a  state  of  suspense  or 
indifference.  Now,  as  we  know  from  experience,  an 
intellectual  faculty  is  capable  of  reflection,  and  in  re- 
flecting on  these  judgments  the  intellect  must  of  neces- 
sity realise  their  contingent  and  unnecessary  character. 
But  to  realise  their  contingency  is  to  find  them  re- 
versible, and,  therefore,  it  is  as  reversible  that  these 
judgments  are  presented  to  the  will.  This  is  the  second 
step  in  the  process  of  the  human  act.  Now,  the  will 
is  essentially  a  moving  faculty,  one  that  moves  the  other 
powers  to  their  ends,  and  therefore  it  is  that,  finding  the 
intellect  neutral,  and  therefore  movable  or  detertninable  as 
regards  its  two  judgments,  the  will  is  able  to  move  the 
intellect  to  the  adoption  of  either  of  them  according  to 
the  will's  own  choice.  This  is  the  third  and  final  step 
in  the  process  of  freedom,  the  determining  of  the  judg^ 
ments  whereby  it  is  itself  to  be  moved.  And  this  power 
of  determining  the  practical  judgments  of  the  intellect 
may  be  exercised  by  the  human  will  not  only  in  cases 
in  which  the  motives  happen  to  be  equal  but  also  in 
cases  in  which  the  motives  are  unequal.  One  object 
ipay  be  more  attractive  than  the  other,  either  because 


iSi  tin:  science  of  ethics 

of  mor-e  iubereni  goodness  or  because  it  better  suits  oui 
pers«Q  character  and  wants.  Still,  there  stands  the 
V. ill,  master  of  the  judgments  of  the  intellect,  and  able 
to  nn'erse  them  according  to  its  own  choice  and  to 
men  (^  the  intellect  to  the  acceptance  of  any  one  of  them. 
It  is  in  its  power  to  determine  that  judgment  which  it 
is  itself  to  follow  that  the  will  is  spoken  of  as  self- 
determined  and  free.  But,  as  we  have  said,  it  deter- 
mines itself  not  immediately  and  directly  but  through 
a  practical  judgment  of  its  own  selection. 

The  ground  of  freedom,  then,  is  the  relation  obtaining 
between  the  universal  and  the  particular  judgments  of 
the  intellect ;  but  an  essential  requisite  of  freedom — 
and  what  we  might  caU  the  hinge  of  freedom — is  our 
power  of  reflection  on  our  own  judgments  and  of 
realising  their  contingenc}^  and  it  seems  to  us  that 
it  is  upon  this  power  to  return  upon,  to  reflect  upon  our 
own  judgments  (de  sue  judicio  judicare  *)  that  St. 
Thomas  lays  most  stress  in  his  exposition  and  proof 
of  freedom.f 


*  "  Dc  Veritate,"  Q.  XXIV.,  Art.  2. 

f  The  reader  should  remember  that  much  of  what  we  have  above 
written  on  the  mutual  inter-relation  of  will  and  intellect  is  matter  of 
ordinary  experience.  Experience  tells  us,  for  instance,  that  we  are 
finally  moved  to  action  by  the  practical  judgments  of  the  intellect, 
and  also  that  the  will  has  power  to  influence  these  judgments.  The 
further  question — how  the  will  has  this  power  and  how  far  the  power 
extends — can  only  be  known  through  a  comparison  of  the  natural 
and  necessary  object  of  the  will  (the  good -in-general)  with  the  objects 
of  particular  judgments,  as  shown  above. 

It  is  interesting  to  compare  St.  Thomas  Aquinas'  view  on  the 
ground  of  freedom  with  that  of  recent  transcendental ists.  St.  Thomas 
bases  the  freedom  of  the  will  on  the  relation  that  subsists  between 
will  and  Reason,  and  on  the  fact  that  Reason  has  as  its  object  bcing- 
in-general  and  not  any  particular  kind  of  being.  Modern  transcen- 
dentalists  ba.sc  freedom  on  the  relation  of  the  self  to  it.'s  desires — on 
the  existence  in  man  of  a  permanent,  universal  self  distinct  from  and 
above  particular  desires  (.see  Seth,  "  Ethical  Principles,"  p.  375).  On 
the  Scliolastic  view  the  ground  is  Rca.son  and  will,  having  as  objects 
IJcing  and  the  good-in-gencral.  On  the  Transcendentalist  view  the 
ground  is  the  universal  self  .'is  director  and  centre  of  all  particular 
(icsircs.  The  two  most  striking  weaknesses  in  the  transcendentalist 
theory  arc,  first,  that  to  transcendentalists  generally  the  "  self  "  is 
not  a  mibstance.  It  must  then  be  either  a  faculty  or  simply  a  bundle 
u£  habits.     If  it  is  a  faculty  the  transcendentalist  theory  is  only  a 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  185 

(c)  The  Extent  of  Freedom 

Before  proceeding  to  determine  the  extent  of  freedom, 
we  must  enquire — Over  what  faculties  does  the  free  will 
exercise  a  mastery,  and  how  far  ?  The  question  is  most 
important  for  our  present  enquiry,  and  we  must  give  at 
least  a  general  answer  to  it.  (i)  The  free  will  controls, 
in  the  first  place,  all  the  judgments  of  the  intellect  except 
such  as  are  analytic  or  self-evident.  It  does  not  extend 
to  the  judgment  that  "  the  good  is  to  be  done,"  nor  to 
such  axiomatic  judgments  of  the  speculative  intellect  as 
that  "  the  whole  is  greater  than  the  part,"  that  "  two 
and  two  are  four,"  or  that  "  nothing  can  be  a  thing  and 
its  contradictory  at  the  same  time."  These  and  such 
judgments  control  the  intellect,  and  the  will  has  no 
power  to  suspend  our  acceptance  of  them  or  to  reverse 
them.  (2)  The  free  will  to  a  large  extent  controls  atten- 
tion. There  are  very  few  things  on  which  a  man  cannot 
at  will  bestow  or  refuse  to  bestow  his  attention,  and  it 
is  by  giving  or  refusing  attention  to  objects  that  we 
are  able  to  increase  or  to  counteract  their  effect  upon 
our  appetites.  (3)  The  will  can  control  the  senses,  but 
only  indirectly.  If  the  eye  be  open  it  cannot  refrain 
from  seeing.  But  the  free  will  can  in  normal  cases 
close  the  eye,  and  consequently  control  the  sense. 
(4)  The  will  has  no  power  over  the  vegetative  facult}^ 
Growth  and  digestion  are  in  no  way  dependent  on  a 
man's  will,  granted  a  sufficient  supply  of  food  and 
health.  (5)  The  motor  faculty  is  to  a  large  extent 
under  a  man's  control — how  far  it  is  not  easy  to  say. 
Physiology  does,  indeed,  distinguish  between  voluntary 
and  involuntary  muscles,  and  even  attempts  a  physio- 
logical explanation  of  why  some  movenfents  are  subject 

weaker  form  of  the  "  Scholastic  "  view.  If  it  is  a  bundle  of  habits 
merely  or  what  is  usually  known  as  character,  we  cannot  see  how  it  is 
related  to  the  particular  desires  as  universal  is  related  to  particular, 
since  character  is  particular.  Secondly,  if  the  ground  of  freedom  is  a 
self,  distinct  from  our  passing  desires,  then  animals  are  free  as  well 
as  men,  since  they  also  are  selves  distinct  from  their  desires.  However 
a  full  discussion  of  this  subject  belongs  not  to  Ethics  but  to  Psychology 


i86  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  will  and  others  are  not  by  marking  out  a  structural 
difference  in  the  two  classes  of  nerves  connected  with 
these  muscles.  But  as  yet  we  have  had  no  satisfactory 
explanation  on  the  point,  and  merely  know  that  while 
some  movements  are  capable  of  being  controlled  by 
will  others  are  independent  of  our  control.  We  walk, 
speak,  and  move  the  eyes  at  will.  On  the  other  hand, 
the  heart  beats  independently  of  our  wills.  We  can 
neither  stop  it  directly  nor  set  it  on. 

This  is  an  indication  in  outline  of  the  extent  of  the 
control  which  the  will  exercises  over  our  faculties,  and 
from  it  we  may  determine  the  extent  of  freedom.  For, 
having  proved  that  the  will  is  free,  it  follows  that  it  is 
free  in  its  control  of  the  faculties  we  have  just  men- 
tioned, and  that  the  acts  of  these  faculties  are  also  free, 
as  coming  under  the  control  of  the  will.  Freedom, 
therefore,  extends,  in  the  first  place,  to  every  act  of 
will  except  the  desire  for  our  last  end  ;  secondly,  to 
the  acts  of  the  other  faculties  in  so  far  as  they  come 
under  the  control  of  will. 

Passing  from  the  question  which  faculties  are  and 
which  are  not  under  the  control  of  a  free  will,  and 
what  acts  may  or  can  be  free,  we  further  ask  concern- 
ing the  ordinary  daily  exercises  of  our  free  faculties 
how  many  such  exercises  are  free  ?  When  consciously 
and  deliberately  performed  they  are,  of  course,  aU  free. 
But  then  we  know  by  experience  that  most  acts  are 
done  without  much  thought  and  deliberation,  and  the 
question,  therefore,  arises — ^Is  it  necessary,  in  order  that 
an  act  be  free,  that  a  formal  and  protracted  delibera- 
tion should  precede  it  ?  We  answer — for  freedom  it  is 
not  necessary  that  a  fornlal  deliberation  or  choice  of 
alternatives  should  precede  our  acts.  It  is  not  even 
necessary  that  the  alternatives  should  come  distinctly 
before  the  mind.  It  is  enough  if  even  the  negative  of 
the  action  presents  itself  to  consciousness  and  in  the 
most  confused  manner  and  momentarily.  And  this 
negative  of  the  original  judgment  is  suggested  to  us  in 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  187 

nearly  ever  case,  and  is  practically  always  within  the 
border-line  of  our  consciousness.  Hence  those  philo- 
sophers *  are  quite  in  error  who  maintain  that  most  of 
our  daily  actions  are  not  free,  on  the  ground  that  they 
are  not  preceded  by  a  lengthy  or  a  formal  deliberation, 
and  because  we  do  not  at  each  moment  make  conscious 
choice  between  one  course  of  action  and  another,  and 
])ecause  most  men  allow  themselves  to  drift — that  is, 
to  take  the  line  of  least  resistance,  except  when  there 
are  special  reasons  for  exercising  special  control.  Our 
contention  is  that  the  ordinary  acts  of  the  day,  even 
what  are  called  the  unthinking  acts,  are  practically  all 
free,  because  there  is  sufficient  thought  and  deliberation 
in  them  to  make  them  free.  Confusion  in  our  thought 
may  lessen  freedom.  It  could  scarcel}^,  except  in  very 
extreme  cases,  remove  it  altogether. 


The  consideration  of. objections  to  freedom  properly 
belongs  to  Metaphysics  or  Psychology,  not  to  Ethics.  Here, 
however,  on  account  of  its  importance  in  recent  philosophy, 
we  wish  to  touch  upon  just  one  objection — that,  namely, 
which  concerns  the  law  of  the  Conservation  of  Energy.  It  is 
an  objection  that  we  believe  is  based  upon  a  misconception, 
for  it  really  tells  not  against  freedom  but  against  "  will," 
and,  therefore,  is  as  much  a  difficulty  for  the  Determinist  as 
for  the  Libertarian.  It  may  be  stated  thus  : — If  a  man 
freely  moves  a  limb,  he  has  to  expend  energy  in  doing  so. 
Now,  just  as  when  I  strike  the  table  with  my  hand,  the 
energy  that  appears  in  the  table  as  heat  must  necessarily 
have  come  from  the  cause  of  the  action — my  hand — so  also 
the  energy  that  moves  the  limb  must  come  ultimately  from 
that  which  causes  the  motion — namely,  our  will.  The  cause 
of  the  act  loses  energy,  the  recipient  gains  it.  Hence,  since 
in  free  acts  the  will  is  the  initial  cause  of  all,  the  energy  of 
all  such  material  acts  as  come  under  the  control  of  free  will 
must,  in  this  theory  of  freedom,  have  first  proceeded  from 
the  will.  There  is,  then,  a  constant  flow  of  energy  from  the 
will  into  the  material  world  which  is  quite  incompatible  with 


*  e.g.,  Father  Maher,  "  Psychology," 


i88  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  Law  of  Conservation — that  the  sum  of  energy  in  the 
material  world  is  constant. 

We  reply — (i)  The  Law  of  the  Conservation  of  Energy  is 
an  unproved  hypothesis.  (2)  Granted,  however,  that  it 
represents  an  established  fact,  it  in  no  way  conflicts  with 
the  theory  of  free  will.  The  reader  will  remember  that  we 
are  here  dealing  with  the  question  of  material  energy  only — 
energ}'  that  can  be  transformed  into  motion,  for  that  is  the 
only  energy  of  which  the  Law  of  Conservation  can  logically 
take  cognisance.  Now,  where,  in  the  theory  of  freedom, 
does  this  material  energy  come  from,  in  the  case  of  the  moving 
limb  ?  Our  point  is  that  it  does  not  come  from  the  will. 
The  muscular  energy  that  moves  our  limbs  when  acted  upon 
by  the  will  comes,  not,  as  our  opponents  suppose,  from  the 
will,  but  from  the  limb  itself,  and  from  the  body  generally. 
When  we  run,  it  is  the  body  that  grows  tired,  not  the  will, 
because  the  body  has  been  giving  out  energy,  but  the  will 
has  not.  The  energy,  then,  that  manifests  itself  in  the  moving 
limb,  the  energy  that  is  turned  into  motion  must  have  existed 
previously,  not  in  the  will,  but  in  the  body,  and,  therefore, 
on  our  theory,  the  sum  of  material  energy  in  the  world  is  tlie 
same  after  motion  as  before.  Our  point,  then,  is  that  the 
will  may  affect  the  muscles  without  sendmg  into  them 
muscular  energy,  and  they  are  incapable  of  receiving  any 
other  kind  of  energy  than  muscular.  Hence  the  theory  of 
Freedom  docs  not  suppose  an  inflow  of  energy  from  the  will 
to  the  material  world. 

Our  opponents,  however,  may  argue — Your  answer  only 
raises  an  additional  difliculty,  for  even  to  turn  the  static 
energy  of  limb  or  muscle  into  the  kinetic  energy  of  motion 
plainly  requires  an  expenditure  of  energy  in  the  will,  and 
since  this  energy  cannot  be  lost  it  must  go  to  swell  the  sum 
of  energies  in  the  material  world.  We  answer — to  turn 
static  into  kinetic  energy  requires  certainly  activity  of  some 
kind  in  the  will  which  initiates  the  change,  but  it  does  not 
require  a  flow  of  energy  out  of  our  wills  into  t/ial  body,  the 
static  energy  of  which  is  being  turned  into  kinetic.  If  we 
might  adopt  an  illustration  from  Physics — a  stone  supported 
above  the  ground  possesses  static  energy.  Remove  the  sup- 
port, the  static  enexgy  is  transformed  into  kinetic,  and  the 
stone  falls  to  the  ground.  Hut  no  new  energy  has  been  added 
to  the  stone.  So  also  in  moving  a  limb  the  will  must  exer- 
cise activity  of  some  kind — some  kind,  perhaps,  of  psychical 
or  mental  energy.  But  whatever  may  be  the  active  process 
within  the  v.ill,  it  need  not  in  changing  static  into  kinetic 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  189 

energy  send  energy  into  the  muscle.  In  all  bodily  movement, 
therefore,  the  material  energy  of  the  material  world  is  the 
same  after  movement  as  before.  What  happens  within  the 
will  itself,  or  what  this  psychical  energy  is  which  enables  the 
will  to  move  a  muscle,  or  whether  it  bears  an  analogy  to 
that  kind  of  energy  which  can  be  turned  into  motion,  or  what 
"  expenditure  "  means  within  the  will,  are  points  that  do  not 
affect  the  present  question,  for  the  law  of  Conservation  of 
Energy  can  only  have  reference  to  that  material  energy  which 
can  be  transformed  into  motion,  and  can  be  measured  in 
terms  of  work.  The  question  also  how  the  wiU  can  act  on 
the  body  and  direct  the  energies  of  the  body^ — a  question 
to  which,  indeed,  this  problem  of  Conservation  ultimately 
leads  us  back — is  beyond  the  scope  of  our  present  enquiry, 
and  is  a  question  for  the  Psychologist  not  for  the  Ethician, 
since  it  is  nothing  more  than  a  particular  application  of  the 
general  question  how  the  body  and  the  soul  are  related  in 
the  individual.  It  is  not  proper  to  the  narrower  question 
of  freedom.  The  difficulty,  therefore,  about  Conservation 
comes  finally  to  this — how  soul  moves  body,  how  thought 
moves  to  act,  a  question  which  requires  to  be  answered  by 
Determinist  as  well  as  by  Indeterminist. 


{(l)  Consequence  of  Freedom 

The  formal  consequence  of  freedom  is  iMPUTABfLiTY. 
Imputability  means  attributing  something  to  a  person 
or  putting  a  thing  down  to  a  person  in  praise  or  blame. 
It  means,  therefore,  ownership,  causation,  production  of 
what  we  do,  and  it  supposes  that  man  is  the  cause  not 
merely  of  the  effect  of  his  act  but  of  the  act  itself. 
But  only  the  free  will  is  the  cause  of  its  own  act.  A 
stone  may  cause  the  breaking  of  a  window  considered 
as  an  effect,  but  a  stone  cannot  cause  its  own  act — its 
own  motion.  He  who  directs  the  stone  is  cause  both 
of  the  act  and  (mediately  also)  of  the  effect.  Anything, 
therefore,  that  is  determined  by  nature  to  an  end, 
though  it  may  be  the  cause  of  effects  produced,  yet 
cannot  be  the  cause  of  its  own  determination  to  its 
own  act.     Imputability,  then,  depends  on  freedom,  and 


190  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

is  the  formal  consequence  of  freedom.*  Consequently, 
if  a  man  were  determined  to  an  action  either  by  nature, 
or  by  some  ph3-siological  cause,  or  by  the  will  and 
intellect  losing  their  power  over  the  other  faculties,  he 
would  not  be  the  cause  of  that  action,  but  the  subject 
only,  and  the  act  would  not  be  imputable  to  him. 
Hence  Hamlet's  protest : — 

"  VVas't  Hamlet  wronged  Laertes  ?     Never  Hamlet 
If  Hamlet  from  himself  he  ta'en  away  ; 
And  when  he's  not  himself  does  wrong  Laertes, 
Then  Hamlet  does  it  not,  Hamlet  denies  it." 

{e)   Other  Theories  of  Freedom 

We  may  now  compare  our  theory  of  freedom  with 
two  theories  closely  allied  to  and  at  the  same  time 
wholly  distinct  from  ours — namely,  the  theories  of  Kant 
and  Hegel.  These  theories  we  select  because  of  their 
bearing  on  the  Ethical  question  of  the  relation  between 
freedom  and  morality  to  be  discussed  later. 

(i)  kant's  theory  of  freedom 

We  may  regard  Kant's  initial  definition  of  freedom 
as  equivalent  to  that  which  is  given  in  the  Scholastic 
writings.  "  The  will,"  Kant  writes,  f  "is  a  kind  of 
causality  belonging  to  living  beings,  in  so  far  as  they 
are  rational ;  and  freedom  would  be  this  property  of 
such  causality  that  it  can  be  efficient  independently  of 
foreign  causes  determining  it."  Here  freedom  is  defined 
as  self-determination  of  the  will,  and  it  will  be  re- 
membered that  this  is  precisely  the  notion  of  freedom 
which  is  given  us  by  the  Scholastic  ethicians,  and  which 
we  have  adopted  as  our  delinition  of  freedom  in  the 
present  chapter — the  will  is  free  when  it  determines 
its  own  acts,  its  own  wishes.     But  when  we  come  to 

•  Wc  shall  sec  later  on  that  a  natural  title  of  ownership  is  pro- 
duction. 

t  "  Metaphysic  of  Morals  "  (Abbot),  page  G5. 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  191 

ask  the  further  question  what  is  meant  by,  or  what  are 
the  conditions  of,  self-determination  we  find  that  these 
two  theories  of  freedom,  which  apparently  include  the 
same  notions,  are  in  reality  very  different  from  each 
other.  It  will  be  evident  to  the  reader  that  in  the 
theory  of  freedom  which  is  advocated  in  this  work, 
there  is  nothing  to  prevent  even  a  free  and  self-deter- 
mined will  from  wishing  for  ends  or  objects  beyond 
itself,  from  wishing  for  them  for  their  own  sake,  or 
for  the  pleasure  of  them.  Self-determination,  in  the 
Scholastic  sense,  implies  onl}-  this — that  the  wiU  is  the 
efficient  cause  of  its  own  act,  its  own  desire.  But  a  will 
might  be  the  efficient  cause  of  its  own  act  of  willing, 
even  though  that  act  of  willing  concerned  some  outer 
object,  since  the  will  might  itself  have  brought  about 
its  own  choice  of,  or  its  own  determination  towards 
that  object,  and  to  bring  about  its  own  act  is  freedom. 
In  other  words,  the  outer  object  desired,  the  outer  end 
for  the  sake  of  which  we  do  a  particular  act,  is  not 
always  the  dckrinining  factor  in  choice.  In  willing,  the 
will  is  often  the  determining  cause  of  its  own  act,  even 
though  its  act  may  be  nothing  else  than  the  willing  of 
some  outer  object.  The  will,  therefore,  may  still  be 
free  even  whilst  it  desires  outer  objects. 

Ver}'  different  is  the  Kantian  view  of  freedom  or  self- 
determination.  Kant  recognises  but  one  determining 
factor  in  human  action — that  thing,  namely,  for  the  sake 
of  which  we  do  our  act.  If  this  be  some  object  or  end 
outside  the  will,  the  will  is  determined,  not  by  itself,  ,  ^  ^ 

but  by  an  outer  object,  and,  therefore,  heteronomously  :^**t71v-ftC'-«^ 
if  it  be  some  law  or  command  within  the  will  itself, 
some  law  that  springs  from  out  the  will  or  the  Practical 
Reason  (in  Kant's  system  these  are  regarded  as  one 
and  the  same  faculty),  our  act  is  both  autonomous  and 
self-determined  or  free.  Hence,  to  do  an  action  for 
the  sake  of  inner  law  is  freedom.  To  do  it  for  any  outer 
end,  or  for  the  pleasure  of  any  end,  is  physical  necessity 
and  heteronomy. 


192  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Criticism — What,  now,  are  we  to  think  of  this 
Kantian  conception  of  freedom  ?  To  'our  mind  it  is 
simply  false  Psychology  to  affirm  that  the  determining 
factor  in  action  is  a-lways  that  thing  or  principle  for  the 
sake  of  which  we  do  our  act.  We  know  from  experience 
that  we  often  act  for  the  sake  of  ends  or  objects  which 
have  no  power  to  determine  us  ;  for,  to  determine  the 
will  is  to  overmaster  it,  and  no  finite  end  or  object  may 
overmaster  a  human  will,  unless,  indeed,  it  be  the  only 
end  or  object  that  comes  before  our  will.*  When,  there- 
fore, a  finite  object  draws  on  our  wills  to  action,  it  does 
so  because  we  ourselves  of  set  purpose  cut  off  all  rival 
objects  from  the  horizon  of  desire,  and  determine  that 
this  one  shall  remain,  in  which  case  it  is  the  will,  and 
not  the  object,  that  determines  the  course  that  is  pur- 
sued. That  thing,  therefore,  for  the  sake  of  which  we 
do  our  act  is  not  always  the  final  determining  cause  of 
action,  and,  hence,  the  will  may  still  be  self-determined 
and  free,  even  while  we  act  from  the  motive  of  ends 
outside  ourselves. 


(2)    THE   HEGELIAN   ACCOUNT   OF   FREEDOM 

The  Hegelian  account  of  freedom  is  at  once  a  develop- 
ment of,  and  a  reaction  against,  the  Kantian  theory  just 
explained.  Freedom,  according  to  Hegel,  is  self-deter- 
mination ;  and  by  self-determination  he  means  doing  an 
action  for  the  sake  of  some  principle  which  either  exists 
in  or  proceeds  from  the  will  or  Practical  Reason  itself. 
So  far  he  is  at  one  with  Kant.j    Now,  according  to 

•  In  all  deliberate  action,  at  least  the  negative  of  the  object  comes 
into  our  consciousness. 

t  This  view  of  freedom,  as  we  have  explained,  is  very  different  from 
the  Scholastic  view.  But  we  could  point  to  passages  in  Hegel  which 
recall  the  Scholastic  doctrine  in  the  most  unmistakable  manner.  Thus, 
he  writes  ("  Phil,  of  Right  "  (Dydc),  p.  22) — "  Man  is  the  completely 
undetermined  and  stands  above  impulse  "  (that  is,  the  desire  for  ex- 
ternal objects  or  pleasures),  "  and  may  fix  and  set  it  up  as  his.  Im- 
pulse is  in  nature,  but  it  depends  on  my  will  whether  I  establish  it  in 
the  e^o," 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY       193 

Hegel,  it  is  an  undeniable  fact — a  fact  to  which  Reason 
and  experience  testify  in  the  fullest  way — that  a  human 
being  must  wish  for  ends  or  pleasures  of  some  sort  and 
for  their  own  sake — ^that  he  cannot  always  act  for  duty's 
sake  alone  ;  and  he  insists,  as  a  consequence  of  this 
fact,  that  if  human  action  is  to  be  regarded  as  possessing 
freedom  on  any  large  scale,  it  must  be  possible  in  the 
same  act  to  act  for  duty's  sake,  and  for  the  sake  of 
objects  or  pleasure — in  other  words,  to  be  determined 
by  the  self,  and,  at  the  same  time,  to  be  determined  by 
the  object  or  pleasure  that  is  desired.*  Accordingly, 
we  find  him  maintaining  by  a  variety  of  arguments  that 
to  be  determined  by  the  self  and  to  be  determined  by 
objects  beyond  the  self  are  one  and  the  same  thing, 
since  the  self  and  its  objects  are  one.  He  argues,  for 
instance,  at  one  place,  from  the  standpoint  of  Monism, 
that  all  objects  are  developments  of  the  Absolute  Will — 
that  "  the  indeterminate  condition  of  the  will  as  neutral 
but  infinite  germ  of  all .  existence  contains  within  itself 
its  definite  character  and  ends,  and  brings  them  forth 
solely  out  of  itself  :  "  f  and,  in  another  place,  arguing 
from  the  point  of  view  of  ordinary  Idealism,  that  the 
willing  or  knowing  subject  is  one  with  its  object,  since 
object  is  "  object  "  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  known  or  willed. 
"  So  with  the  true  will,"  he  writes.J  "  that  which  it  wills 
— viz.,  its  content — is  identical  with  it."  And  again,§ 
"  Conception  is  the  penetration  of  the  object,  which  is 
then  no  longer  opposed  to  me." 

This  latter  point  of  view,  which  bases  freedom  on  the 
identity  of  subject  and  object  in  consciousness,  is,  it 
seems  to  us,  insisted  on  by  Hegel,  in  his  analysis  of 
freedom,  more  than  any  other ;    and  it  is  the  only  one 


*  In  Hegel's  system  negative  freedom  is  the  freedom  that  belongs 
to  acts  that  are  done  for  duty's  sake  only  ;  positive  freedom  is  the 
freedom  that  belongs  to  any  self-determined  action  in  which  sonie 
value  is  given  to  outer  objects  and  to  pleasure, 

t  "  Phil,  of  Right,"  page  23, 

J  Ibid.,  page  30. 

§  Ibid.,  page  18. 
Vol.  I — 13 


194  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

that  gets  prominence  in  the  works  of  the  Neo-Hegelian 
schooh  Thus,  Professor  Caird  writes  : — "  The  opposi- 
tion between  the  self  and  its  objects  is  not  real  at  all. 
Objects  are  such  only  by  being  objects  for  a  self.  .  .  . 
To  put  it  more  directly,  their  existence  is  not  merely 
an  existence  for  a  self,  but  an  existence  of  a  self — an 
existence  which  is  essentially  spiritual.  .  .  .  The  con- 
sciousness of  a  self,  therefore,  is  necessarily  a  conscious- 
ness of  freedom,  for,  just  in  so  far  as  the  self  is  pre- 
supposed or  presupposes  itself  as  a  subject  in  all  deter- 
mination of  the  object  and  of  itself  ...  it  cannot  be 
conscious  of  the  object  as  externally  determining  it ; 
and  though  the  object-self,  as  one  object  amongst 
others,  might  be  regarded  as  so  determined,  yet,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  identified  with  the  subject  itself,  the  external 
relation  of  determination  becomes  itself  a  vehicle  for 
self-determination."  We  shall  devote  most  of  our 
criticism  to  this  idealistic  argument. 

Criticism — Our  first  point  of  criticism  is  that,  in  our 
belief,  no  amount  of  metaphysical  jugglery  will  ever  be 
able  to  efface  the  common  judgment  and  experience  of 
men  that  the  thing  which  I  think  and  wish  is  often  dis- 
tinct from  me,  and  that  mere  thinking  or  willing  could 
not  possibly  make  such  an  object  one  with  me  ;  that, 
therefore,  subject  and  object  are  not  necessarily  one. 
Hence,  if  freedom  is  to  be  made  consistent  with  the 
desire  for  outer  objects  or  for  pleasure,  their  reconcilia- 
tion must  depend  upon  some  other  view  of  freedom, 
and  of  the  relation  of  subject  to  object,  than  that  advo- 
cated by  Hegel.  Secondly,  it  is  absurd  to  regard  the 
subject  and  object  as  one  on  the  mere  ground  that 
object  is  object  in  relation  to  a  subject,  for  then  it  would 
follow  that  the  right  must  be  the  left,  merely  because 
it  is  right  in  relation  to  the  left,  and  that  an  object 
which  is  heavier  or  lighter  than  four  pounds  is  four 
pounds,  simply  because  it  is  licavier  or  lighter  in  relation 
to  four  pounds— propositions,  indeed,  which  to  Hegel's 
mind  are  not  at  all  impossible,  but  which,  we  think, 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  195 

could  never  recommend  themselves  to  the  multitude  of 
men,  or,  indeed,  to  any  man  in  his  rational  moments. 
Thirdly,  we  should  remember  that  in  Hegel's  system 
freedom  and  morality  are  one  thing,  and,  therefore,  if 
willing  a  thing  makes  it  one  with  the  subject,  it  would 
follow  that,  since  any  object  may  be  willed,  there  is  no 
object  the  willing  of  which  may  not  be  free,  and,  conse- 
quently, the  willing  of  which  is  not  a  moral  act.  Thus, 
in  the  Hegelian  system  no  room  is  left  for  distinctions 
of  good  and  evil — a  position  which  is  properly  described 
as  Ethical  Nihilism,  or  the  negation  of  all  Ethics. 

We  may  at  this  point  sum  up  our  own  theory  in 
opposition  to  that  of  Kant  and  Hegel.  First,  freedom 
means  self-determination — i.e.,  it  is  a  property  of  a  will 
which  is  the  efficient  cause  of  its  own  act,  or  of  its  own 
movement  to  certain  objects.  Secondly,  the  will  may 
desire  ends  external  to  itself,  and  the  pleasure  of  them, 
but  that  fact  in  no  way  militates  against  the  freedom  of 
the  will,  for  the  final  cause  of  desire  may  lie  outside  the 
will,  even  though  the  will  itself  is  the  efficient  cause, 
and  determines  itself  to  embrace  those  objects,  in  other 
words  is  free. 

The  question  now  arises,  is  freedom  necessary  to 
morality — i.e.,  to  a  moral  system — and  is  it,  therefore, 
presupposed  in  Ethics  ?  This  question  is  of  prime 
importance  and  requires  to  be  treated  at  some  length.* 

•  In  "  Studies  in  Humanism,"  page  405,  Professor  Schiller  makes 
an  interesting  and  curious  attempt  to  reconcile  Determinism  (which  he 
regards  as  simply  a  methodological  assumption,  not  as  a  principle 
capable  of  being  proved)  w:th  free  will,  by  showing  that,  even  if  we 
assume  that  the  will  is  free,  the  determinist  may  yet  maintain  in  every 
case  that  our  act,  whatever  it  may  be,  is  the  necessary  result  of  the 
individual  forces  that  moved  us  at  the  time  of  acting.  This  claim,  he 
says,  the  believer  in  free  will  can  never  disprove,  because  after  the  act 
it  is  never  demonstrable  that  any  other  course  was  possible  than  that 
which  happened,  and,  before  the  act,  the  Determinist  need  not  venture 
to  predict.  Professor  Schiller's  contention  is  not,  we  think,  without 
its  touch  of  humour. 


CHAPTER  VII 

FREEDOM  AND   MORALITY 

[Continued) 

Concerning  the  relation  of  freedom  to  morals,  we  pro- 
pose to  discuss  two  questions — [a)  is  freedom  necessary 
to  morality,  and  is  it,  therefore,  presupposed  in  the 
Science  of  Ethics  ?  {b)  Granted  that  freedom  is  neces- 
sary to  morality,  are  these  two  conceptions  identical,  or 
is  freedom  only  a  pre-requisite  of  moral  goodness  ? 

{a)  Necessity  of  Freedom   for   Morality  and   for 
THE  Science  of  Ethics 

For  the  clear  treatment  of  this  complex  and  much- 
debated  question  it  will  be  well  to  set  out  our  views  in 
a  series  of  definite  propositions.  The  following  three 
wiU,  we  believe,  fully  represent  our  view  : — 

(i)  Freedom,  though  not  necessary  to  distinctions  of 
good  and  evil,  is  necessary  to  the  particular  aspect 
these  distinctions  bear  in  Ethics — namely,  as  distinc- 
tions of  moral  good  and  evil. 

(2)  Freedom  is  necessary  to  moral  obligation. 

(3)  Freedom  is  necessary  to  imputability,  and  is, 
therefore,  necessary  to  the  attendant  conceptions  of 
merit  and  retributive  punishment. 

(i)  Relaiion  of  freedom  to  "  good  "  and  "  evil." 

We  do  not  think  we  could  logically  maintain  the 
necessity  of  freedom  for  mere  good  and  evil.  For  there 
are  a  good  and  an  evil  for  animals  as  well  as  a  good 
and  evil  for  men,  and  animals  are  not  free.     Besides,  in 

196 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  iq; 

distinguishing  human  good  from  human  evil  we  do 
not  necessarily  take  into  account  the  freedom  of  our 
faculties,  but  simply  determine  that  certain  objects  are 
natural  to  our  faculties  and  certain  others  are  not.  So 
we  say  that  food  is  natural  and  good  for  man  just  as  it 
is  natural  and  good  for  a  horse,  and  in  neither  case  does 
our  judgment  take  account  of  freedom.  In  general  the 
good  is  the  natural  object  of  appetite,  and  in  assigning 
that  object  we  do  not  ask  whether  the  faculty  in  ques- 
tion is  free  or  determined.  When,  indeed,  we  have 
succeeded  in  assighing  the  natural  object  of  will — that 
is,  the  Infinite  Good — we  may  proceed  then,  as  St. 
Thomas  does,  to  show  that  the  will  is  free.  But  the 
"  good  "  of  the  faculty  is  the  first  thing  settled  upon, 
and  hence,  apart  from  the  character  that  it  bears  in 
morals,  the  determination  of  the  "  good  "  does  not  pre- 
suppose the  freedom  of  the  will.  We  know  that 
drunkenness  is  bad  because  in  drunkenness  the  natural 
order  of  the  faculties  is  set  at  nought  ;  that  suicide  is 
bad  becavise  the  natural  tendency  of  every  appetite  is 
to  maintain  itself  in  being ;  and  that,  therefore,  the 
opposites  of  these— sobriety  and  the  proper  maintenance 
of  the  bodily  life — are  good.  These  arguments  make 
no  mention  of  freedom. 


Freedom  and  Moral  Distinctions. 

Freedom,  as  we  have  seen,  is  not  necessary  to  the 
conception  of  good  and  evil  as  such,  nor  to  the  con- 
struction of  a  table  of  good  actions.  But  Ethics  is  more 
than  a  mere  tabulation  of  value-judgments  or  of  judg- 
ments about  good  and  evil.  It  is  the  science  of  moral 
good  and  evil — that  is,  of  acts  of  the  will  as  directed  by 
Reason  to  natural  ends.  It  is,  therefore,  the  science  of 
self-directed  action.  But  self-directed  action  is  free 
action.  Again,  having  proved  that  the  will  is  free,  it 
becomes  certain  that  much  human  conduct  is  free.  But 
human  conduct  is  evidently  subject  to  laws,  even  that 


igS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

portion  of  it  which  comes  under  human  control  and  is 
free.  Consequently,  some  science  must  consider  it,  and 
the  science  to  which  we  hand  over  this  department  of 
human  action  is  Ethics.  Those  elements  in  human 
action  that  are  not  free,  or  which  do  not  come  under  the 
control  of  Reason,  are  subject  to  other  laws  than  those 
of  Ethics,  and  they  are  part  of  another  science — namely, 
of  Physics  or  of  Psychology.  So  freedom  is  a  necessary 
presupposition  of  Ethics  or  of  Moral  Science.  To  put 
the  matter  technically — Ethics  in  its  material  aspect  as 
a  simple  tabulation  of  good  acts  does  not,  as  such,  pre- 
suppose freedom.  In  its  formal  aspect,  as  a  science  of 
acts  of  the  will  controlled  by  Reason  and  directed  by 
Reason  to  their  last  end,  it  does  presuppose  freedom,  and 
it  is  in  its  formal  aspect  that  it  has  a  title  to  be  con- 
sidered a  separate  science  from  Psychology.* 

(2)  Freedom  and  obligation,  i^ 

Freedom  is  necessary  to  obligation.  But  it  is  not 
easy  to  prove  its  necessity  scientifically,  since  men  are 
not  agreed  about  their  definition  of  obligation.  We 
believe,  however,  that  even  the  most  widely  divergent 
schools  will  agree  in  allowing  that  obligation,  if  it  exists 
at  all,  is  a  categorical  necessity  of  some  kind.  Starting 
with  this  conception  of  obligation  it  is  open  to  us  to 
bring  out  the  two  following  points — (a)  that  if  freedom 
be  not  presupposed,  then  "  obligation  "  ceases  to  have 
any  distinctive  meaning  such  as  mankind  has  always 

*  Freedom  is  equally  necessary  for  moral  good  and  for  moral  evil. 
In  "  Studies  in  Humanism,"  page  400,  Prof.  Schiller  makes  the 
peculiar  claim  that  freedom,  though  necessary  for  moral  evil,  is  not 
necessarily  presupposed  in  moral  good.  The  Moralist,  he  says,  "  wants 
to  be  able  to  say  to  the  bad  man,  you  need  not  have  bocoino  the  Icpor 
you  arc  .  .  .  but  he  does  not  need  or  desire  to  say  analogously  lo  the 
good  man — in  .spite  of  the  deeply-ingrained  goochiess  of  your  habits 
you  are  still  free  to  do  evil."  This  view  is  built  upon  the  false  assump- 
tion that  Ethics  is  only  an  art,  that  its  solo  purpose  is  to  make  men 
bctttir,  and  that  what  does  not  improve  mankind  has  no  right  to  a 
plare  in  Ethics.  We  saw,  on  the  contrary,  that  Ivthics  is  a  .science, 
and  that  its  object  is  to  tell  us  what  is  good  and  what  is  evil,  and  as 
wc  saw  freedom  is  necessary  for  moral  good  as  well  as  for  moral  evil. 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  199 

attached  to  it  ;  (b)  (a  consequence  of  this  last  point) 
that  they  who  deny  freedom  tend  also  to  deny  the  reality 
of  obligation,  and  to  regard  it  as  a  mere  subjective 
feeling  with  no  corresponding  objective  value — with  no 
real  validity. 

(a)  There  are  three  kinds  of  necessity  in  nature : 
Physical  necessity,  or  the  necessity  of  cause  and  effect 
— e.g.,  the  necessity  that  a  stone  flung  from  the  hand 
should  go  forward  ;  metaphysical  neces'  tke  neces- 
sity of  essence  and  property — e.g.,  that  ,.  igftslionld 

contain  two  right  angk  s  ;    and  ideological  nei .  or 

the   necessity   of   1  icarv  to    an   end. 

This  last  is  of  two  1...  ...^^ :.   and  caiigorical — 

i.e.,  the  necessity  of  taking  tiie  means  to  :in  end  if  we 
desire  the  end,  and  the  lu  i  ■  the  means  to 

an  end  which  wc  do  nd  n...-  - Moral  obliga- 
tion, as  will  be  shown  in  the  following  chapter  (and  this 
is  the  common  tliougli  ill-d' lined  conception  of  obliga- 
tion), is  a  telcological  necessity  and  categorical.  This, 
even  our  opponents  on  the  question  of  freedom  them- 
selves assniiic.  For  tKcy  attempt  to  account  for  the 
feeling  of  obligation  by  showing  how  a  feeling  of  cate- 
gorical necessity  could  arise  out  of  the  mere  remem- 
brance of  hvpothit'  al  necessities,  thereby  conceding 
that  the  ess'Htiil  clement  in  our  ordinary  conception  of 
dnt\  is  tl  I  categorical  and  not  a  hypothetical 
necessity 

Let  11  t]  n,  toke  this  ordinary  conception  of  duty 
as  a  c;  il  necessity  and  examine  it  in  conjunction 

with  two  oUier  propositions,  neither  of  which  will  be 
readily  deniecl — first,  that  if  a  man  be  under  moral 
obligation  at.  all,  he  is  under  an  obligation  to  do  the 
gooil  (bonum  est  faciendum),  that  no  man  could  be 
obliL;ed  to  do  evil  ;  and  secondl}',  that  man  is  some- 
tina  s  guilty  of  evil. .  Arguing  from  these  three  ad- 
mi>  ions  vM  shall  arrive  at  the  desired  conclusion.     A 

'  "  Must  i>hvsically — i.e.,  it  is  something  which  we  cannot  help 
de  iiiug.     N.I'..     By  "  physical  "  we  do  not  mean  "  material." 


200  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

man  is  always  bound  to  do  the  good  :  he  is  bound  to 
do  it  even  when  he  does  what  is  evil.  Now,  on  the 
determinist  hypothesis  when  a  man  does  evil  he  could 
not  have  done  the  good.  And,  therefore,  on  the  de- 
terminist hypothesis  a  man  would  be  bound  to  do  what 
he  is  unable  to  do.  But  this  is  impossible — man 
cannot  be  bound  to  do  the  thing  which  he  is  not  able 
to  do. 

It  is  clear,  then,  that  on  the  determinist  hypothesis 
if  duty  exists  at  all  it  must  be  something  very  different 
from  what  men  have  always  understood  by  "  duty." 
The  following-  niight  on  the  Deterministic  hypothesis  be 
a  possible  meaning  for  duty :— just  as  a  tree  must  have 
moisture  if  it  is  to  reach  its  acquired  perfection,  so  a 
man  ought  to  do  the  good  (even  in  the  case  in  which  he 
cannot  do  it)  if  he  is  to  act  up  to  the  ideal  of  humanity. 
But  this,  we  contend  in  reply,  is  not  moral  obligation 
as  men  have  always  understood  it.  Moral  obligation  in 
the  common  mind,  as  well  as  in  the  scientific,  is  an 
obligation  to  do  a  thing  simply  and  unconditionally. 
The  moral  "  ought  "  is  nothing  if  it  is  not  categorical, 
whereas  here  we  find  the  "  ought  "  reduced  to  a  mere 
hypothetical  necessity,  or  rather  to  something  much 
lower — to  a  sheer  impossibility.  Freedom,  therefore, 
is  necessary  to  the  conception  of  duty,  for* we  have  now 
proved  the  proposition — "  deny  the  freedom'  of  the  will 
and  the  '  ought '  ceases  to  have  any  distinctive  mean- 
ing." If  duty  is  not  categorical  it  is  nothing.  And  if 
the  will  is  not  free,  duty  cannot  be  categorical. 

(6)  Again,  Deterministic  Ethics  opposes,  and  has 
always  opposed,  the  conception  of  obligation  as  a  con- 
ception with  an  objective  value — that  is,  as  a  concep- 
tion with  a  natural  title  to  a  place  in  our  thoughts  as 
representative  of  objective  things  or  relations.  For 
the  determinist,  the  notion  of  obligation  is  a  purely 
subjective  growth,  a  kind  of  epiphcnomcnon  or  bye- 
product  from,  other  thoughts  and  feelings — nmrjiely,  the 
feelings  that  certain  actions  are  to  be  avoided  if  we 


^ 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  201 

would  escape  punishment.  These  feelings,  the  de- 
terminist  assures  us,  have  an  objective  value,  for  if 
we  do  not  avoid  the  forbidden  acts  we  shall  in  truth 
be  punished.  But,  then,  in  course  of  time,  this 
hypothesis  "  if  you  would  escape  punishment  "  is 
either  forgotten  or  drops  out  of  our  consciousness  in 
some  way,  and  we  are  left  with  a  feeling  quite  different 
from  the  first — namely,  the  feeling  that  some  acts  are 
to  be  avoided — without  any  "  if."  This  is  the  feeling 
of  duty,  according  to  determinists.  It  is  purely  sub- 
jective. It  is  a  part  or  remnant  of  that  which  was 
once  genuinely  real  and  true — ^namely,  the  feeling  of 
hypothetical  necessity  from  which  it  is  derived,  but  it 
itself  represents  nothing,  just  as  a  mutilated  photograph 
represents  nothing  in  the  objective  world.  Later  in  our 
chapter  on  Duty,  we  shall  have  an  opportunity  of  study- 
ing this  theory.  At  present  we  wish  merely  to  bring 
out  the  point  that  freedom  is  necessary  to  obligation 
since  Determinism  tends  uniformly  to  its  rejection. 

We  claim,  therefore,  that  without  freedom  there  can 
be  no  such  thing  as  moral  obligation,  and  for  two 
reasons  :  first,  because  on  the  deterministic  hypothesis, 
obligation  would  sometimes  be  an  obligation  to  do 
evil ;  secondly,  because  in  Determinism  there  seems  to 
be  no  room  for  the  idea  of  obligation. 

(3)  Freedom  and  Impidahility. 

Freedom  is  also  necessary  to  Imputability.  Imputa- 
bility  implies,  as  we  saw,  ownership  of  act,  and  owner- 
ship means  that  the  agent  produces  the  act  or  is  its 
cause.  Now,  if  I  am  not  free,  then  the  act  that  is  done 
is  not,  properly  speaking,  my  act,  for  I  am  not  its  cause. 
The  fire  that  burns  is  the  cause  of  the  ruin  that  it  pro- 
duces ;  but  the  fire  is  not  the  cause  of  its  own  action, 
for  it  does  not  determine  itself  to  the  act.  So  the  man 
who  is  not  free,  but  is  determined  by  nature  or  character 
to  an  action,  may  be  the  cause  of  the  outer  effect  of  his 


202  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

action,  but  he  cannot  be  the  cause  of  his  own  action,  and 
his  act  is  not  imputable  to  him. 

And  as  merit  and  retributive  punishment  presuppose 
imputability  they  also  demand  freedom.     Merit  includes  - 
besides  imputability  the  conception  of  a  good  done  to     ' 
another   person,    and   retributive   punishment   the   con-       ^ 
ception  of  an  injury.     But  both  suppose  imputability        rj; 
or  the  mastery  of  the  agent  over  his  act — and  since 
freedom   is  necessary   to  imputability  it   is   necessarily 
supposed  in  merit  also.     We  must  here  say  a  special 
word  01  the  question  of 

Freedom  and  Retributive  Punishment. 

The  question  of  the  nature  of  punishment  will  occupy 
us  in  a  future  chapter — that  on  Sanction — but  we  men- 
tion it  now  because  of  its  connection  with  the  question 
of  the  relation  of  free  will  to  Ethics.  For  purposes  of 
present  discussion  it  will  be  enough  to  point  out  that 
there  are  two  theories  on  the  nature  and  meaning  of 
punishment — {a)  the  theory  that  ^all  punishment  is 
emendatory  and  exemplary — that  is,  is  meant  merely 
for  the  improvement  of  the  person  punished  and  also 
as  an  example  to  deter  others  from  crime  ;  (b)  that 
all  punishment  is  primarily  and  essentially  retributive 
— ^that  is,  is  inflicted  on  account  of  the  act  that  has 
been  done,  which  act  must  be  atoned  for  in  order  to 
satisfy  the  requirements  of  the  moral  order. 

In  the  present  work  the  view  taken  is  that  punish- 
ment is  essentially  and  primarily  retributive,  and  the 
question  therefore  arises — How  is  freedom  related  to 
retributive  punishment  ?  We  answer^free  will  is  neces- 
sary to  retributive  punishment,  and  it  is  necessary  for 
the  following  reason  : — Punishment  as  retributive  is  in- 
flicted on  some  one  as  cause  of  the  crime  committed. 
But  he  who  is  not  free  is  not  cause  of  his  own  act.  To 
be  cause  of  one's  own  act  and  to  be  free  are  one  and  the 
same  thing,  and  they  are  part  of  the  very  meaning  of 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  203 

iniputability.  Therefore,  freedom  is  necessary  to  retri- 
butive punishment. 

A  brief  reference  at  this  point  to  two  other  well- 
known  views  of  the  relation  of  freedom  to  punishment 
will  not  be  out  of  place. 

(i)  Leslie  Stephen  s  view.  Punishment  inflicted  upon 
something  which  is  not  the  cause  of  evil  action  is  unjust 
punishment.  Therefore,  that  an  act  be  punishable  it 
should  spring,  not  from  something  which  passes  in  a 
moment,  from  something  that  passes  with  the  action 
itself — for  instance,  a  momentary  desire,  or  the  will's 
passing  choice— but  from  something  which  is  permanent 
in  a  man  and  remains  after  the  action  has  been  per- 
formed. But,  he  adds,  the  free  choice  passes,  and 
conseqeuntly,  if  action  be  the  result  of  free  choice,  it 
would  be  illogical  and  unethical  to  punish  on  account 
of  it.  Punishment,  therefore,  can  only  be  inflicted  if 
the  act  springs  out  of  the  permanent  character,  and 
an  act  that  springs  out  of  the  permanent  character  is 
a  determined,  not  a  free,  act.  And  Hume  writes : 
"  Actions  are  from  their  very  nature  temporary  and 
perishing,  and  where  the}'  proceed  not  from  some  cause 
in  the  character  and  disposition  of  the  person  who  per- 
formed them,  they  can  neither  redound  to  his  honour 
if  good  nor  infamy  if  evil."     (Enquiry.) 

Our  reply  is  as  follows  : — We  quite  admit  that  if 
retributive  punishment  is  to  be  rational,  that  inner 
element  from  which  the  evil  act  proceeds  must  not  be 
something  which  passes  away  with  the  act,  but  some- 
thing that  persists  up  to  the  time  of  punishment,  some- 
thing that  is  at  once  the  cause  of  the  act  and  permanent. 
But  we  submit  that  that  permanent  something  is  not 
character,  but  rather  the  free  will.  For  the  free  will 
realises  the  two  conditions  of  punishment — it  is  at  once 
the  cause  of  the  act  and  permanent.  But  the  cha- 
racter, though  it  may  be  the  cause  of  action,  is  not 
necessarily  permanent.  What  is  more  changeable  than 
human  character  ?     It  changes  under  the  influence  of 


204  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

punishment  itself.  It  changes  sometimes  even  with  the 
doing  of  the  deed  which  sprang  from  it.  Character  is 
but  the  resultant  of  many  deep-set,  yet  not  necessarily 
permanent,  tendencies  ;  and  that  resultant  keeps  ever 
changing  as  its  components  change,  and  sometimes  it  is 
neutralised  and  blotted  out  altogether.  But  the  free 
will  is  a  permanent  possession.  It  is  permanent  because 
every  natural  faculty  is  permanent  ;  and  it  remains 
with  us  to  the  end  just  like  the  faculty  of  feeling  and 
knowing,  or  just  like  the  soul  itself.  The  free  will, 
therefore,  and  not  the  character,  is  the  right  and  proper 
recipient  for  punishment,  and  consequently  determinism 
is  not  the  onl}-  theory  consistent  with  retributive  pun- 
ishment. 

Again,  as  we  shall  see  later,  retributive  punishment 
is  essentially  the  restoration  of  an  order  violated.  Now, 
no  necessary  agent  could  violate  the  order  of  nature, 
because  it  is  itself  a  natural  force,  and,  therefore,  its 
acts  are  themselves  part  of  the  natural  order.  Hence, 
retributive  punishment,  if  it  be  inflicted  at  all,  must  be 
inflicted  on  something  other  than  a  force  of  nature — 
that  is,  it  must  be  inflicted  upon  a  free  wih. 

(2)  Butler's  theory,  briefly  expressed,  is  that  punish- 
ment is  the  other  half  of  crime  ;  *  that  punishment 
follows  as  naturally  upon  an  evil  act  as  being  hurt 
follows  a  fall,t  that  as  the  hurt  follows  whether  the  fall 
was  free  or  not,  so  must  punishment  follow  whether 
the  breaking  of  the  law  was  free  or  not. 

Criticism — In  one  sense  of  the  word,  punishment 
includes  all  those  evil  effects  that  follow  on  the  viola- 
tion of  any  law.  In  this  sense  we  might  say  that  a 
plant  is  punished  which  is  neglected  and  dies  in  conse- 

*  This  theory  is  also  taught  by  Kant. 

t  Ixjckc  gives  an  express  denial  to  the  theory  that  punishment 
follows  as  a  natural  consequence  of  the  act.  Speaking  of  the  necissity 
of  punishment  for  law  he  writes  :  "  It  would  be  vain  for  one  intelligent 
btnng  to  set  a  rule  to  the  actions  of  another  if  he  had  it  not  in  his 
power  to  reward  the  compliance  with,  and  punish  deviation  from,  his 
rule  by  some  f^ood  and  rvil  that  is  not  the  natural  f^rodttct  and  consequence 
of  the  action  itself"  (ICss.iv,  IVtok  11.,  rii.iptcr  28). 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  205 

qiicnce  of  its  neglect.  But  such  punishment  is  natural 
or  physical  in  the  sense  of  non-moral.  Moral  punish- 
ment is  punishment  inflicted  for  the  violation  of  moral 
law,  and  it  is  with  moral  punishment  we  are  concerned 
in  the  science  of  Ethics.  As,  therefore,  a  moral  law  is 
violated  ethically  only  by  him  who  violates  it  freely 
and  knowingly,  so  moral  punishment  implies  the  free 
violation  of  a  moral  law. 

Again,  Butler  would  not  contend  that  an  act  is 
punishable  which  is  done  under  the  impression  that  it 
is  good  and  moral.  But  to  fall  from  a  height  will 
injure  us  whether  it  is  done  knowingly  or  not.  There- 
fore, there  can  be  no  parity  between  such  natural 
physical  evils  as  the  hurt  that  comes  from  falling  and 
the  moral  evil  which  is  at  the  root  of  retributive 
punishment.* 

*  Perhaps  an  unsympathetic  critic  of  Butler  would  even  go  farther, 
and  say  that  in  the  cases  adduced  by  Butler,  punishment — accepting 
the  word  punishment  in  his  sense — instead  of  being  the  natural  result 
of  the  violation  of  law,  is  really  inflicted  for  its  observance.  A  stone 
cannot  disobey  a  law.  The  very  definition  of  a  determined  Being  is 
that  it  is  a  creature  of  law.  Its  motion  is  the  resultant  of  all  the  laws 
that  affect  it  put  together.  Now,  if  a  rock  rolls  down  into  the  valley, 
and  crushes  the  life  out  of  the  plants  that  stand  in  its  course,  they  are 
there  to  meet  their  doom  in  obedience  to  law,  and  they  are  punished 
(in  Butler's  sense)  for  being  there  ;  and  the  rock  itself  is  shivered  to 
pieces  in  the  depths  below  because  it  has  unresistingly  yielded  itself 
up  to  law.  If  these  things  then  be  punishment,  punishment  is  in- 
flicted not  for  violation,  but  for  observance. 

Butler  advances  another  argument  in  favour  of  the  deterministic 
theory  of  retributive  punishment  which  requires  some  notice.  Briefly 
put  it  is  this  :  "  If  necessity  destroys  the  injustice  of  murder,  it  will 
also  destroy  the  injustice  of  sanction  or  punishment  "  ("  Analogy," 
Chapter  VI.).  This  means  that  if  we  hold  that  a  murderer  who  must 
murder  is  not  morally  a  sinner,  and  consequently  is  not  guilty  of  the 
injitsticc  of  murder,  wc  must,  on  the  very  same  ground,  admit  that 
the  punishment  meted  out  to  him  is  just — that  is,  that  the  proper 
ground  of  punishment  is  not  liberty,  but  necessity.  Now,  what 
Butler  ought  to  have  said  is  this  :  "If  necessity  destroy  the  tn  justice 
of  murder,  it  will  also  destroy  the  justice  of  sanction."  It  should  be 
remembered  that  the  injustice  of  murder  is  followed  not  by  the  in- 
justice, but  by  the  justice,  of  punishment,  and  that  a  just  murder  is 
followed  by  unjust  punishment.  Because  murder  is  unjust,  therefore, 
the  punishment  that  follows  it  is  just.  And  hence,  if  necessity  destroy 
the  injustice  of  murder  it  destroys,  as  a  matter  of  course,  the  justice 
of  punishment.  And  that  is  exactly  what  we  are  contending  for — that 
since  Determinism   removes  guilt  it  removes  also  the  occasion  for 


2o6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

On  the  Bearing  of  this  Question  of  Freedom  on 
Human  Action 

We  must  here  say  a  word  on  the  practical  bearing  of 
the  question  of  freedom  on  human  action  or  on  the 
practical  defence  of  deterministic  Ethics — a  defence  of 
which  some  determinists  make  prominent  mention. 
Briefly,  this  practical  defence  of  Deterministic  Ethics 
may  be  reduced  to  two  points — (i)  "  Determinism  will 
not  reasonably  modify  a  man's  view  of  what  is  right  for 
him  to  do  " — i.e.,  it  does  not  hinder  our  distinguishing 
truly  between  good  and  evil  action.  (2)  Determinism 
will  not  weaken  a  man's  motives  for  doing  good. 

(1)  It  is  quite  true  that  Determinism  will  not  modify 
our  view  of  what  is  good  and  evil.  For,  certain  things 
are  good  and  certain  others  are  evil  for  determined 
beings  as  well  as  for  free  beings.  Thus,  food  is  good 
for  plants,  for  animals,  and  for  men.  But,  on  the  other 
hand,  Determinism  will  modify  our  view  of  what  is 
morally  good  and  evil,  or  morally  right  and  wrong,  since, 
on  the  deterministic  hypothesis,  there  can  be  no  such 
things  as  7noral  good  and  evil.  But  Ethics  is  not  con- 
cerned with  the  good  merely,  but  with  the  moral  good, 
with  good  action  as  controlled  by  Reason  and  directed 
by  Reason  to  the  last  end.  Hence  determinism  is  not 
consistent  with  Ethical  distinctions.* 

punishment — i.e.,  as  it  destroys  the  injustice  of  murder  and  of  every 
other  act,  it  destroys  also  the  justice  of  punishment. 

There  is,  however,  another  way  of  looking  at  Butler's  argument. 
He  may  mean  that  just  as  necessity  makes  a  subject's  crime  not  un- 
just, since  a  man  who  is  determined  cannot  help  his  crime,  it  will  make 
punishment  also  not  unjust  (in  the  Ruler  or  him  who  punishes),  since 
the  Ruler  who  punishes  a  criminal  cannot — on  the  deterministic 
hypothesis— -help  punishing,  and  therefore  cannot  be  unjust.  On  that 
reading,  however,  though  the  ruler  would  be  subjectively  excused  from 
guilt,  still  punishment  as  an  institution  could  have  no  meaning,  and 
would  be  intrinsically  unjust. 

♦  Prof.  Rashdall  ("  Good  and  Evil,"  Vol.  II.  p.  329)  argues  that 
"  the  (lilfcrencc  between  a  crime  and  a  disease  is  the  same  for  the 
determinist  us  for  the  indetcrminist.  The  difference  lies  just  in  the 
fact  that  a  better  will  would  have  jirevented  tiie  one,  but  not  the 
other."  We  think,  however,  that  this  is  not  the  difterence.  To  the  in- 
dcterminiKt  the  difference  is  tliat  not  merely  a  better  will  but  any  will 
may  prevent  a  crime  whereas  disease  arises  independently  of  our  wills. 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  207 

(2)  The  second  point  of  defence  we  also  traverse. 
Determinism,  in  the  first  place,  cuts  the  ground  from 
under  moral  obligation,  and  the  fact  that  we  ought  to 
do  the  good  is  no  small  motive  for  doing  it.  Secondly, 
if  our  actions  are  determined,  we  cannot  see  what 
rational  motive  a  man  can  have  for  trying  to  do  the 
good,  since  what  a  man  does  at  any  moment  is,  on 
this  theory,  simply  givett  in  the  conditions  of  the  moment 
before,  and  there  is  no  use  in  his  trying  to  do  otherwise 
than  what  is  "  given "  in  these  conditions.  Deny  it 
as  best  we  may,  the  logical  result  of  Determinism,  so 
far  as  human  endeavour  is  concerned,  is  fatalism.*  The 
man  who  wanted  to  lie  lazily  in  bed  in  the  morning, 
and  consoled  himself  that  his  angel  guardian  and  Satan 
were  fighting  it  out,  and  that  he  must  await  the  issue, 
was  a  logical  determinist,  except  that,  for  the  Deter- 
minist,  the  angel  guardian  and  Satan  are  not  without 
but  are  within  a  man  and  part  of  his  constitution — 
that  is,  they  represent  the  opposing  antecedent  con- 
ditions within  his  mind.  These  antecedent  conditions, 
indeed,  may  be  affected  by  a  man's  own  conduct.  But 
since,  according  to  determinists,  a  man's  own  conduct 
is  itself  antecedently  determined,  it  follows  that  "  what 
will  be  "  is  altogether  in  nature's  hands  at  each  moment 
and  not  in  ours,  and  that  it  was  in  nature's  hands  from 
the  beginning.  Actions,  then,  on  the  determinist 
hypothesis  are  like  a  person's  stature — we  cannot,  "  by 
taking  thought,  add  to  our  stature  one  cubit."  Of 
course,  it  may  be  said  by  determinists  that  if  we  do  not 
strive  we  shall  not  obtain  certain  ends,  and  that,  there- 
fore, the  determinist  theory  affords  us  a  just  and  logical 
ground  for  striving.     They  forget  that  on  this  theory 

*  The  distinction  sometimes  drawn  between  fatalism  and  deter- 
minism— that  the  former  represents  man's  actions  as  determined  from 
without,  the  latter  as  determined  largely  from  nature  and  character 
and  efforts  within — makes  no  practical  difference  in  the  present  case. 
A  man  may  Imow  that  his  acts  are  determined  by  the  "  self  within," 
but  if  he  believes  that  the  "  self  within  "  is  itself  antecedently  deter- 
mined, then  he  may  logically  say  :  "  Whatever  will  be  to-morrow  was 
determined  yesterday,  I  cannot  alter  that  necessity." 


2o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of  Determinism  even  the  fact  of  our  striving  or  not 
striving  is  "given"  at  each  moment  in  the  conditions 
of  a  moment  before.  Why,  then,  should  we  bother 
further  about  it  ?  If  these  conditions  are  such  as  to 
make  a  man  strive,  infalhbly  he  will  strive.  If  they 
are  not,  he  will  not  strive.  We  cannot,  on  the  deter- 
ministic hypothesis,  break  the  causal  sequence.  If 
this  be  not  rank  fatalism,  then  fatalism  has  no  mean- 
ing. 

It  should  be  remembered,  however,  that  our  main 
quarrel  with  determinism  is  not  its  practical  effect  on 
human  life,  but  the  fact  that  it  makes  the  moral  good 
impossible,  and  that  it  removes  all  ground  of  responsi- 
bility. We  can,  therefore,  see  no  logic  in  such  language 
as  the  following,  which  we  quote  from  Mr.  Calder- 
wood,  who,  we  may  remark,  is  himself  a  professed 
libertarian  : — *  "  If  determinists  can  find  their  require- 
ments met  in  a  lofty  metaphysical  determinism,  in  which 
conscience  is  sovereign,  the  will  absolutely  good,  and 
activity  is  wholly  rational,  and  can  allow  that  the  con- 
dition of  social  life  is  such  as  to  require  and  render 
possible  individual  struggle  towards  moral  self-culture, 
I  do  not  know  what  controversy  libertarians  can  have 
with  this  view  of  Ethical  life."  This  is,  indeed,  to 
expect  a  great  deal  from  detenninism,  yet,  granted 
these  conditions,  we  cannot  agree  with  Calderwood's 
contention.  For,  on  the  deterministic  theory,  it  is,  as 
we  have  shown,  absurd  to  speak  of  individual  struggle  to 
the  social  good.  The  struggle  towards  the  social  good 
can  result  only  from  a  man's  sense  of  the  obligation  to 
struggle  towards  it.  But  on  the  deterministic  hypo- 
thesis obligation  is,  as  we  saw,  impossible.  Therefore, 
between  determinism,  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  main 
ethical  conceptions  on  the  other,  there  is  a  cleavage 
which  nothing  can  overcome.  These  mnin  ethical  con- 
ceptions are  moral  good,  obligation,  imputabilit}',  merit, 
and  punishment. 

•  Page  20J,  "  lithics." 


FREEDOM  AND  MORALITY  209 


(b)  Whether    Freedom    and    Moral    Goodness    are 
Identical  ? 

We  now  come  to  the  second  portion  of  this  enquiry. 
We  have  already  enquired — (a)  Is  Freedom  necessary  to 
moral  science  ?  We  now  ask — (b)  What  is  the  relation 
of  freedom  to  moral  goodness  ?  Are  they,  as  Kant 
asserts,  one  thing  ?  Is  the  free  will  the  morally  good 
will,  and,  vice  versa,  is  the  morally  good  will  the  free 
will  ?  *  Our  answer  is  that  they  are  not  identical ; 
that  freedom  is  only  one  of  the  pre-conditions  of  moral 
goodness,  but  that  it  is  not  moral  goodness  itself ;  that, 
on  the  contrary,  a  bad  will  is  free  just  as  a  good  will  is 
free,  and  that,  therefore,  freedom  and  goodness  are  far 
from  being  convertible  terms. 

(i)  We  admit,  of  course,  that  only  the  good  man  is 
fully  free.  For,  vice  is  slavery — the  slavery  of  a  man 
to  his  passions — the  mastery  of  the  flesh,  and  we  have 
already  shown  that  passion  diminishes  freedom,  and  in 
certain  cases  may  even  destroy  it  altogether.  The 
drunkard,  though  sufficiently  free  to  be  responsible  for 
getting  drunk,  is  not  a  perfectly  free  man.  He  is  to  a 
large  extent  the  slave  of  his  passion.  St.  Paul  speaks 
of  the  "  servus  peccati  " — and  there  is  no  doubt  what- 
soever that  sin  and  the  tendency  to  it  are  a  bondage. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  good  man — the  man  who  cheer- 
fully obeys  the  law — is  to  a  large  extent  saved  from  the 


*  This  question  is  important,  since  many  modem  Ethicians — for 
instance,  Fichte  and  Hegel — take  the  identification  of  the  two  con- 
ceptions, freedom  and  moral  goodness,  as  the  starting  points  of  their 
Ethical  systems,  for  whicli  assumption  they  are  indebted  to  Kant. 
The  reasons  for  this  assumption  will  be  more  conveniently  studied 
when  treating  of  the  Kantian  theory  of  the  Autonomy  of  Human 
Reason,  to  which  therefore  we  refer  our  readers.  Perhaps,  however, 
it  will  not  be  out  of  place  to  refer  here  to  one  possible  reason  for  the 
Kantian  assumption  which  some  authorities  quote  as  the  main  reason 
— namely,  that,  according  to  Kant,  the  only  freedom  with  which  we 
are  acquainted  is  freedom  to  do  that  which  we  are  obliged  to  do — "  I 
ought,  therefore,  I  can."  And  as  we  arc  only  obliged  to  the  good, 
freedom  and  the  good  are  one  and  coextensive  in  his  theory. 
Vol.  I — 14 


210  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

thraldom  of  the  passions,  and  is  so  far  a  freer  man  than 
others. 

"  Ah  !   Christ,  if  there  were  no  hereafter, 
It  still  were  best  to  follow  Thee  ; 
Tears  are  a  nobler  gift  than  laughter, 
Who  wears  Thy  yoke  alone  is  free." 

(2)  But  this  holds  merely  for  freedom  in  the  sense  of 
its  fullest  possession,  as  implying  not  only  the  -power 
of  self-determination,  but  also  the  absence  of  strong 
passions  and  a  consequent  increased  power  of  self- 
determination  to  the  "  good."  But  freedom  is  the 
power  of  self-determination  itself,  and  in  that  sense 
freedom  is  not  the  same  as  the  morally  good  will.  For, 
first,  the  content  of  the  two  ideas  is  not  the  siime.  Free- 
dom means  simply  self-determination  or  the  power  to 
£2ilSfi— QXlgls_own_act.  Moral  goodness  means  that  a 
man's  act  is  in  accordance  with  the  ultimate  end. 
Secondly,  freedom  is  necessary  not  only  to  the  morally 
good  but  also  to  the  morally  bad  will.  A  morally  bad 
man  is  not  one  that  wishes  an  evil  end,  but  one  that 
causes  his  own  desire  for  that  end.  The  tree  that  fails 
to  bloom  is  not  morall}^  bad,  since  in  the  circumstances 
it  could  do  nothing  else  than  fail  to  bloom — its  failure 
is  not  due  to  itself.  The  horse  that  bites  is  not  bad 
morally.  It  does  not  cause  its  own  vicious  desire  to 
injure  another.  But  a  morally  bad  man  is  one  who 
not  only  does  evil,  but  does  it  of  himself — who  deter- 
mines his  own  evil  desire.  Freedom,  then,  is  a  necessary 
presupposition  of  moral  badness  as  well  as  of  goodness, 
and  hence  it  cannot  be  one  with  goodness. 


CHAPTER  VIII 

ON  DUTY 

{a)  The  Problem  of  Duty  Explained 

In  a  former  chapter  we  eatablished  an  essential  distinc- 
tion between  good  and  evil  acts.  A  man  who  does 
good  acts  will  be  accounted  a  good  man,  and  a  man 
who  does  evil  acts  is  a  bad  man. 

A  further  question  remains  to  be  answered.  Is  a 
man  bound  in  any  way  to  be  a  good  man  and  to  choose 
a  good  or  virtuous  line  of  conduct  rather  than  the  oppo- 
site ?  Is  there  any  necessity  laid  on  a  man  to  be  good 
rather  than  bad  ?  To  men  who  are  not  accustomed  to 
strict  scientific  enquiry  such  a  question  will  seem  almost 
superfluous.  They  will  say — "  Of  course,  an  evil  action 
ought  to  be  avoided,  and  only  good  actions  done.  What 
else  is  a  good  action  but  one  that  ought  to  be  done  ?  " 
But  Ethicians  know  that  this  is  a  question  that  they 
must  answer,  and  that  the  answer  to  it  is  neither  obvious 
nor  easy.  For  it  is  clear  that  besides  showing  that 
there  is  a  natural  distinction  between  good  and  evil, 
we  must  also  show  that  men  are  bound  to  observe  the 
distinction  in  their  actions  and  to  do  only  such  acts  as 
are  good.  Thus,  if  I  tell  a  lie  I  am  a  liar  and  a  bad 
man  ;  but  I  can  still  ask — Why  may  I  not  be  a  bad 
man  if  I  choose  ?  *  Can  I  show  that  men  are  under  any  \ 
necessity  to  do  good  and  avoid  evil  ?  Such  necessity  I 
is  what'  we  understand  by  duty  or  obligation.  And  ' 
on  our  power  of  proving  that  such  necessity  exists  will 
depend  our  power  of  proving  the  reality  of  duty  or  of 
obligation. 

*  "  The  great  releasing   question  :    '  Then  why  shouldn't  we  have 
a  good  time  ?  '  "  says  H.  G.  Wells  ("  Marriage,"  page  9). 


212  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

/  By  duty,  then,  we  understand  a  necessity  laid  on  a 
/man  to  do  certain  acts  and  to  avoid  others.  Now,  it  is 
/evident  that  the  necessity  of  duty  cannot  be  a  physical 
I  necessity — ^that  is,  a  necessity  which  so  coerces  us  into 
the  following  of  a  certain  course  of  action  that  the 
opposite  course  ceases  to  be  possible  to  us.  A  man, 
for  instance,  may  be  able  physically  to  tell  a  lie, 
though  at  the  same  time,  he  is  under  the  necessity  of 
duty  not  to  tell  it.  Thus  the  necessity  of  duty  is  a 
necessity  which  is  compatible  with  our  physical  freedom 
to  do  or  not  to  do  that  which  duty  prescribes.  In  other 
words,  the  necessity  of  duty  is  a  moral  necessity,  a  neces- 
sity which  is  compatible  with  freedom.  And  the  proof 
of  duty  will  consist  in  showing  that  we  are  under  some 
kind  of  necessity  to  do  certain  acts  which  yet  physically 
we  are  able  to  do  or  to  avoid. 

From  all  this  it  follows  that  duty  is  a  necessity  laid 
on  the  will.  For,  in  the  first  place,  it  is  a  necessity 
which  is  compatible  with  freedom,*  and  freedom  resides 
exclusively  in  the  will.  Secondly,  duty  is  a  necessity  of 
doing  certain  acts  and  avoiding  others,  and  hence  the 
necessity  of  duty  must  be  laid  upon  that  faculty  on 
which  all  human  action  depends — namely,  the  will. 
Consequently,  the  moral  necessity  which  we  shall  have 
to  establish  in  this  chapter  must  be  a  necessity  that 
primarily  and  essentially  binds  the  will,  and  through 
the  will  the  other  faculties  also  and  the  whole  man. 

Moral  Obligation  or  Duty,  as  we  have  just  said,  is  a 
necessity  to  do  certain  actions.  But  every_jiecessity 
depends  on  law  of  some  kiad- -  The  necessity  of  the 
chemical  affinities,  the  neceaeity  of  flowering  in  a  plant, 

*  That  duty  is  laid  on  a  f^ee  will  is  not  the  point  of  the  present 
chapter.  Wc  wish  simply  to  show  that  there  is  laid  on  the  will  a 
necessity  of  doing  the  Rood.  But  clearly  this  necessity,  if  we  can 
succeed  in  establishing  it,  is  not  a  physical  necessity,  since  men,  as  a 
matter  of  fact,  sometimes  do  evil,  and  if  they  were  under  a  physical 
necessity  of  doing  the  good  they  could  not  do  evil.  In  tluit  way  we 
claim  that  duty  is  a  moral  necessity  or  a  necessity  that  is  compatible 
with  freedom.  Sec  also  dur  argument  in  last  chapter,  page  198.  How- 
ever, our  argumcntatioa  in  this  chapter  will  not  relate  to  freedom. 


ON  DUTY  213 

the  necessity  of  eating  in  the  case  of  the  animal,  all 
spring  from  law,  proximately  from  some  law  of  nature 
through  which  these  necessities  manifest  themselves  to 
us,  and  ultimately  from  that  eternal  necessary  law  of 
the  Supreme  Lawgiver  on  which  the  laws  of  nature 
are  founded,  and  which  is  their  ultimate  ground.  Now 
since  duty  is  a  necessity,  it  also  ultimately  rests  on  the 
eternal  law  of  the  Supreme  Lawgiver,  and  hence  the 
ultimate  ground  or  reason  why  I  must  or  am  bound  to 
do  this  or  that  good  action  is  because  such  is  the  eternal 
and  necessary  law  of  the  Supreme  Being. 

But  we  are  led  also  to  look  for  a  proximate  ground 
of  duty  residing  in  nature  itself.  And  it  is  this  proxi- 
mate natural  ground  of  duty  that  we  are  about  to  in- 
vestigate in  the  present  chapter.  That  such  a  proxi- 
mate ground  of  duty  exists  in  nature  is  to  be  expected 
from  the  manner  in  which  the  eternal  law  relates  to 
things  in  the  other  departments  of  the  created  world. 
For,  first,  the  eternal  law  of  God  does  not  move  the 
world  directly  and  immedia:ely,  but  mediately,  i.e., 
through  the  operation  of  secondary  causes  or  causes 
residing  in  nature  itself ;  and  therefore  it  is  not  to  be 
expected  that  in  the  moral  world  the  eternal  law  will 
be  operative  without  some  such  intermediate  natural! 
principle.  The  plant  is  urged  or  necessitated  to  reach 
its  natural  end  because  of  natural  necessities  residing 
within  itself.  The  animal  is  necessitated  to  seek  for 
food  because  of  an  inner  natural  appetite  moving  it 
to  take  food  ;  and  so  we  may  expect  to  find  that  the 
necessity  of  duty  though  resting  ultimately  on  God's 
eternal  law,  without  which  it  could  not  exist,  will  be 
grounded  immediately  upon,  and  will  manifest  itself 
through  some  more  proximate  law  residing  in,  and 
arising  out  of  human  nature  itself.  Secondly,  we  are 
led  to  expect  that  moral  duty  must  rest  upon  some 
inner  natural  ground  because  moral  goodness  to  which 
duty  relates  is  dependent  immediately  upon  the  inner 
requirements  of  our  human  nature.     The  goodness  of 


214  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  human  act  depends  upon  the  inner  character  of  the 
act  itself :  it  would  be  strange  if  duty  which  is  the 
necessity  of  doing  good,  should  be  found  not  to  rest 
Upon  an}^  ground  of  nature,  but  should  be  caused 
immediately  by  the  eternal  law.  As  we  said  before, 
not  only  the  good  or  the  perfection  of  plant  and  animal 
are  determined  immediately  by  their  nature,  but  the 
necessity  also  by  which  they  are  moved  to  reach  their 
final  perfection  is  from  nature.  And  duty  is  the  necessity 
of  reaching  our  natural  perfection.* 

The  question — What  is  the  immediate  ground  of 
duty  (which  also  will  supply  us  with  our  proof  of  duty) 
we  now  go  on  to  investigate. 


(b)  Proof  that  it  is  our  Duty  to  do  the  Good 

Now,  duty  being  a  necessity  laid  on  the  will,  we  must, 
before  we  can  definitely  establish  the  existence  of  moral 
duty,  consider  in  what  sense  and  how  far  the  human 
will  can  be  made  subject  to  necessity — that  is,  we  must 
determine  what  are  the  various  kinds  of  necessity,  and 
which,  if  any,  of  them  can  affect  the  v;ill.  Into  this 
question  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  enters  most  fully  when 
treating  of  the  psychology  of  the  will. 

St.  Thomas  distinguishes J^  four  kinds  of  necessity 
arising  from  each  of  jdieJourJdnHs  of  cause — the  formal, 
the  material,  the  efficient,  and  the  final  cause.  Two  of 
these  kinds  of  necessity,  however — those  arising  from 
the  material  and  formal  causes,  that  is,  from  the  in- 
ternal constituent  causes  of  things — he  groups  together, 

•  This  law  of  nature  whereby  we  prove  the  existence  of  duty  will 
be  found  to  exhibit  a  very  special  dependence  on  the  Supreme  Being. 
For  besides  resting  like  other  laws  on  the  eternal  law  of  God,  it  arises 
immediately  (unlike  other  natural  laws)  out  of  the  final  causal  activity 
of  the  ultimate  end  of  tlic  will,  which  is  the  perfect  or  infinite  good. 
Also  this  natural  law  itself  requires  to  be  supplemented  by  other 
truths  connected  with  the  Divine  legislation,  e.g.,  the  sanctions  of 
the  IMvine  law,  in  order  to  give  us  the  full  conception  of  duty  and 
what  it  involves. 

t  "  S.  Theol.,"  I.,  Q.  LXXXII.,  Art.  i. 


ON  DUTY  215 

and  calls  them  natural  necessities,  that  is,  inner  neces- 
sities depending  solely  on  the  inner  essence  or  nature 
of  things.  We  are  then  left  with  tll££e  distinct  classes 
of  necessity— namely,  (i)  the  necessity  of  nature,  (2)  the 
necessity  of  efficient  cause,  (3)  the  necessity  01  end. 
Min Absolute  necessity,  or  the"necessity  of  nature,  is,  as 
we  said,  the  necessity  which  arises  from  the  inner 
essence  of  a  thing.  For,  given  a  certain  nature,  certain 
properties,  relations,  and  acts  must  follow,  and  with 
absolute  necessity.  Examples  are  the  necessity  that  a 
triangle  should  have  its  angles  equal  to  two  right  angles, 
that  a  material  object  should  be  capable  of  divisioij'J 
or  that  a  compound  substance  should  be  chemically 
alterable.  The  farmer  necessity — that  of  the  triangle — 
arises  out  of  the  formal  cause  of  things  ;  the  latter 
from  the  material  cause.  These  are  the  internal  con- 
stituents. Again  ((2))  necessity  may  arise  from  some- 
thing extrinsic  to  the  object.  Thus,  it  may  arise  from 
some  e^cient  cause  or  agent  outside  the  object,  as  when 
a  man  is  thrown  to  the  ground  by  another  whom  he 
cannot  resist.  This  St.  Thomas  calls  the  necessity  of 
compulsion  or  of  constraint.  /(3)jOr  the  extrinsic  prin- 
ciple of  necessity  may  be  tnlS^nd  or  final  cause,  as 
when  a  man  7nust  take  ti  boat  if  it  is  his  purpose  to  cross 
the  ocean.  To  this  "  must  "  he  gives  the  name  "  final 
necessity,"  or  "  necessitas  finis,"  or  "  necessitas  ex 
fine  "  or  "ex  suppositionc  finis  " — which  latter  phrases 
are  clearer  and  better  than  "  necessitas  finis,"  since  they 
clearly  indicate  that  the  necessity  referred  to  affects, 
not  the  end  itself,  but  the  means  to  it,  and  that  these 
means  become  a  necessity  to  us  only  on  condition  of 
our  desiring  the  end.  They  are  a  necessity,  on  the  sup- 
position of  our  desiring  the  end. 

Now,  of  these  three  kinds  of  necessity,  the  second — 
that  is,  the  necessity  of  constraint — is  wholly  foreign 
to  the  will,  for  the  will  cannot  be  violently  compelled 
to  an  act  by  any  agent  outside  itself.  Acts  of  the  will 
are    voluntary    acts ;     and    voluntary    movement    and 


2i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

violence  are  diametrically  opposed  to  each  other.  But 
the  other  two  kinds  of  necessity,  St.  Thomas  shows, 
may  and  do  affect  the.,will,„ and  hence  the  consideration 
of  them  is  required  here.  We  shall  for  convenience' 
sake  consider,  as  St.  Thomas  also  does,  the  third  kind 
of  necessity  first. 

In  the  first  place,  the  will  is  subject  to  that  species  of 
necessity  which  we  have  called  necessitas  ex  fine  or  ex 
suppositione  finis.  For  it  is  plain  that  if  a  man  wishes 
an  end,  and  if  there  be  but  one  means  to  its  attainment, 
then  that  means  becomes  a  necessity  to  the  will.*  Thus, 
if  a  man  wants  to  cross  the  ocean,  he  must  travel  in  a 
ship.  If  he  wants  to  be  learned,  he  must  study.  This 
kind  of  necessity  holds  good,  however,  provided  only 
that  the  will  truly  and  seriously  desires  the  end.  For  if 
the  wish  of  the  will  be  only  a  velleity — that  is,  if  the  will 
merely  would  wish  the  end  (under  some  supposition  or 
condition),  but  does  not  actually  wis-i  it  because*  that 
condition  is  not  fulfilled,  then  no  necessity  arises  as 
regards  the  desire  of  the  means,  for  in  that  case  the  will 
does  not  really  wish  the  end.  Thus,  a  poor  man  might 
wish  to  see  America  if  it  were  not  so  expensive.  His 
wish  is  merely  a  "  velleity."  But  such  a  wish  involves 
no  necessity  as  to  the  means,  since  de  facto  he  does  not 
will  the  end.  But  if  the  end  be  wished  actually  and 
seriously,  then  the  means  to  it  biecome  a  necessity  to  the 
will— I  must  wish  to  take  the  means  if  I  seriously  wish 
to  gain  the  end.  The  will,  then,  is  subject  to  that 
kind  of  necessity  which  we  called  necessitas  finis  or  ex 
fine. 

Secondly,  the  will  is  subject  to  the  absolute  and 
natural  necessity  of  wishing  the  last  end — that  is,  it 
wishes  this  last  end  in  itself  and  cannot  help  wishing 
it.  It  wishes  the  final  end  from  its  very  nature.  Our 
proofs  of  this  proposition  are : — First,  jjj  The  will  must 
of  its  very  nature  desire  happiness-in-general  and  the 
good-in-general — its  natural  object.     If  the  perfect   or 

•  "  Qui  vcut  la  fin  veut  aussi  lea  moyens."— Rousseau. 


ON  DUTY  217 

infinite  good  were  perceived  immediately  the  will  should 
also  desire  it  necessarily,  since  the  perfect  good  contains 
all  that  is  included  under  the  good-in-general.  The 
will  may,  indeed,  refuse  to  desire  this  or  that  par- 
ticular or  finite  object,  this  or  that  finite  pleasure, 
because  in  every  finite  good  there  is  something  which 
the  will  can  regard  as  evil,  and  from  which  it  can  turn 
away.  This  "  something  "  may  be  a  positive  evil,  or 
it  may  be  the  mere  absence  of  good — mere  limitation 
in  good ;  but  because  of  this  "  something  "  there  is  no 
finite  good  which  the  will  must  of  necessity  desire. 
But  the  perfect  good  it  cannot  help  desiring,  for  in  the 
perfect  good  there  is  nothing  from  which  the  will  can 
turn  away.  (2)  Our  second  proof  that  the  will  must 
wish  the  last"end,  and  cannot  help  wishing  it,  is  that 
the  will  depends  on  and  follows  the  intellect — we  desire 
only  that  which  is  known,  and  after  the  manner  in 
which  a  thing  is  known.  But  the  speculative  intellect 
{e.g.,  as  used  in  Geometry)  begins  its  reasonings  from 
axioms  which  it  must  accept,  which  it  cannot  help 
accepting,  on  which  it  is  fixed  by  nature  ;  no  intellect 
can  refuse  to  assent  to  these  first  principles,  and  unless 
it  were  so  fixed  in  them  it  could  not  even  begin  to 
reason.  So,  also,  no  will  can  refuse  its  adhesion  to 
what  we  might  call  the  first  principle  of  the  will — - 
namely,  its  last  end.  Of  its  nature  it  has  to  desire 
that  end.  "  Finis  se  habet  in  operabilibus  sicut  prin- 
cipium  in  speculabilibus."  (^  Thirdly,  the  act  of  the 
will  is  essentially  an  act  of  movement,  of  direction 
towards  an  end.  But  movement  is  impossible  unless  it 
begins  in  something  which  is  firmly  fixed — Omne  mobile 
procedit  ah  immohili.  Consequently,  our  will-movements 
must  begin  with  the  desire  of  some  fixed  end — some 
end,  that  is,  on  which  the  will  is  itself  naturally  and 
permanently  fixed.  If  there  were  no  such  object  or 
end  the  will  could  not  even  begin  to  move.     There  is, 

*  Ethicians  of  the  most  widely  divergent  schools,  e.g.,  Aristotle, 
Mill,  Kant,  Spencer,  are  in  agreement  on  this  principle. 


2i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

then,  an  end  which  the  will  desires,  not  by  choice,  but 
because  it  is  fixed  on  such  an  end  by  nature.  The 
necessity  of  this  end  is  what  is  described  by  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas  as  absolute  or  natural  necessity.  Subjectively 
this  end  is  happiness  ;  objectively  it  is  the  object  of 
perfect  happiness. 

Now,  just  as  from  the  desire  for  any  end,  there  arises 
the  necessity  of  taking  the  means  which  lead  to  it,  so 
from  the  natural  desire  for  the  last  end  there  springs 
the  necessity  {necessitas  ex  fine)  of  taking  at  least  some 
of  the  means  that  lead  to  it — namely,  those  that  are 
necessary  for  it,  and  of  avoiding  all  those  things  that 
lead  away  from  it.  But  good  acts,  we  assume,  are 
those  that  lead  to  the  final  end,  bad  acts  lead  us  away 
from  it.  Therefore,  just  as  from  the  desire  to  ride 
there  arises  the  necessity  for  a  horse,  and  from  the 
desire  to  cross  the  ocean  there  arises  the  necessity  of 
travelling  in  a  ship,  and  from  the  desire  for  health  there 
arises  the  necessity  of  avoiding  certain  foods — so  also, 
from  the  desire  for  the  final  end,  there  arises  the  necessity 
of  doing  good  and  avoiding  evil.* 

Thus  far  we  are  brought  by  St.  Thomas  in  his  Psy- 
chology. Of  moral  obligation  he  makes  no  express 
mention  in  this  part  of  his  work.  But  it  is  evident 
that  this  necessity  which  we  have  just  established — 
the  necessity  of  wishing  those  things  that  are  required 
for  the  final  end — is  none  other  than  the  necessity  of 
moral  obligation.  For,  in  the  first  place,  it  is  a  necessity 
of  doing  the  good  and  of  avoiding  evil.  It  is  a  necessity, 
that  is,  of  taking  the  means  to  the  final  end,  and,  there- 
fore, it  is  just  precisely  what  St.  Thomas,  in  his  exposS, 
calls  necessitas  ex  fine.  Secondly,  in  his  treatise  on 
"  Justice,"  St.  Thomas  expressly  identifies  these  con- 
ceptions of  moral  obligation  and  final  necessity.     Writing 

•  Duty  therefore  is  founded  on  our  desire  for  the  pood  and  for 
happiness.  It  is  common  amonp  writers  to  ojipose  these  two  con- 
ceptions, and  to  regard  what  is  a  duty  as  oxchidinx  iiappiiiess  or 
plcastirc.  "No,  he  replied  sagely,"*  your  garden  is  nt»t  your  duty 
because  it  is  your  pleasure  "  (Elizabeth  and  her  German  Garden). 


ON  DUTY  219 

on  the  question  whether  Justice  is  a  virtue,*  he  offers 
this  difficulty.  "  That  which  is  done  from  necessity 
is  not  a  cause  of  merit.  But  to  render  to  each  man 
his  due,  which  is  the  end  of  justice,  is  necessary. 
Therefore,  it  is  not  a  cause  of  merit.  But  acts  of  virtue 
are  meritorious.  Therefore,  justice  is  not  a  virtue." 
This  difficulty  he  answers  as  follows  :  "To  the  second 
objection  our  reply  is — There  are  two  kinds  of  necessity 
— one  the  necessity  of  constraint  {coactionis) ,  and  this 
because  opposed  to  will  does  not  admit  of  merit.  But 
there  is  another  necessity  which  is  ex  ohligatione  frae- 
cepti  sive  necessitate  finis — namely,  when  the  end  of 
virtue  cannot  be  gained  without  a  certain  act,"  &c.,  &c. 
But,  as  we  said,  apart  from  this  express  quotation,  it 
is  evident  that  what  we  have  proved  to  be  a  moral 
necessity  laid  on  the  will  'to  do  good,  is  precisely  what 
St.  Thomas  means  by  necessitas  ex  fine  as  expounded  in 
the  Psychology. 

THE    ABSOLUTE    CHARACTER   OF   MORAL    DUTY  f 

As  yet  we  have  not  emphasised  an  essential  character- 
istic of  the  necessity  of  duty — a  characteristic  which  is 
all-important  in  connection  with  our  present  enquiry^ 
namely,  that  on  St.  Thomas'  own  showing  the  necessity 
of  taking  the  means  which  lead  to  our  final  end  is  not 
a  hypothetical  or  conditional,  but  an  absolute,  necessity, 
or,  as  moderns  call  it,  a  categorical  necessity — in  other 
words,  that  duty  is  categorical.  The  reader  will  already 
have  been  familiar  with  these  terms  from  his  studies  in 
Logic.  A  hypothetical  proposition  is  a  proposition  of 
the  form — if  a  is  h,  c  is  d.  A  categorical  proposition  is 
one  of  the  form — c  is  d.  So  also  a  hypothetical  necessity 
is  one  that  depends  on  an  // — if  I  want  a  I  must  do  6. 

*  "  S.  Theol.,"  II.,  Ila^.,  Q.  LVIII.,  Art.  3.     Second  objection. 

•f  The  reader  must  be  careful  to  distinguish  between  this  absolute 
(or  categorical)  necessity  of  which  St.  Thomas  speaks  and  the  absolute 
or  categorical  Imperative  of  Kant.  The  categorical  Imperative  of 
Kant  is  discussed  and  disproved  in  our  chapter  on  Law. 


/cs^ 


220  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

A  categorical  necessity  is  one  that  depends  on  no  if,  no 
condition^=I  must  do  h.  It  is  now  our  purpose  to  show- 
that  duty  is  an  absolute  or  categorical  necessity,  that  it 
depends  on  no  if — that  we  must  do  the  good,  not  if  we 
wish  to  gain  some  end  which  we  are  able  to  wish  or  not 
to  wish,  but  absolutely,  and  always,  and  in  every  act, 
without  any  if,  or  any  qualification  or  condition. 

Let  us,  in  order  to  bring  out  this  distinction,  take  a 
particular  case  of  hypothetical  necessity  and  see  how  it 
arises  and  how  it  differs  from  the  necessity  of  duty. 
The  necessity  of  taking  a  boat  or  a  carriage  can  never 
be  more  than  a  hypothetical  necessity,  for  it  always 
depends  upon  an  if.  These  things  are  a  necessity  to 
me  if  I  desire  to  travel.  If  I  do  not  desire  to  travel 
they  are  not  a  necessity.  The  necessity  of  the  ship  or 
carriage,  then,  is  always  hypothetical,  always  dependent 
on  that  if.  Why  is  this  ?  The  reason  is  because  the 
end — travelling — is  not  itself  a  necessary  end — that  is, 
it  is  not  absolutely  necessary  to  the  will.  It  is  not  some- 
thing which  we  have  to  desire  by  an  inner  necessity  of 
our  nature.  Of  travelling  we  can  never  say  simply  and 
universally — "  the  will  has  to  wish  it,"  since  it  is  in 
my  power  at  any  moment  either  to  desire  it  or  not  to 
desire  it.  But,  suppose  that  there  be  an  end  which  is 
itself  absolutely  necessary  to  our  wills,  an  end  which  we 
cannot  help  wishing,  an  end  on  which  Nature  herself 
has  permanently  fixed  our  wills,  then  undoubtedly  the 
necessity  of  willing  the  means  to  that  end  will  depend 
on  no  if — they  will  be  necessary  to  us  unconditionally, 
absolutely,  categorically. 

Now,  it  is  exactly  in  this  way  that  we  establish  the 
categorical  character  of  the  moral  ought  or  duty.  On 
our  final  end — happiness  and  the  '  good  ' — the  will, 
as  we  have  shown,  is  absolutely  and  permanently  fixed 
by  an  irresistible  law  of  nature  herself.  Consequently, 
the  means  to  our  final  natural  end  are  categorically 
necessary  to  us.  I  ought  to  wish  the  means  //  I  wish 
the  end.     But  I  do  wish  the  end.     Therefore,  I  ought 


ON  DUTY  221 

to  wish  the  means  (without  any  if  or  condition).  The 
categorical  necessity  of  duty,  then,  is  estabhshed  as  we 
estabUsh  any  other  categorical  conclusion — namely,  by 
affirming  the  antecedent  *  of  a  conditional  proposition. 
Thus  I  ought  to  wish  a  if  I  wish  6  to  which  it  leads  ;  I 
ought  to  wish  6  if  I  wish  c  to  which  it  leads.  ...  I 
ought  to  wish  y  if  I  wish  z  to  which  it  leads.  But  I  do 
wish  z.  Therefore,  I  ought  (without  any  if)  to  wish  y 
and  X  and  .  .  .  c  and  b  and  a.  It  will  be  said  that 
following  this  method  a  man  might  establish  other 
categorical  necessities  besides  those  of  duty.  For 
instance,  that — "  I  ought  to  take  a  boat  if  I  wish  to 
cross  to  America.  But  I  do  wish  to  cross  to  America. 
Therefore,  I  ought  to  take  a  boat."  But,  as  we  have 
just  pointed  out,  such  arguments  as  these  are  only 
categorical  in  form,  because  the  minor  proposition  of 
the  inference  is  in  reality  conditional  and  dependent. 
It  is  not  absolutely  true.  It  is  true  only  as  long  as  my 
present  humour  lasts,  and,  therefore,  it  is  true  con- 
ditionally. About  such  ends  I  can  always  seriously 
raise  the  question  whether  I  do  desire  them.  But 
the  desire  of  the  ultimate  end  is  an  absolute  necessity 
which  depends  on  no  if  or  condition,  and  it  is  the  only 
truly  unconditional  desire  of  our  will.  This  desire  I 
can  never  question.  Therefore,  duty  is  the  only  neces-  ] 
sity  which  is  absolutely  and  in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  I 
word  categorical.  I 

A  point,  too,  of  interest  and  importance  in  connection 
with  the  categorical  necessity  of  duty  is,  that  in  the  case 
of  duty,  the  hypothetical  series,  out  of  which,  as  we  said, 
we  obtain  our  categorical  conclusion,  is  closed  (in  logical 
terms,  the  minor  is  established)  by  nature  and  not  by 
the  individual  will  or  intellect,  for  it  is  nature  that  fixes 
our  wills  on  the  final  end,  and  thus  by  establishing  the 
minor  proposition  "  I  do  wish  the  end,"  nature  has  also 
established  the  categorical  conclusion  that  I  ought  to 

*  The  other  method — denying  the  consequent — is  not  appUcable 
here. 


222  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

wish  the  means  to  it.  In  the  fullest  sense  of  the  word, 
then,  moral  duty  is  natural.  For  not  only  are  certain 
objects  natural  means  to  man's  final  end,  but  our  desire 
of  that  end  is  natural  also,  and,  therefore,  the  necessity 
of  the  means  is  natural. 

HISTORICAL   NOTE 

The  foregoing  line  of  argument  is  followed  by  Fathers 
Schiffmi,  S.J..  and  Taparelli,  S.J.,  and  by  other  Scholastics. 
"  In  order,"  writes  Taparelli,*  "  to  form  the  judgment — the 
good  ought  to  be  done — we  require  to  realise  mentally  a 
final  necessity — i.e.,  a  necessary  connection  of  means  with 
end,  such  that  without  the  means  the  end  cannot  be  obtained. 
But  is  this  connection  enough  ?  What  if  the  end  be  not 
itself  necessary  ?  Shall  we  then  be  compelled  to  admit  an 
'  ought.'  Study  is  necessary  to  science — but  is  science 
necessary  ?  If  it  is  not,  in  what  sense  can  you  say  that 
study  is  necessary  ?  Its  necessity  is  merely  hypothetical. 
But  moral  necessity  is  an  absolute  necessity  ;  a  thesis,  not  a 
hypothesis  (that  is,  a  categorical  necessity,  not  a  hypothetical). 
It  arises  from  an  end  to  which  every  will  tends  with  real 
necessity.  What  end  is  that,  but  the  object  of  perfect  human 
happiness?  .  .  .iMoral  obligation  may  therefore  be  defined 
as  an  ought  resulting  from  the  necessary  connexion  of  means 
with  a  necessary  end.") 

This,  the  reader  will  have  no  difficulty  in  seeing,  corre- 
sponds exactly  with  the  line  of  thought  developed  by  our- 
selves above. 

Father  Rickaby  follows  the  same  system  of  proof,  though, 
to  our  thinking,  he  does  not  bring  it  to  the  successful  issue 
to  which  it  is  brought  by  Taparelli.  "  The  word  ought,"  he 
writes,  "  denotes  a  necessary  bearing  of  means  on  end.  To 
every  ought  there  is  a  pendent  if.  The  means  ought  be  taken 
if  the  end  is  to  be  secured.  Thus  we  say — You  ought  to 
study  harder  if  you  want  to  pass  your  examination.  The 
person  spoken  to  might  reply — but  what  if  I  do  .  .  .  fail  in 
my  examination  ?  He  might  be  met  with  another  otigld — 
You  ought  not  fail  if  you  are  to  get  your  profession.  Thus 
the  train  of  oughts  and  ifs  extends  imtil  wo  come  (innlly  to  a 
concatenation  like  the  following — You  ought  not  break  your 
word.  &€.,  if  you  don't  want  to  do  violence  to  that  nature 
which  is  yours  as  a  reasonable  being."     "  If,"  Father  Rickaby 

*  "  Saggio  Tcoretico  di  dritto  naturale,"  page  55. 


ON  DUTY  223 

continues,  "  a  person  goes  on  to  ask — well  what  if  I  do  con- 
tradict my  rational  self  ?  We  can  only  answer  that  he  is  a 
fool  for  his  question." 

Father  Rickaby's  line  of  proof  corresponds  exactly  with 
that  developed  by  us  except  for  its  conclusion,  to  the  abrupt- 
ness of  which  we  venture  to  take  exception.  The  question — 
why  a  man  may  not  contradict  his  rational  self  is  not,  it 
seems  to  us,  a  foolish  question.  The  man  who  asks  "  what  if 
1  do  contradict  my  rational  self  "  may  be  a  fool  indeed,  not 
for  his  question,  but  for  wishing  to  violate  his  nature.  He 
may  be  a  bad  man  also,  but  the  question  still  remains,  why 
may  I  not  be  bad  ?  Why  may  I  not  violate  my  nature  and 
be  a  fool  ?  Until  Father  Rickaby  has  shown  a  why,  he  has 
not  established  the  ought  of  moral  obligation.  But  once  it 
is  shown  that  the  final  end  is  absolutely  necessary  to  my  wTlT, 
ft  becomes  evident  tlTat  the  means  are  necessary  also.* 

Mafiy "modern  philosophers,  some  of  them  far  from  the 
Scholastic  tradition,  have  given  clear  expression  to  the  view 
that  the  proof  of  duty  (if  duty  exists  at  all,  which  many  of 
them  deny)  lies  obviously  in  the  line  of  argument  followed 
by  us.  But  without  the  guiding  principles  of  the  Scholastic 
philosophy,  it  is  not  remarkable  that  they  have  failed  to 
bring  the  argument  to  a  successful  conclusion.  In  this 
connection  nobody  has  written  more  clearly  or  more  rationally 
than  Dr.  Simmel  of  the  University  of  Berlin. 

"  If  only,"  he  writes, t  "  you  can  discover  a  final  end  for 
the  will,  you  will  have  discovered  that  which  gives  to  the 
endless  teleological  series  meaning  and  content.  Until  you 
can  discover  that  end,  you  can  always  still  ask — why  we 
ought  wish  this  or  that  other  end.  But  if  you  can  discover 
the  supreme  end  of  the  will,  then  that  question  has  no  longer 
any  meaning."  Simmel  fails,  however,  to  discover  any  such 
single  final  end. 

Again  Sidgwick  writes — "  It  can  hardly  be  denied  that  the 
recognition  of  an  end  as  ultimately  reasonable  involves  the 
recognition  of  an  obligation  to  do  such  acts  as  most  conduce 
to  tliis  end."  But  if  an  end  ultimately  reasonable  involves 
the  recognition  of  obligation,  a  fortiori,  an  end  on  which 
nature  has  so  fixed  the  will  that  we  cannot  help  wishing  it, 
involves  an  obligation  of  doing  what  leads  to  that  end. 

And  Ed.  von  Hartmann — "  All  such  ends  "  (namely  goods 
of  the  individual,  the  family,  and  the  State)  "  are  but  means 

♦  See  also  "  Du  Bien,"  by  De  Lantsheere  (Louvain),  page  76. 
f  "  Einleitung,"  page  341.      Many  of  the  views  here  given  are  re- 
tracted by  Prof.  Simmel  in  his  later  works 


424  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  the  absolute  final  end  of  the  Universe  (Weltzweck)  ;  and 
their  relative  value,  and  the  value-judgment  that  they  give 
rise  to,  must  be  determined  from  their  teleological  relation  to 
the  final  end." 

And  M.  Fouillee,  writing  from  the  point  of  view  of  the 
idee-force  philosophy,  says  * — "  If  life  is  an  object  of  desire 
for  men,  all  that  tends  to  maintain  and  promote  life  becomes 
hypothetically  necessary.  .  .  .  These  hypothetical  impera- 
tives become  assertory  the  moment  one  adds — de  facto  man 
wishes  to  live  and  be  happy.  .  .  .  But  as  for  judging  whether 
such  an  end  is  the  supreme  end,  the  supreme  obligation, 
whether  it  is  imposed  on  each  man  categorically,  whether 
there  is  or  is  not  a  supreme  principle  of  conduct,  &c.,  these 
are  the  problems  of  first  philosophy  since  they  deal  with 
ultimates,  and  they  ought  be  reserved  for  philosophy 
properly  so  called."  f 

(c)  A  Difficulty 

Our  theory  of  obligation  raises  the_diffi£ully  whether 
wHaT'we  ha^ve  said  on  the  absolute  necessity  with  which 
our  wills  are  made  to  tend  to  the  final  end  can  be  recon- 
ciled with  the  freedom  of  the  will  as  regards  the  means  ; 
which,  as  we  saw,  is  an  indispensable  condition  of  moral 
obligation.  If,  it  may  be  objected,  the  will  is  fixed 
absolutely  on  the  final  end — that  is,  if  it  must  wish  this 
end,  and  cannot  help  wishing  it,  and  if  the  intellect 
knows  that  certain  acts — viz.,  bad  acts — lead  away 
from  this  end,  how  is  it  possible  for  the  will  to  desire 
these  acts,  in  other  words,  how  can  man  do  evil  know- 
ingly  ? 

Now  this  difficulty  is  met  in  the  clearest  and  fullest 
way  by  Aristotle  in  his  Nichomachean  Ethics,  +  and  his 
argument  has  Feen  amplified  in  such  a  manner  by  St. 
Thomas  Aquinas  as  to  merit  the  description  of  "  the 
one  thoroughgoing  refutation  perhaps  ever  given  of  the 
determinism  of  Socrates  and  Plato  who  reduced  moral 

•  "  Lcs  616mcnt.s  socioloRiquos  dc  la  Morale,"  pages  21  and  22. 

f  Some  philosophers  regard  all  final  necessity  as  of  its  nature 
hypothetical,  anil  these  are  naturally  debarreci  from  following  out  any 
such  line  of  ))roof  as  that  given  in  the  text. 

}  Book  VII.,  chapter  3. 


ON  DUTY  225 

to  intellectual  error,  and  put  it  beyond  the  control  of 
the  will."  * 

Aristotle's  solution  is  as  follows :  knowledge  is  of 
two  kinds— knowledge  in  use  f  and  knowledge  possessed 
but  not  in  use  ;  in  other  words,  knowledge  applied  to 
action  and  knowledge  in  abeyance  and  not  applied. 
Now  it  would  be  a  strange  thing,  says  Aristotle,  were  a 
man  to  know  in  the  first  way  that  his  act  was  evil, 
that  is  to  know  with  knowledge  in  use,  and  then  to  do 
the  evil  act ;  but  there  is  nothing  impossible  in  a  man 
doing  evil  knowingly  provided  his  knowledge  though 
possessed   is  in   abeyance,  |    and   not   applied.     Such   a 

•  In  other  words  these  two  philosophers  succumbed  to  the  diffi- 
culty and  taught  that  all  vice  is  ignorance,  that  it  is  impossible  to  do 
wrong  knowingly. 

t  6  xp^f^foi  and  6  ?x'«"'  M^''  o^  xP'^f^^"'^- 

I  Sir  A.  Grant  considers  that  Aristotle  borrowed  the  distinction 
from  the  Theaetetus  where  Plato  "introduces  his  famous  image  of 
the  pigeon-house.  Every  knowledge  once  acquired  by  the  mind  is 
like  a  bird  caught  and  placed  in  the  pigeon-house  ;  it  is  possessed, 
but  not  available,  till  it  be  chased  within  the  enclosure  and  captured 
anew." 

Aristotle,  continumg  the  argument  given  above,  goes  on  to  show 
from  a  number  of  examples  that  this  distinction  is  not  invented  merely 
for  the  sake  of  solving  the  present  difficulty.  The  possession  of 
knowledge  which  yet  is  not  in  use  is  a  familiar  experience.  Crude 
instances  are  those  of  the  drunken  man,  the  sleeper,  and  the  man  who 
is  driven  mad  by  passion.  The  latter  particularly  knows,  but  his 
knowledge  is  not  in  use.  No  doubt,  says  Aristotle,  if  you  ask  him  he 
will  tell  you  that  his  act  is  bad,  but  he  used  the  words  as  learners  do 
who  repeat  their  master's  sayings  without  realising  their  full  import, 
or  as  actors  do  who  do  not  feel  the  things  their  speeches  represent. 
It  is  in  some  such  way  that  a  man  does  evil,  knowing  that  it  is  evil, 
yet  without  applying  what  he  knows. 

Aristotle  then  goes  on  to  examine  the  psychological  machinery 
{(t>v<TiKw — ^he,  of  course,  regarded  Psychology  as  a  branch  of  Physics) 
by  which  the  mind  is  enabled  to  put  its  knowledge  in  abeyance.  This 
consists  in  the  fact  that  will  is  moved  by  the  practical  judgment 
of  the  intellect  declaring  that  this  is  good  and  to  be  done  ;  now  this 
judgment  is  itself  a  conclusion  from  many  premisses,  and  it  is  in  the 
power  of  the  intellect  to  ignore  any  one  or  group  of  the  premisses 
available,  and  to  select  a  group  that  will  represent  the  bad  act  as  not 
bad  or  even  as  good.  Thus  the  man  who  is  resolved  upon  doing  a 
bad  but  pleasure-producing  act  will  emphasise  the  judgments,  "  pleasure 
is  a  good  thing,"  and  "  this  act  is  pleasant,"  ignoring  the  other  premisses 
in  which  are  set  out  the  bad  elements  in  the  act. 

We  may  Ix;  permitted  to  remark  at  the  conclusion  of  this  note  that 
the  fact  that  the  passage  here  referred  to  is  by  some  not  regarded  as 
genuine  in  no  way  detracts  from  its  value  and  force. 

Vol.  I— 15 


226  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

one,  though  knowing  that  his  act  is  bad  is  free  to  ignore 
the  element  of  evil,  and  to  attend  to  what  is  good  in 
it  (in  every  bad  act  there  is  some  good  element — it  is 
at  least  pleasure-producing)  and  to  act  for  the  sake  of 
that  good  element. 

Thus  far  we  are  brought  by  Aristotle.  The  will  is 
able  to  do  evil  knowingly  because  knowledge  may  be  put 
in  abeyance  at  any  time.  But  then  the  difficulty  arises 
— ^how  is  a  man  responsible  for  his  evil  acts  since  it  is 
possible  to  do  them  only  when  one's  knowledge  is  in 
abeyance.  It  is  here  that  St.  Thomas  takes  up  the 
discussion.  A  man  is  responsible  for  his  evil  action 
since  it  is  by  his  own  free  will  that  he  puts  his  know- 
ledge in  abeyance,  by  electing  to  consider  this  and  to 
ignore  that,  that  is,  his  lack  of  regard  for  what  his  reason 
knows  is  voluntary.  "  Whenever,"  writes  St.  Thomas,* 
"  the  will  tends  to  act  under  the  motive  of  an  appre- 
hension of  reason  representing  to  it  its  own  proper  good, 
a  due  action  ensues.  But  when  the  will  bursts  out  into 
action  upon  the  apprehension  of  the  sensible  appre- 
hensive faculty,  or  even  upon  the  apprehension  of  reason 
itself,  representing  some  other  good  than  the  proper 
good  of  the  will,  there  ensues  in  the  action  of  the  will  a 
moral  fault.  Therefore  any  fault}'  action  in  the  will  is 
preceded  by  a  lack  of  due  regard  to  reason,  and  to  the 
proper  end  of  willing.  I  say  "  a  lack  of  due  regard  to 
reason "  in  such  cases  as  when  upon  some  sudden 
apprehension  of  "  sense  the  will  tends  to  some  good 
that  is  pleasant  according  to  sense  ;  I  say  "  a  lack  of 
due  regard  to  the  proper  end  of  willing  "  in  cases  when 
the  reason  arrives  by  reasoning  at  some  good  which  is 
not  either  now  or  in  this  way  good,  and  still  the  will 
tends  to  it  as  though  it  were  its  proper  good.  Now  this 
lack  of  due  regard  is  voluntary  ;  for  it  is  in  the  power 
of  the  will  to  will  and  not  to  will ;  it  is  Hkewise  in  its 
power  to  direct  reason  actually  to  consider  or  to  cease 
from   considering,    or   to   consider   this   or   that.     Still, 

*  Sumtna  Contra  Gentiles  (Rickaby's  transl.)  111.  lo. 


ON  DUTY  227 

this  failure  of  due  consideration  is  not  a  moral  evil ; 
for,  consideration  or  no  consideration,  or  whatever  the 
consideration  be  on  reason's  part,  there  is  no  sin  until 
the  will  comes  to  tend  to  some  undue  end,  which  thenv 
is  an  act  of  evil."     Briefly,  evil  is  possible  through  our  K 
not  actually  considering  the  evil  which  our  act  contains.  1 
But  in  as  much  as  this  turning  away  of  the  reason  from    \ 
the  evil  of  our  act  is  itself  free  and  voluntary,  and  inas-  f 
much  as  we  do  not  cease  to  be  aware  of  the  evil  of  our  act,  1 
even  when  we  ignore  the  evil  of  it,  the  whole  act  that  J 
we  do,  evil  and  good  alike,  is  free  and  imputable  to  us.  X 

It  is  important  to  remember  that  this  phenomenon 
to  which  Aristotle  directs  our  attention,  viz.,  the  putting 
of  our  knowledge  in  abeyance  in  order  to  do  evil  repre- 
sents a  common  and  familiar  operation.  The  sinner 
always  excuses  himself,  that  is,  he  looks  only  to  the 
innocent  or  the  good  element  in  his  act.  But  it  is  in  con- 
nection with  the  graver  crimes  that  the  conclusiveness  of 
Aristotle's  reasoning  becomes  fully  apparent.  The  man 
who  could  not  possibly  kill  his  father  as  long  as  he 
realises  that  he  is  killing  a  parent,  will  consciously  and 
freely  turn  his  mind  from  the  actual  consideration  of 
this  fact,  and  fix  his  attention  on  some  wrong  done 
him  or  the  good  to  be  gained  by  his  act,  in  order  to 
make  the  murder  possible.  And  this  unwillingness  to 
face  a  premeditated  crime  when  it  appears  before  one 
in  its  full  wickedness  is  not  unnatural.  The  will  is 
fixed  upon  the  good  and  recoils  from  evil.  It  is  this 
voice  of  nature  that  speaks  so  eloquently  in  the  soul  of 
Lady  Macbeth,  when  she  prays  the  night  to  hide  from 
her  the  full  evil  of  her  terrible  deed  :  for  she  fears  that 
even  when  "  top  full  of  direst  cruelty  "  she  still  needs 
something  to  conceal  from  her  the  character  of  her 
own  act. 

"  Come,  thick  night. 
And  pall  thee  in  the  dunnest  smoke  of  hell 
That  my  keen  knife  sec  not  the  wound  it  makes 
Nor  heaven  peep  through  the  blanket  of  the  dark 
To  cry— hold,  hold  !  " 


228  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

From  these  illustrations  we  can  understand  how, 
though  the  will  must  wish  the  "  good,"  it  can  yet  do 
evil  deeds,  and  be  responsible  for  the  evil  of  thern.  It 
can  do  evil  deeds,  because  "  it  is  in  the  power  of  the  will 
to  direct  the  reason  actually  to  consider  or  cease  from 
considering,"  and  it  is  responsible  for  its  evil  deeds 
because  "  this  lack  of  due  regard  is  voluntar}^" 

{d)  Corollaries 

(i)  There  is  no  force  in  the  suggestion  of  Sidgwick 
that,  unless  a  man  finds  in  his  consciousness  this  cate- 
gorical necessity,  it  is  impossible  to  bring  home  the 
idea,  either  by  proving  the  existence  of  duty  or  in  an}^ 
other  wa}^  "  I  am  aware,"  he  writes  (Book  I.,  Chap.  3), 
"  that  some  persons  will  be  disposed  to  answer  all  the 
preceding  argument  by  a  simple  denial  that  they  can 
find  in  their  consciousness  any  such  unconditional  or 
categorical  imperative  as  I  have  been  trying  to  exhibit. 
If  this  is  really  the  final  result  of  self-examination  in 
any  case,  there  is  no  more  to  be  said.  I,  at  least,  do 
not  know  how  to  impart  the  notion  of  moral  obligation 
to  anyone  who  is  entirely  devoid  of  it."  * 

Sidgwick's  admission — "  I,  at  least,"  &c. — we  regard 
as  equivalent  to  the  suggestion  that  no  argument  could 
possibly  bring  home  the  idea  of  moral  obligation  to  one 
who  has  not  already  that  idea  in  his  mind — a  position 
which  practically  amounts  to  contending  that  the  idea 
of  moral  obligation,  if  it  exists  at  all,  must  be  innate. 
Now,  this  position  is  untenable.  For  no  argument  is 
vitiated  merely  because  its  conclusion  tells  us  something 
which  we  do  not  already  find  in  our  consciousness. 
The  principle  would  be  absurd.  For  instance,  could  we 
hold  that,  unless  a  man  finds  in  his  mind  the  idea  of 

•  Prof.  Paulsen  also  maintains  that  we  cannot  disprove  Ethical 
Nihilism — that  is,  that  if  a  man  declares  that  he  cannot  find  in  his 
consciousness  any  such  .sentiment  as  that  of  duty  or  moral  wrong,  it 
would  Ix;  impossible  to  prove  to  him  that  these  things  arc  existent 
realities  ("  System  of  Ethics,"  page  374). 


ON  DUTY  229 

tlie  dark  rays  of  the  spectrum,  he  is  free  to  reject  the 
proof  by  which  the  existence  of  these  rays  is  estabhshed  ? 
That  a  p'-oof  of  their  existence  should  be  necessary  is 
itself  a  pro  f  that  at  some  time  men  must  have  been 
without  the  idea  of  them,  and  we  have  already  shown 
that  a  proof  of  duty  is  also  necessary. 

(2)  Our  second  corollary  is  that  moral  duty  is  rssf;n- 
tially  dependent  upon  God,  and  cou/d  110/  cxisl  uulhout 
Hiin.  For  (a)  Dut\',  as  we  saw,  (hiHiuls  on  two 
necessities,  both  relating  to  the  last  end — namely,  the 
necessity  which  directs  the  will  absolutely  and  irresis- 
tibly to  the  last  end,  and  the  necessity  of  certain  means 
to  this  last  end.  But  God  is  our  last  end,  as  has  been 
proved  already.  Therefore,  duty  is  essentially  depen- 
dent on  God.  We  must,  therefore,  reject  the  theory 
of  Independent  Duty,  which  holds  that  duty  has  no 
ultimate  relation  to  and  dependence  on  God.  (6)  Again, 
the  natural  law  cannot  be  self-sustaining,  since,  like  the 
finite  things  in  which  it  is,  and  which  it  directs,  it  is 
itself  finite  and  dependent.  Hence  the  natural  law  of 
doing  moral  good  depends  intrinsically  on  that  higher 
law  of  God  from  which  all  other  law  proceeds — namely, 
the  Eternal  law,  the  law  existing  within  the  Divine 
intellect.  This  eternal  law  is,  as  we  shall  show  in  a 
later  chapter,  the  necessary  law  of  God's  own  nature, 
and  is,  in  fact,  one  with  His  nature,  (c)  God  cannot 
but  bind  His  creatures  to  the  following  of  His  law,  and 
hence,  in  violating  the  natural  law  of  doing  the  good, 
we  are  violating  His  precept  and  offending  against  His 
majesty.  It  is  this  personal  reference  to  the  Divine 
majesty  (which,  it  should  be  remembered,  attaches  to 
the  conception  of  duty  not  accidentally  but  necessarily 
and  essentially)  that  lends  to  duty  that  sense  of  personal 
compelling  power  and  of  sanctity  which  are  so  insepar- 
able from  it.  {d)  But  the  conception  of  Duty  has  a 
wider  and  a  fuller  content  still  than  that  of  majesty 
offended,  as  we  shall  now  see.  The  question  "  why 
ought  I  to  do  the  good  "   may  be  understood  in  a  two- 


230  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

fold  way.  First,  there  is  the  ethician's  question — What 
are  your  proofs  of  duty  ?  How  am  I  necessitated  in 
any  way  to  do  the  good  and  avoid  evil  when  I  know 
that  it  is  in  my  power  to  do  either  at  my  own  will  ? 
This  question  has  been  answered  in  what  precedes. 
Secondly,  there  is  the  plain  man's  question — What  if  I 
do  violate  duty  ?  What  then  ?  For  the  plain  man 
the  question  of  consequences  is  all  in  all.  For  the 
ethician,  if  he  is  sensible,  it  is  a  great  deal.  This  second 
question  we  can  only  answer  by  pointing  out,  as  before, 
that  if  we  transgress  the  natural  law  of  doing  the  good, 
we  violate  the  Divine  eternal  law,  and  that  the  Divine 
majesty  must  punish  us  for  its  violation.  For  it  cannot 
be  the  same  to  the  Divine  majesty  whether  we  regard 
or  disregard  the  Divine  law,  and,  therefore,  it  cannot 
be  the  same  with  us  whether  we  have  observed  or 
violated  it.  Every  legislator  must  vindicate  his  law, 
and  none  the  less  so  when  the  interests  which  it  involves 
are  eternal.  We  should  also  remark  that  it  would  not 
be  right  to  regard  these  consequences  as  accidental 
merely,  or  extrinsic  to  duty.  They  are  essential  and 
spring  from  its  very  nature.  From  this  aspect  of  the 
consequences  of  duty,  or  of  the  pain  that  attends  upon 
its  conscious  violation,  spring  both  the  fear  of  evil  and 
the  mind  to  do  good,  and  we  should  be  wanting  in  our 
duty  as  ethicians,  as  well  as  misleading  in  our  teaching, 
were  we  to  fail  to  take  account  of  it.  The  conception, 
therefore,  of  "  independent  duty  "  cannot  be  accepted 
either  as  true  or  as  an  adequate  account  of  duty. 

{e)  Some  other  Theories  of  Duty 

We  will  now  consider  other  theories  on  duty — its 
meaning  and  its  ground.  We  will  take  up  these 
theories  not  in  the  order  of  their  popularity,  but  in 
the  more  logical  order  of  the  degree  in  which  they  de- 
part from  that  objective  character  of  the  ground  and 
proof  of  duty  which  we  have  established  in  the  fore- 


ON  DUTY  231 

going  pages — that  is  to  say,  we  shall  take  them  in  a 
descending  scale  of  objectivity. 

(i)   Theory  that  duty  is  a  "  willing  thetotality  of  ends."^ 

This  theory  is  widely  taught  amongst  certain  schools 
of  modern  Ethicians,  yet  in  forms  that  vary  so  much 
that  a  common  expression  for  them  is  not  easy  to  find. 

We  shall,  therefore,  take  one  form — that  of  Dr.  Lipps 
in  "  Die  Ethischen  Grundfragen."  "  The  conscious- 
ness of  moral  duty  is  nothing  else,"  he  writes,  "  than 
.  .  .  the  consciousness  of  the  pure,  all-sided,  objectively- 
conditioned  will,"  *  This  "  all-sided,  objectively-con- 
ditioned will  "  he  explains  as  a  will  to  which  nothing 
is  wanting  which  has  a  significance  for  human  valuing 
and  willing.  In  other  words,  it  is  a  will  that  possesses 
all  that  any  man  can  set  a  value  on — a  will  that  pos- 
sesses the  totality  of  human  ends,  so  that  the  man  of 
duty  can  truly  say  "  alle  moglichen  menschlichen  Zwecke 
sind  in  mir  " — "  all  possible  (human)  ends  are  mine." 

Criticism — In  the  first  place,  it  might  be  thought  that 
this  theory  is  rather  a  theory  of  the  content  of  duty  than 
a  theory  of  duty  itself,  that  it  tells  us  rather  what  we 
ought  to  desire  than  what  the  ought  itself  is,  or  in  what 
the  ought  is  grounded.  But  this,  though  part  of  Dr. 
Lipps'  teaching,  is  not  his  whole  theory,  for  the  view 
just  quoted,  that  the  content  of  duty  includes  the 
totality  of  ends,  implies  another  and  more  fundamental 
theory  which  has  gained  a  wide  acceptance  amongst 
modern  Ethicians — the  theory,  namel}',  that  the  giound 
of  duty  or  moral  necessity  is  to  be  found  in  the  necessity 
which  compels  the  will  to  choose  out  its  objects  from 
amongst  the  totality  of  ends,  which,  therefore,  is  to  be 
regarded  as  the  adequate  and  all-inclusive  object  of 
the  will.  The  will  must  choose  amongst  the  totality  of 
ends.     This  "  must,"  we  are  told,  is  dut3^ 

But  this  theory  of  Dr.   Lipps  is   false  in  both  con- 
ceptions— (a)  that  of  the  content  of  duty,  and  {b)  that 
•  "  Die  Ethischen  Grundfragen,"  page  129. 


232  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of  its  grounds,  (a)  The  content  of  duty  cannot  be  the 
totality  of  ends,  since  there  are  some  ends  which  not 
only  are  not  a  part  of  our  duty  but  which  it  is  our  duty 
to  avoid.  These  are  bad  ends  which  no  man  may  seek. 
Again,  some  ends  are  possible  to  some  men  and  are  their 
duty,  whilst  they  are  impossible  to  others,  and  therefore 
cannot  be  their  duty.  Thus  the  ends  of  a  subject  are 
not  those  of  a  ruler.  The  ends  of  a  father  and  husband 
are  not  those  of  the  son.  The  father  must  seek  the 
means  of  sustenance  for  his  family.  Young  children 
cannot  do  so.  Some  ends,  again,  are  possible  to  all, 
but  they  are  not  the  duty  of  any.  Thus,  though  every 
man  is  bound  to  eat,  no  man  is  bound  to  eat  this  food 
or  that.  Our  duty  extends  to  necessities  merely. 
Hence  the  content  of  duty  is  not  the  totality  of  ends. 

{b)  Neither  is  the  totality  of  ends  the  ground  of  duty. 
For  duty  is  the  necessity  of  seeking  good  ends  only 
and  of  avoiding  evil  ends.  But  the  necessity  of  choos- 
ing our  objects  from  out  of  the  totality  of  ends  is  not  a 
necessity  of  doing  the  good,  but  of  seeking  out  any 
object  good  or  bad,  provided  only  it  be  included  in 
the  totality  of  ends.  The  necessity,  therefore,  which 
the  totality  of  ends  imposes  on  the  will  cannot  be  the 
ground  of  duty. 

To  some  extent,  however.  Dr.  Lipps'  theory  presents 
an  analogy  to  that  which  we  have  adopted  from  St. 
Thomas  Aquinas — that  the  end  of  man  is  the  perfect 
good.  For  since  duty  is  grounded  in  our  wish  for  the 
perfect  good,  and  since  in  the  perfect  good  is  contained 
all  possible  good,  therefore,  duty  might  be  described  as 
the  necessity  of  doing  that  which  will  lead  to  the  totality 
of  all  ends.  But  still  our  theory  could  not  be  con- 
founded with  the  theory  defended  by  Dr.  Lipps.*     For 

•  The  reader  can  also  trace  analogies  between  the  theory  of  M. 
Guyau,  to  be  dcscrilK'd  later,  and  that  of  St.  Thomas  on  the  nature  of 
obligation.  We  do  not  know  of  any  theory  of  duty  (except  the  positi- 
vistic  theory,  which  is  simply  a  denial  of  duty)  which  might  not  be 
described  as  in  some  way  a  reflection  of  one  point  or  anotlier  in  St. 
Thomas'  exposition. 


ON  DUTY  233 

duty  in  our  theory  is  the  necessity  of  desiring  not  the 
final  end  but  the  means  that  lead  to  it,  whereas  the 
analogy  referred  to  lies  between  the  totality  of  ends 
and  the  final  end  itself.  Again,  duty  in  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas'  theory  extends  only  to  such  means  as  are 
necessary  to  our  final  end.  It  does  not  extend  to  the 
totality  of  ends.  In  Dr.  Lipps'  theory  it  extends  to 
the  totality  of  ends.  Again,  duty  in  our  theory  is 
grounded  on  the  necessity  with  which  the  will  desires 
not  all  ends,  but  only  the  final  end,  in  which  end  is 
contained  virtualiter  et  eminenter  all  that  any  being  can 
desire.  In  Dr.  Lipps'  theory  duty  is  grounded  in  the 
totality  of  actual  ends. 

To  our  argument  that  in  Dr.  Lipps'  theory  every 
action  should  be  accounted  good,  and  that  hence  his 
theory  cannot  be  regarded  as  a  proper  ethical  account 
of  duty,  there  is  one  possible  reply.  In  the  chapter  of 
the  "  Ethischen  Grundfragen  "  which  precedes  that  on 
Duty,  Dr.  Lipps  speaks  of  the  good  desire  as  th.it  which 
belongs  not  to  man  as  an  individual  but  to  man  as  man. 
Therefore,  it  may  be  said  that  by  "  wilUng  the  totality 
of  all  men's  desires  "  is  only  meant  the  willing  of  those 
things  which  all  men  desire  not  as  individuals  but  as 
men  ;  in  other  words,  those  things  which  all  men  desire 
in  common.  But  this  interpretation  only  widens  the 
breach  between  Dr.  Lipps'  theory  and  ours.  For  it 
excludes  from  the  content  of  duty  many  ends  which 
are  proper  to  certain  men  but  which  it  is  their  bounden 
duty  to  attain.  If,  then,  by  "  alle  moglichen  Men- 
schlichen  Zwecke "  we  are  to  understand  all  human 
desires,  we  put  upon  the  individual  duties  which  cer- 
tainly do  not  belong  to  him.  If  by  it  is  meant  the  ends 
which  all  men  seek  in  common,  we  exclude  duties  which 
certainly  are  binding  on  individual  men.  The  theory, 
therefore,  of  duty  as  the  totahty  of  human  ends  is  untrue 
in  any  case. 


234  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(2)  The  disjunctive  theory. 

We  have  seen  that  duty  is  the  categorical  necessity  of 
taking  such  neans  as  are  neceaeaty  for  the  attaining  of 
the  final  end.  Professor  Meyer,  on  the  contrary,  in  his 
"  Grundsatze,"  gives  expression  to  the  pecuKar  theory 
that  duty  is  a  disjunctive,  not  a  categorical  necessity, 
that  its  formula  is  either — or  (entweder-oder),  meaning 
that  a  man  must  either  do  certain  actions  or  bear  the 
consequences  in  the  way  of  punishment — either  do  the 
right  or  suffer  the  punishment  of  wrong-doing. 

Criticism — Now,  this  theory  contradicts  the  most 
essential  element  in  moral  duty — nameh',  its  absolute 
or  categorical  nature.  My  dut}-  towards  the  truth  is  not 
expressed  in  the  formula — "  Either  tell  it  or  suffer." 
My  duty  is  simply  and  solely  to  tell  the  truth,  for  this 
is  the  only  alternative  that  fulfils  the  law.  The  other 
alternative — that  is,  the  undergoing  of  punishment — not 
only  does  not  fulfil  the  law  but  actually  presupposes 
that  the  law  has  been  already  broken.  But  that  which 
presupposes  duty  violated  cannot  be  regarded  as  a  ful- 
filment of  duty.  Hence  duty  is  not  the  fulfilment  of 
either  alternative,  but  of  one  only.  I  fulfil  the  law  only 
when  I  observe  it,  not  when  I  undergo  punishment  for 
not  observing  it.  Duty,  therefore,  is  not  a  disjunctive 
necessity. 

(3)  Theory  of  Psychological  Intuitionism. 
Psychological    Intuitionism    means    that    we    believe 

duty  to  be  a  reality  because,  on  examining  our  own 
selves,  we  find  that  there  is  within  us  something  which 
corresponds  to  our  notion  of  duty,  or  is  an  indication  of 
itp  presence — namely,  a  natural  submission  to  law,  a 
shrinking  before  law,  a  natural  hurraing  away  from 
certain  deeds  as  from  things  that  a  man  should  avoid, 
and  a  natural  going  out  to  others  as  to  things  a  man 
ought  to  do,  with  feelings  in  the  one  case  of  aversion, 
and  in  the  other  of  approbation'.  Now,  these  pheno- 
mena, we  are  told,  are  nothing  more  than  the  effects 


ON  DUTY  235 

and  signs  of  duty,  things  inexplicable  save  as  the  natural 
accompaniments  of  duty,  and  through  them  we  have  an 
immediate  knowledge  of  ourselves  as  subject  to  duty. 

Intuitionism  is  the  theory  of  Butler,  Kant,  Fichte, 
and  Schelling.  We  should,  however,  explain  that  Kant, 
Fichte,  and  Schelling,  besides  professing  to  possess  an 
immediate  introspective  intuition  of  duty  and  law,  claim 
in  addition  that  for  purposes  of  science  it  is  necessary 
to  deduce  the  existence  of  duty  from  some  deeper 
metaphysical  ground,  like  the  ego  or  the  will — otherwise 
it  could  not  be  regarded  as  a  scientific  fact  or  a  fact  of 
philosophy.  They  nevertheless  admit  that  the  intro- 
spective act  comes  first,  that  even  before  a  man  attempts 
the  deduction  of  duty  he  has  but  to  turn  his  mind  in 
on  himself  in  order  to  find  duty  asserting  itself  within 
his  mind,  and  claiming  from  him  notice  and  assent. 
Psychologically,  according  to  these  philosophers,  duty 
is  self-evident  ;  but  as  scientific  men  they  claim  that 
we  must  seek  to  ground  duty  upon  a  deeper  metaphysical 
basis  than  mere  intuition.  The  only  question,  however, 
that    now   concerns    us   is    whether   mere   psychological 

r  intuition  is  a  sufficient  ground  for  our  believing  in  the 
existence  of  duty. 

One  or  two  expressions  of  this  theory  will  help  to 
make   it   clear.     But   before   quoting   them   we   should 
remark    that    to    the    Psychological    Intuitionists    the 
problem  of  the  existence  of  duty  is  not  a  different  pro- 
blem from  that  of  the  existence  of  a  conscience  or  a 
/     I    moral  nature  in  man.     Their  claim  is  that  if  they  can 
iS-     discover   that   man   is   naturally   directed   by   a   moral 
Y       conscience,   they   shall  have  proved   that   man  is   also 
^      subject    to   duty,    which    is    submission   to   conscience. 
Hence,  in  these  passages  that  follow,  any  reference  to 
conscience  or  a  moral  nature  may  always  be  regarded 
as  including  a  reference  to  duty. 
\       "  Every  man,"  writes  Kant,   "  has  a  conscience  and 
finds    himself    observed    by    an    inward    judge,    which 
threatens  and  keeps  him  in  awe  ;    and  this  power  .  .  . 


^ 


236  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

j  follows  him  like  a  shadow  when  he  thinks  to  escape. 
He  may,  indeed,  stupify  himself  with  pleasures  and 
distractions,  but  cannot  avoid  now  and  then  coming  to 
himself  or  awaking,  and  then  he  at  once  perceives  its 
awful  voice.  .  .  .  This  original  intellectual  and  (as  a 
conception  of  duty)  moral  capacity  called  conscience 
has  this  peculiarity  in  it  that  although  its  business  is  a 
business  of  man  with  himself,  yet  he  finds  himself  com- 
pelled by  his  reason  to  transact  it  as  if  at  the  command 
of  another  person."  * 

Fichte  writes  : — "  When  that  impulsion  (namely,  our 
moral  nature  impelling  us  to  certain  acts)  is  discovered 
by  him  {i.e.,  any  man)  in  his  self-observation  as  a  fact, 
and  it  certainly  is  assumed  that  each  rational  being  will 
thus  discover  it,  if  he  but  closely  observe  himself,  man 
may  simply  accept  it  as  such  fact  .  .  .  without  en- 
quiring from  what  grounds  it  becomes  thus.  Perhaps 
he  may  fully  resolve  to  place  unconditioned  faith  in 
the  requirements  of  that  compulsion."  f 

The  following  brief  and  clear  statement  of  the  theory 
taken  from  a  French  writer  %  will  be  useful  : — "  II  y  a 
d'abord  I'evidence  interieure,  I'oracle  de  la  Conscience, 
qui  n'admet  pas  de  replique  ni  d'hesitation ;  nous 
sentons  le  devoir  parler  en  nous  comme  avec  une  voix, 
nous  croj^ons  au  devoir  comme  a  quelque  chose  qui  vit, 
qui  palpite  en  nous,  comme  a  une  partie  de  nousmemes, 
bien  plus  comme  a  ce  qu'il  y  a  en  nous  de  meilleur." 

Criticism — ^We  shall  discuss  two  questions  : — 

(i)  Are  there  such  moral  impulses  or  such  voices  in 
man  r.s  those  referred  to  by  the  Psychological  Intui- 
tionists  ? 

(2)  Even  if  there  are,  what  is  their  binding  force  ? 

(i)  I  cannot  find  in  my  own  mind  any  trace  of  these 
impulses  or  of  a  voice  commanding  me  to  do  certain 
actions  such  as  that  of  which  those  Intuitionists  speak. 

•  "  MetaphyHiciil  Elements  of  Ethics  "  (Abbot),  page  321. 

t  "  Science  of  Ethics,"  page  17. 

j  Guyau's  "  Esquissc  d'unc  Morale,"  &c.,  page  66. 


ON  DUTY  237 

I  find  within  myself  a  reaaoned  judgment  that  I  ought 
to  do  certain  acts,  and  that  reasoned  judgment  naturally 
impels  me  to  those  actions  just  as  the  judgment  that  I 
ought  to  save  up  money  if  I  want  to  be  secure  in  my  old 
age  impels  me  to  save  money.     But  this  is  very   far 
indeed  from  the  impulses  and  the  voice  spoken  of  by 
the   Psychological    Intuitionists.     For    (a)    the   voice   of 
conscience  is  described  by  many  of  these  Philosophers 
as  a  voice  naturally  superior  to  me  and  commanding  me 
through  a  part  of  me  and  within  me.     But  the  reasoned 
judgment  which  I  find  within  my  own  mind  and  which 
is  the  only  trace  I  can  find  of  a  voice  of  duty  is  my  own 
judgment,  elicited  by  myself,  and,  therefore,  not  superior 
to  me.     {h)  Also  the  impulse  of  duty  spoken  of  by  the 
Psychological  Intuitionists  is  an  impulse  which  is  born 
with  us  and  arises  out  of  the  very  nature  of  man,  whereas 
the  impulse  of  duty  which  I  am  conscious  of  is  nothing 
more  than  an  acquired  rational  conviction,  not  innate  in 
any  sense,   but   the  product  partly  of  instruction   and 
partly  of  our  own  personal  reasoning,     (c)  Again,  these 
impulses    and    voices    described    by    the    Psychological 
Intuitionists  are  unlike  anything  else  in  our  mental  life, 
they  are  sui  generis,   different   from   our  reason  itself, 
whereas  the  conviction  of  duty  that  we  are  conscious 
of  is  a  common  judgment,  and  as  a  mental  act  it  is 
similar  to   a   thousand   other  judgments,   and   different 
only   from   them  in  the  subject-matter  to  which  they 
severall}'    refer,     {d)  Again,    according    to    the    Psycho- 
logical Intuitionists,  to  violate  duty  is  to  offend  against 
an   inner   tribunal,    to   which   I   am   responsible   and   of 
which  I   am   afraid.     But  my  consciousness  reveals  to 
me  no  such  inner  tribunal  and  no  sense  of  responsibility 
to  it  or  of  fear  of  its  judgments.     When  I  violate  duty 
I  know  that  I  have  violated  the  law  of  a  legislator  who 
is  outside  me  and  to  whom  I  shall  have  to  render  an 
account    of   my   action.     We   cannot,    therefore,    accept 
this  theory  that  our  intuitive  consciousness  makes  duty 
known    to    us    immediately    and    directly    and    without 


238  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

reasoning  of  any  sort  in  the  same  way  that  we  become 
aware  of  our  ordinary  acts  of  tliinking,  feehng,  speaking. 

We  should,  however,  warn  the  reader  that  when  we 
call  in  question  the  existence  of  any  such  inner  voice  of 
duty  as  that  spoken  of  by  the  Intuitionists,  it  is  no  part 
of  our  theory  to  deny  Conscience  itself  or  the  fact  that 
Conscience  is  the  Voice  of  God  in  the  sense  of  truly 
representing  His  Law  and  Will  in  our  regard.  What 
we  deny  is  the  existence  of  an  inner  voice  distinct  from 
our  own  judgments  and  superior  to  ourselves,  yet  part 
of  us  and  claiming  submission  from  us  on  its  own  ac- 
count, and  not  as  merely  representing  the  law  of  a 
Personal  Divinity  'outside  of  and  above  us.  With  this 
understanding  we  go  on  to  our  second  point,  which  is 
as  follows  : — 

(2)  Even  if  there  were  in  man  a  voice,  a  feeling,  an 
impulsion  such  as  the  Intuitionists  describe,  urging  him 
to  shrink,  to  bend  before  an  inner  tribunal,  would  man 
be  bound  to  shrink  before  such  a  voice  or  feeling  ?  Is 
he  bound  to  acknowledge  in  any  way  the  binding  force 
of  those  inner  feelings  ?  In  other  words,  are  those 
feelings  a  legitimate  and  valid  authority  ?  Why  should 
we  submit  to  their  guidance  ?  Our  repl}'  is  that  even 
if  we  admit  their  existence  there  is  nothing— either  fact 
of  sense  or  analytic  truth — to  inform  us  of  the  authority 
of  these  voices  and  feelings.  FeeHngs,  inner  voices,  and 
such  things  can  rarely  if  ever  be  accepted  as  guides  to 
truth,  and  the  voice  that  announces  itself  as  the  Voice 
of  God  within  us  is  not  likely  to  be  a  better  guide  than 
any  other  inner  voice  or  feeling.  We  have,  therefore, 
as  already  explained,  a  right  to  ask — Whence  is  this 
voice  ?  What  guarantee  lias  it  that  It  is  what  it  declares 
itself  to  be  ?     How  does  it  justify  its  ckiims  ? 

These  questions  some  Psychological  Ethicians  regard 
as  unholy.  "  I  would  not,"  writes  Herbert,*  "  profane 
the  sacred  Temple  of  the  Practical  Reason  by  asking 
authorisation    from    the    '  Sittliche    Ideen '    (the    Moral 

•  "  Allgemcinc  Practischc  Philosophic  "  (chap.  I.). 


ON  DUTY  239 

Ideas)  dwelling  therein."  And  Beneke  *  claims  that 
we  cannot  call  in  question  the  "  note  of  necessity  "  that 
accompanies  the  good  act — it  belongs  to  the  "deepest 
ground-nature  of  the  human  soul." 

Such  fears  and  such  exaggerated  reverence  will  not 
provide  this  inner  tribunal  with  the  credentials  or  proofs 
of  its  authority  which  no  tribunal  can  afford  to  dispense 
with.  For  if  the  inner  tribunal  of  law  and  duty  of 
which  these  philosophers  speak  has  real  authority  over 
us  it  should  be  able  to  justify  its  authority.  If  it  re- 
fuses to  do  so  it  is  plain  that  it  has  no  authority — that 
it  is  nothing  more  than  mere  subjective  fancy.  It  is 
then  a  fair  target  for  the  jest  of  P.  Ree.f  who,  in  attack- 
ing Conscience  theories  in  general,  has  chiefly  before  his 
mind's  eye  a  sort  of  Conscience  like  that  of  the  Psycho- 
logical Intuitionists.  He  amusingly  compares  Con- 
science to  Lohengrin,  and  describes  it  as  remaining 
only  as  long  as  we  ask  not  whence  it  is,  but  flying  when 
we  ask  that  question. 
I  We  cannot,  then,  accept  the  theory  that  duty  is 
/  revealed  to  us  in  our  inner  consciousness  intuitively. 
We  know  it  as  we  know  other  intellectual  truths — by 
[  reasoning  and  instruction.  + 

•  "  Grundlinien." 

t  "  Entstehung  des  Gewissens,"  page  229. 

J  We  have  not  space  in  these  pages  to  notice  at  any  length  a  recent 
modification  of  the  Psychological  Intuitionist  Theory  known  as  "  Morale 
Criticiste  "  or  "  Phenomenal  Criticism  "  or  "  Morale  de  la  foi,"  which 
has  been  developed  by  certain  members  of  the  Nco- Kantian  school, 
notably  M.  Renouvier  and  M.  Secretan,  and  which  tends  more  even 
than  the  theory  we  have  just  criticised  to  exclude  the  possibility  of  a 
Science  of  Ethics. 

The  principal  points  in  these  Neo-Kantian  theories,  which  differ  a 
good  deal  from  one  another  (an  account  of  some  of  them  is  to  be  found 
in  M.  Guyau's  "  Esquisse  d'une  Morale  sans  obligation,"  page  62,  and 
in  M.  Fouillee's  "  Critique  des  Systemes  de  Morale  Contempo rains," 
page  77)  are  that  duty  is  to  be  regarded  as  belonging  solely  to  the 
phenomenal  world  ;  that  duty  is  a  simple  and  irreducible  phenomenon  ; 
that  we  believe  in  it  because  it  is  our  duty  to  believe  in  it  {"  je  ne  suis 
pas  logiquement  oblige  de  croire  au  devoir  ;  mais  j'y  suis  tenu  morale- 
ment.  Je  raffirme  et  je  passe,"  writes  M.  Ch.  Secretan  in  "  Le 
principle  de  la  Morale,"  page  128)  ;  that  we  do  not  need  proof,  there- 
fore, of  the  existence  of  duty,  belief  being  prior  to  proof.  The  theory 
is  an  evident  development  of  the  Kantian  Ethics. 


240  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

{4)  Positivistic  theory  of  duty. 
Moral  Positivism  has  many  forms,  all  of  which  have 
this  common  element,  that  they  regard  Duty  as  nothing 
more  than  a  subjective  feeling,  which  corresponds  to 
nothing  in  the  objective  world.  Our  sense  of  duty,  this 
theory  explains,  2S__nierely_  an  illusion,  which  has  been 
brought  about  in  our  minds  by  tKose  most  fruitful 
sources  of  error  and  illusion — the  laws  of  association. 
How  the  feeling  of  duty  arises  under  the  influence  of 
these  laws  is  explained  by  the  Positivists  as  follows  :— 
Duty  is  simply  a  feeling  that  something  is  necessary  or 
should  be  done.  This  feeling  of  duty  originated  tn~the' 
feeling  of  external  constraint  connected  with  certain 
acts — those  acts,  namely,  which  were  once  enforced  by 
tribal  laws  or  laws  of  State,  and  the  violation  of  which 
was  accompanied  by  punishment,  and  therefore  by  pain. 
The  necessity  of  doing  such  acts  was  a  hypothetical  or 
disjunctive  necessity — the  necessity,  namely,  either  of 
obeying  or  of  undergoing  punishment,  which,  according 
to  the  Positivists,  is  the  only  original  kind  of  necessity 
attaching  to  action. 

Gradually,  however,  they  explain,  this  hypothetical 
necessity  became  changed  into  categorical  necessity. 
The  "  or  undergo  punishment  "  disappeared  from 
memory  ;  and  from  the  feeling  that  acts  should  be 
done  in  order  to  avoid  punishment  men's  minds  passed, 
under  the  influence  of  the  laws  of  association,  to  neglect 
the  condition  or  the  disjunction,  and  to  regard  these 
same  acts  as  necessary  in  themselves — as  things  that 
should  be  done  on  their  own  account.  This  feeling  that 
acts  are  necessary  categorically  and  on  their  own  ac- 
count is,  it  is  explained,  our  feeling  of  moral  duty. 

Thus,  Spencer  writes  :  *  "  Thinking  of  the  extrinsic 
effects  of  a  forbidden  act  (that  is,  the  punishment  im- 

•  "  Data  of  Ethics,"  page  127.  Spencer  also  claims  that  the 
consciousness  of  the  sujxjriority  of  some  feelings  over  others — the 
consciousness,  namely,  that  some  feelings  arc  meant  as  guides  for 
others — has  a  good  deal  to  do  with  the  formation  of  the  abstract  con- 
ception of  duty. 


ON  DUTY  241 

posed  by  positive  laws)  excites  a  dread  which  continues 
present  while  the  intrinsic  effects  of  the  act  (that  is, 
the  natural  effects  of  the  act  itself)  are  thought  of,  and 
being  thus  linked  with  the  intrinsic  effects  causes  a 
vague  sense  of  moral  compulsion  " 

And  Bain  *  writes  : — "By  a  familiar  effect  of  con- 
tiguous association  the  dread  of  punishment  clothes  the 
forbidden  act  with  a  feeling  of  aversion  which  in  the  end 
persists  of  its  own  accord,  and  without  reference  to 
punishment.  Actions  that  have  long  been  connected 
in  the  mind  with  pains  and  penalties  come  to  be  con- 
templated with  a  disinterested  repugnance.  They  seem 
to  give  pain  on  their  own  account.  .  .  .  Now,  when  by 
such  transference  a  self-subsisting  sentiment  of  aversion 
has  been  created,  the  conscience  seems  to  be  detached 
from  all  external  sanctions  and  to  possess  an  isolated 
footing  in  the  mind.  It  has  passed  through  the  stage 
of  reference  to  authority  and  has  become  a  law  to 
itself.  .  .  .  There  is  no  act,  however  trivial,  that 
cannot  be  raised  to  the  position  of  a  moral  act  by  the 
imperative  of  Society." 


THE   TWO   FORMS   OF  THE   POSITIVISTIC   THEORY 

We  must  now  distinguish  between  two  prominent 
forms  of  this  Positivistic  theory  of  duty,  which  differ 
greatly  in  regard  to  the  forces  to  which  they  make 
appeal  in  order  to  explain  the  origin  of  our  conception 
or  feeling  of  duty.  These  two  forms  are  distinguished 
as  (a)  the  simple  Association,  and  (&)  the  Evolutionist 
theory  of  duty. 

{a)  The  simple  Association  theory,  represented  by 
Mill,  explains  the  transformation  of  the  feeling  of  hypo- 
thetical necessity  into  the  feeling  of  categorical  necessity 
or  of  duty  by  laws  of  Association  only.  As  children, 
it  informs  us,  we  feel  that  certain  actions  are  necessary 

♦  "  Moral  Science,"  page  457 
Vol.  I— 16 


242  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

in  order  to  avoid  punishment.  The  feeling  of  necessity 
is  one  of  fear  of  external  authority.  Later  on,  this  end 
or  condition,  the  avoiding  of  punishment,  drops  out  of 
sight,  and  then  we  believe  that  these  actions  are  neces- 
sary on  their  own  account. 

(6)  Evolutionists  (Spencer,  Darwin,  Professor  Simmel, 
Professor  Wundt),  whilst  acknowledging  the  influence 
of  the  laws  of  Association,  still  regard  these  laws  as 
inadequate  of  themselves  to  explain  the  conception  of 
duty,  and  they,  therefore,  supplement  the  Associationist 
theory  by  considerations  of  Evolution. 

The  supplementary  factors  invoked  by  the  Evolu- 
tionists in  explanation  of  "  duty  "  are  principally  two- 
fold :— 

First,  they  make  appeal  to  the  law  of  heredity,  and 
claim  that  the  process  which  has  resulted  in  our  present 
feeling  of  duty  began,  not  in  the  childhood  of  each 
individual,  but  in  distant  ages  long  ago  when  man  first 
began  to  rule  his  fellowmen  by  means  of  laws  and 
commands,  and  the  dread  of  punishments.  It  is  the 
feelings  of  external  compulsion  and  of  fear  thus  gene- 
rated, and  accumulated  and  consolidated  during  that 
long  period,  and  transmitted  by  heredity  from  one  age 
to  another,  and  moulded  within  the  consciousness  of  the 
race  under  the  laws  of  Association  into  newer  and  newer 
forms  at  each  period,  that  have,  according  to  the  Evolu- 
tionist Ethicians,  become  transformed  into  our  present 
conception  of  moral  necessity  or  obligation. 

Secondly,  they  also  claim  to  show  how  the  mere  fear  * 

*  Evolutionists  are  not  all  agreed  as  to  the  manner  in  which  the 
transmitted  feelings  become  associated  so  as  to  form  the  fcclinn  of 
duty,  nor  do  they  agree  as  to  what  feelings  arc  involved  in  its  forma- 
tion. We  may  take  the  views  defended  by  Prof.  Taylor  in  his  "  Problem 
of  Conduct  "  and  by  Prof.  Paulsen  in  his  "  System  of  Ethics  "  as  ex- 
amples of  this  divergency.  The  evolutionary  process,  Prof.  Taylor  tells 
us,  begins  with  the  feeling  of  dissatisfaction  with  our  own  act — for 
instance,  the  discontented  feeling  of  the  Australian  whose  boomerang 
has  failed  to  bring  down  a  duck.  This  feeling,  however,  is  not  itself 
a  feeling  of  duty.  Duty  first  appears  when  personal  dissatisfaction 
becomes  transformed  into,  or  is  sup])lcmi'nt<'(l  bv,  tril)ril  (hssntiafddion. 
Then  comet  the  r$ligious  period,  in  which  our  imayinatious  nprisent 


ON  DUTY  243 

of  external  authority  (which,  according  to  Mill,  suffi- 
ciently explains  our  feeling  of  duty,  but  which,  accord- 
ing to  the  Evolutionists  is  not  sufficient,  since  duty  is 
felt  to  be  not  only  a  categorical  necessity,  but  also  a 
categorical  necessity  laid  upon  us  from  within  ourselves) 
becomes  transformed  into  a  feeling  of  internal  authority, 
and  thus  produces  in  ourselves  what  is  known  as  the 
feeling  of  autonomy.  This  feeling  of  internal  authority 
has  its  beginnings,  according  to  some  writers,  in  the 
felt  superiority  of  the  more  highly  evolved  over  the 
less  evolved  impulses  within  us.  Others  explain  how 
under  the  influence  of  heredity  the  feelings  of  the 
whole  race  come  to  be  transmitted  to  and  consolidated 
in  each  individual  man,  so  that  the  individual  becomes 
a  microcosm  of  humanity  or  of  the  State,  and  the  law 
and  authority  of  the  State  are  thus  felt  within  himself 
as  if  belonging  to  himself.  From  this  arises  the  feeling 
of  self-rule  or  of  autonomy. 

In  all  these  theories,  however,  the  original  factor  out 
of  which  the  feeling  of  duty  is  said  to  be  evolved  is  that 
of  external  compulsion.  Dread  and  compulsion  are  thus 
the  working  factors — time  and  inheritance  the  con- 
ditions under  which,  in  the  Evolutionary  theory,  our 
f eeUngs  of  coerciveness  grow  into  that  of  mora )  duty. 

the  Deity  as  punishing  for  offences  against  the  tribal  will,  and  then  as 
punishing  our  secret  actions  on  their  own  account.  It  is  religion,  he 
says,  that  has  "  substituted  an  inward  morality  of  character  and 
intention  for  a  legalistic  morality  of  outward  performance  "  (page  142). 
The  last  or  purely  ethical  stage  is  reached  when  this  conception  of  ex- 
ternal law-giver  and  outward  sanction  gives  place  to  that  of  internal 
law-giver  and  inward  sanction— a  transformation  which  easily  becomes 
possible  as  soon  as  the  tribal  religion  comes  to  be  regarded  as  a  part  only 
of  the  Universal  religion.  For  then  we  see  that  there  are  bad  acts 
which  yet  are  not  forbidden  by  our  tribal  religion,  and  in  that  way 
the  conception  of  a  personal  law-giver  gives  way  gradually  to  the 
conception  of  impersonal  prohibition,  which  ultimately  takes  the 
form  of  a  prohibition  arising  out  of  the  nature  of  the  act  itself. 

Prof.  Paulsen  asserts  that  the  feeling  of  duty  arises  from  the  re- 
action that  we  feel  when  custom  is  violated — a  reaction  that  reveals 
itself  as  the  authoritative  command  of,  or  as  punishment  inflicted  by, 
parents,  people,  and  gods,  whom  we  regard  as  the  custodians  of  the 
world's  customs.  The  feeling  of  duty,  however,  is  an  evolutionary 
growth,  and  is  present  in  an  imperfect  form  in  animals  as  well  as  in 
men  (page  343). 


244  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

It  would  be  impossible  for  us  to  criticise  the  various 
forms  of  this  Positivist  theory  in  detail,  and  we  shall 
confine  ourselves  to  a  consideration  of  the  one  funda- 
mental principle  of  all  these  theories — the  principle, 
namely,  that  our  conception  of  moral  obligation  is  a 
growth  out  of  former  feelings  ol  compulsion  by  public 
authority,  whether  that  authority  be  felt  as  without 
or  within  the  mind,  and  whether  it  be  due  to  Evolu- 
tionary factors  or  to  mere  association. 

Criticism — {a)  The  positivist  theory  of  duty  is  only  a 
necessary  appendage  to  the  positivist  theory  of  "  good  " 
or  of  moral  distinctions,  and  stands  or  falls  with  that 
theory.  But  by  showing  that  there  are  in  man  natural 
appetites,  we  have  already  disproved  the  positivist 
theory  of  "  good."  Therefore,  their  theory  of  duty  is 
also  disproved,  at  least  indirectly. 

(6)  Having  once  proved,  as  we  claim  to  have  done  in 
this  chapter,  the  reality  of  duty,  the  question  of  the 
origin  of  our  idea  of  duty  can  be  answered  in  one  way 
only — namely,  that  our  idea  of  duty  arose  from  our 
perception  of  the  reality  of  duty  itself.  To  imagine 
intangible  and  unverifiable  hypotheses  such  as  those 
formulated  by  the  positivists  concerning  the  origin  of 
the  idea  of  duty,  when  duty  has  been  proved  to  be  a  reality 
would  be  like  forming  deep  metaphysical  hypotheses  to 
explain  the  existence  of  a  photograph  of  which  we 
know  the  original,  and  neglecting  the  simplest  explana- 
tion of  all — namely,  that  it  is  a  copy  of  and  represents 
the  original. 

(c)  Mere  association,  even  when  helped  on  by  heredity, 
cannot  force  our  intellects  into  beUeving  or  assenting  to 
any  proposition.  Association  may,  indeed,  create  cer- 
tain subjective  bonds  between  our  ideas,  but  it  can 
never  give  rise  to  judgment.  A  colour  and  a  perfume 
may  always  occur  together,  but  the  subjective  associa- 
tion that  thereby  arises  between  them  can  never  make 
UH  believe  that  one  is  the  other.  Consequently,  mere 
associations,    however    long-continued,    cannot    explain 


ON  DUTY  245 

our  belief  in  duty.  And  this  argument  is  strengthened 
by  the  consideration  that  whereas,  on  the  one  hand,  if 
the  Association  hypothesis  is  to  be  invoked  to  explain 
our  belief  in  duty,  we  should  be  satisfied  that  the  hypo- 
thesis is  not  itself  the  merest  imagination — that  is,  we 
should  be  satisfied  that  mere  association  has  actually 
given  rise  to  intellectual  beliefs  in  very  many  cases — on 
the  other  hand,  it  is  plain  that  associationsists  are  not 
able  to  point  to  a  single  indisputable  instance  in  which 
association  has  ever  given  rise  to  an  intellectual  belief. 
An  hypothesis  of  this  kind  should  not  be  purely 
imaginary.  Again,  even  if  an  association  could  become 
a  judgment,  the  mind  retains  always  the  power  of  re- 
turning upon  its  judgments,  of  examining  them,  and, 
if  they  be  not  capable  of  some  kind  of  rational  justi- 
fication, of  rejecting  them.  Yet  under  no  circumstances 
will  men  ever  come  to  reject  the  ordinary  principles  of 
natural  duty  such  as  that  it  is  a  duty  of  parents  to 
educate  their  offspring.  Hence  the  necessity  of  these 
judgments  is  not  due  to  association.  Neither  is  the 
conception  of  duty  in  general  due  to  association, 

{d)  Supposing  that  mere  external  compulsion  by  the 
State  could  generate  the  judgment  that  certain  acts  are 
intrinsically  necessary,  then  if  any  customs  like  the 
wearing  of  pig-tails  by  the  Chinese  were  to  become  a 
universal  law,  we  should  gradually  come  to  beheve  that 
such  things  were  intrinsically  a  duty,  and  that  non- 
conformity to  them  was  intrinsically  a  violation  of  duty, 
and  we  should  still  believe  it  was  a  violation  of  duty 
even  though  the  law  forbidding  it  were  to  be  repealed. 
Yet  this,  we  claim,  no  sensible  man  could  possibly 
believe.  For,  many  such  customs  have  prevailed 
amongst  men  for  a  very  long  time,  and  then  have 
fallen  into  disuse.  Yet  no  trace  survived  of  a  feeling, 
or  even  of  the  beginning  of  a  feeling,  that  they  were 
obligatory. 

[c)  Even  if  the  State  were  to  command  such  acts  as 
lying,   stealing,   and  blasphemy,   we  could  never  come 


246  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  regard  these  things  as  intrinsically  our  duty.  Hence 
extrinsic  compulsion  could  not  of  itself  give  rise  to  the 
idea  of  intrinsic  obligation. 

(/)  If  the  idea  of  obligation  be  wholly  due  to  State 
and  to  social  compulsion,  the  State  must  once  have 
formally  commanded  such  acts  as  the  care  of  offspring, 
marital  fidelity,  and  the  like.  Now,  if  the  State  did 
prescribe  such  courses  of  conduct  it  must  have  recog- 
nised the  necessity  of  these  courses.  For  the  State 
cannot  have  acted  at  random  in  the  past  any  more  than 
in  the  present.  But  the  duty  of  conduct  is  nothing 
more  than  the  necessity  of  it.  Hence  State  compulsion 
must  have  been  itself  built  upon  conceptions  of  duty. 
Consequently,  duty  does  not  originate  in  mere  external 
compulsion.  Also,  the  legislator  makes  laws  because 
he  is  persuaded  that  it  is  his  duty  to  secure  the  common 
good,  and  that  it  is  the  duty  of  the  people  to  obey  them. 
Legislation  then  supposes  duty. 

(g)  If  we  must  suppose  that  the  intellectual  concep- 
tion of  duty  has  grown  out  of  some  formerly  experienced 
necessity  it  is  much  easier  to  imagine  that  the  concep- 
tion of  duty  arose  out  of  our  experience  of  the  necessity 
of  objects  for  our  inner  appetites  than  from  the  neces- 
sity of  outer  compulsion.  For  the  feeling  of  duty,  like 
our  appetites,  is  intrinsic  not  extrinsic  to  man,  whereas 
compulsion  is  extrinsic.  Besides,  these  appetites  are 
older  than  the  laws  of  society — they  are  as  old  as  the 
individual  himself,  and  hence  the  feeling  of  duty  is  more 
likely  to  have  originated  with  appetite  than  in  the  feel- 
ing of  external  compulsion  by  society.  But  if  the  con- 
ception of  duty  arose  from  the  feeling  of  the  necessities 
of  certain  appetites  its  origin  accords  with  the  theory  of 
duty  which  we  have  sought  to  establish  in  the  present 
chapter. 

{h)  The  po8iti\i.st  theory  of  duty  is  built  on  the  sup- 
position that  tlicre  is  no  fmal  end  of  our  wills.  As  we 
showed  in  the  present  chapter,  many  positivists  have 
admitted  that  if  there  were  a  fmal  end  to  the  will,  the 


ON  DUTY  247 

series  of  hypothetical  necessities  would  become  a  cate- 
gorical series,  and  would  be  our  duty.  But  we  claim  to 
have  established  the  existence  of  this  final  end. 

{i)  Lastly,  we  might  argue  against  Posit  ivist 
Morality  on  the  ground  of  expediency.  If  at  any 
time  men  should  come  generally  to  believe  that  obli- 
gation is  mere  imagination,  that  there  is  nothing  in 
the  nature  of  things  that  corresponds  to  the  concep- 
tion of  obligation,  then  morals  must  decline,  and  the 
race  must  quickly  come  to  ruin.  Taking  man  as  he 
is,  even  at  his  best,  we  cannot,  as  Spencer  does,  look 
forward  to  a  time  when  man  will  not  need  the  con- 
ception of  obligation  in  order  to  do  good  deeds.  This 
being  the  case,  we  should  not  lightly  and  without 
sufficient  reason  accept  the  theory  of  Positivism. 

But  there  is  no  sufficient  reason  for  accepting  the 
theory  of  Positivism.  Positivism  is  grounded  on  no 
reasons,  no  proofs.  It  is  an  historical  theory  without 
historical  support  (the  conception  of  duty  is  certainly 
as  old  as  history)  ;  an  ethical  theory  without  ethical 
grounds  (its  one  aim  is  to  disprove  morality,  to  render 
it  meaningless,  to  show  that  it  has  sprung  out  of  error)  ; 
an  anthropological  theory,  which  yet  contradicts  all  that 
we  know  of  man  (the  parent  must  always  have  recog- 
nised that  he  has  a  natural  duty  to  his  children,  the 
citizen  that  it  is  his  natural  duty  to  support  the  State)  ; 
a  sociological .  theory  which  cuts  at  the  very  root  of 
society  (society  could  not  now  subsist  a  day,  nor  could 
it  have  subsisted  in  the  past  had  no  one  believed  he  had 
a  natural  duty  to  help  to  maintain  it).  For  these  reasons 
we  reject  the  positivi^tfc  conception  of  Duty. 

(5)   Theory  of  the  complete  and  formal  rejection  of  duty. 

M.  Guyau  has  formulated  a  theory  which  frankly  and 
completely  discards  "  Duty  "  without  retaining  even  the 
shadow  of  it  which  lingers  in  some  of  the  positivist 
theories.     The  title  of  his  book  in  which  the  subject  is 


248  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

discussed  will  leave  the  reader  in  no  doubt.  It  is 
"  Esquisse  d'une  Morale  sans  Obligation  ni  Sanction." 
The  theory  of  the  future,  he  says  in  his  preface,  is  not 
the  theory  of  "  autonomous  "  reason  biit  of  "  anomous  " 
reason. 

According  to  M.  Guyau  there  is  no  obligation,  no 
duty,  and  no  sanction.  But  he  admits  there  is  in  the 
life  of  man  a  certain  force  or  influence  which  acts  on 
man's  mental  faculties,  and  which  moves  his  will,  his 
intellect,  and  his  senses,  soliciting  or  persuading  them, 
saying  "  II  faut — ."  But  this  force  is  not  duty,  for 
there  is  no  such  thing  as  duty. 

What,  then,  are  these  various  things  which  can  move 
us  as  duty  would — ^that  play  the  part  of  duty,  or,  as 
M.  Guyau  says,  are  a  "  substitute  for  or  an  equivalent 
of  duty  "  ?  The  fundamental  principle  in  these  moving 
forces  is  "  life,"  for  life  is  the  cause  of  all  action.  It 
is  the  efficient  cause  of  all  imconscious  action  in  man 
and  the  final  cause  or  end  of  conscious  action.  Life  is 
the  necessary  object  of  every  desire,  and  it  is  that  which 
moves  us  to  every  act.  We  must  see  now  how  the 
movements  of  life  supply  us  with  equivalents  of  duty. 
"  Let  us  place  ourselves  successively,"  he  writes,  "  at 
the  three  points  of  view — ^that  of  the  will,  that  of  the 
intellect,  that  of  sense." 

1st.  For  the  will  this  equivalent  of  duty  is  superabun- 
dance of  life,  the  power  of  life  to  overflow  in  action,  the 
power  to  act.  (Existence  d'un  certain  devoir  imper- 
sonnel  cr66  par  la  pouvoir  memc  d'agir.  Premier  Equiv- 
alent du  devoir.)  "  Life  cannot  maintain  itself  except 
on  condition  of  expanding  itself,"  and  in  expanding  it 
produces  a  feeling  of  "  prcssion  interne,"  which  is  a 
feeling  of  inner  compulsion.  We  can  make  comparison 
with  the  plant  to  illustrate  life's  impulse  to  expand. 
The  plant  cannot  help  bursting  into  flower,  for  the 
general  tendency  of  life  is  "  Ever  onward,  ever  higher 
still."  The  same  impulse  of  life  has  given  to  the  will 
the  tendency  ever  to  expand,  which  is  our  capacity  for 


ON  DUTY  249 

action.  This  is  the  first  equivalent  of  duty.  As  regards 
the  necessity  of  acting  and  the  feehng  of  necessity  the 
"  pression  interne  "  explains  all  that  duty  explains. 

2nd.  How  does  the  intellect  tend  to  move  one  to 
action,  and  what,  therefore,  is  its  equivalent  for  duty  ? 
M.  Guyau  answers  : — Thought  and  act  are  really  one 
in  principle.  No  bridge  is  needed  to  pass  from  one  to* 
the  other.  All  ideas  are  force-ideas  (idees-forces).  That 
is  to  say,  the  idea  of  action  tends  to  pass  into  action 
and  supplies  the  intellect  with  the  needful  motor  power. 
The  Conception  itself,  therefore,  supplies  the  second 
equivalent  of  duty  (Existence  d'un  certain  devoir  imper- 
sonnel  cree  par  la  conception  meme  de  Taction.  Deux- 
ieme  equivalent  du  devoir). 

3rd.  What  equivalent  for  duty  is  possessed  by  sense  ? 
According  to  M.  Guyau,  sense  (sensibilite)  acquires  this 
equivalent  by  evolution — that  is,  by  its  tending  ever  to 
evolve  to  a  higher  and  more  complex  condition.  M. 
Guyau  tells  us  that  "  les  plaisirs  egoistes  "  are  on  a 
lower  plane  than  altruistic  pleasure — that  as  pleasures 
become  higher  they  become  less  egoistic  and  more 
altruistic — that  as  pleasure  becomes  more  complex  it 
becomes  more  sociable  and  further  removed  from  the 
pleasure  of  the  isolated  individual.  In  the  higher 
degree  of  evolution,  therefore,  the  sociability  of  pleasure 
becomes  an  essential  part  of  pleasure.  This  feeling  of 
tendency  towards  altruism  imposes  on  us  a  "  bond  " 
(lien)  which  is  the  third  equivalent  of  duty.  It  is  created 
by  "  la  fusion  croissante  des  sensibilites." 

In  a  brief  resumptive  paragraph  M.  Guyau  explains 
these  three  equivalents  of  duty.  "  Prendre  la  con- 
science de  devoirs  moraux,  c'est  prendre  la  conscience 
de  pouvoirs  interieurs  et  superieurs  qui  se  developpent 
en  nous,  et  nous  poussent  a  agir,  d'idees  qui  tendent  a 
se  realiser,  par  leur  force  propre,  de  sentiments  qui  par 
leur  evolution  meme  tendenf  a  se  socialiser,  a  s'empregner 
de  toute  la  sensibilite  presente  dans  I'humanite  et  dans 
I'univers." 


250  THE   SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Now,  all  these  forces  or  tendencies  to  action  beget  in 
us  instincts,  the  highest  of  which  is  the  altruistic; 
instinct. 

But  the  question  arises — Suppose  that  some  day  men 
should  ask  why  should  they  follow  these  instincts,  or 
why  may  they  not  do  what  they  wish,  what,  then,  will 
become  of  morality  ?  Moral  duty,  on  M.  Guyau's 
teaching,  does  not  exist,  consequently  we  cannot  answer 
that  men  ought  to  follow  these  instincts.  In  that  case 
is  there  anything  in  man  that  can  act  as  an  equiva- 
lent of  duty  and  save  morality  ?  According  to  M. 
Guyau  there  are  two  tendencies  in  man  which  can 
"  lutter  contre  la  dissolution  morale  et  suppleer  ainsi 
I'obligation  absolue  des  anciens  moralistes."  They  are 
the  following,  and  they  supply  the  fourth  and  fifth 
equivalents  of  duty  in  performing  the  function  usually 
attributed  to  duty  of  keeping  men  moral ;   namely  : — 

4th.  Equivalent  of  duty — the  pleasure  of  risk  and 
struggle  in  action.  Man  finds  pleasure  in  risk,  in 
danger,  in  struggle.  And  this  pleasure  is  grounded  in 
man's  "  besoin  de  se  sentir  grand,  d'avoir  par  instants 
conscience  de  la  sublimite  de  sa  volonte.  Cette  con- 
science 11  I'acquiert  dans  la  lutte,  lutte  contre  soi  et 
contre  ses  passions." 

This  equivalent  for  Duty,  therefore,  will  maintain 
morality  even  when  men  begin  to  ask  for  a  reason  why 
they  should  be  moral,  for  it  will  tend  to  lessen  the  force 
of  passion  and  to  maintain  self-control. 

5th.  Equivalent  for  duty  in  maintaining  morality— le 
risnue  m^taphysique — I'hypothcse,  "  risk  in  thought." 

This  is  man's  tendency — (a)  to  form  for  himself  an 
ideal  of  action,  an  ideal  which  is  purely  h3'pothetical 
and  unreal,  and  {h)  then  in  the  sphere  of  action  to  pro- 
duce this  ideal,  and  to  act  as  if  it  were  his  end,  when, 
as  a  matter  of  fact,  we  don't  know  that  it  is  our  end. 
This  risk  which  we  tend  to*  run  in  producing  an  ideal 
which  may  never  be,  tends  to  maintain  the  higher  life. 
"  J-a   vie   de   toutos    p.irts    est    enveloppi^c    d'inconnu. 


ON  DUTY  251 

Pourtant  j'agis,  je  travaille,  j'entreprends ;  et  dans 
toutes  mes  actes,  dans  toutes  mes  pensees,  je  presuppose 
cet  avenir  sur  lequel  rien  ne  m'autorise  a  compter,  je 
depense  mon  energie  sans  craindre  que  cette  depense 
soit  une  perte  seche.  Je  m'impose  des  privations  en 
comptant  que  I'avenir  les  rachetera,  je  vais  mon  chemin." 

These  five  equivalents  supply  the  place  of  duty.  The 
first  three  explain  everything  in  what  is  called  man's 
moral  nature — everything  that  is  explained  by  duty. 
The  last  two  supply  the  place  of  duty  in  securing  for 
man  control  over  the  passions  and  in  the  maintaining 
of  a  moral  ideal. 

Criticism — (a)  Our  first  point  of  criticism  is  that  if 
the  word  "  moral "  has  a  definite  meaning,  then  a 
moral  system  without  duty  (Une  Morale  sans  obliga- 
tion) is  an  impossible  conception.  For  a  moral  system, 
if  it  means  anything,  means  a  system  of  laws  binding 
on  human  beings  who  yet  are  free  to  obey  or  not  to 
obey  these  laws.  A  system  of  laws  which  binds  in  any 
other  way  than  this,  a  system  of  laws  which  must  be 
obeyed,  which  cannot  be  resisted,  is  a  physical  not  a 
moral  system.  Hence  the  necessity  that  obtains  in  a 
moral  system  must  be  a  necessity  of  obligation,  not  of 
physical  compulsion. 

[h)  If  the  only  necessity  that  moves  to  action  is  the 
inner  force  of  expansion  belonging  to  all  living  things, 
and  if  morals  be  only  the  necessity  resulting  from  this 
expansion,  then  the  movements  of  plants  and  animals 
are  subject  to  the  very  same  kind  of  necessity  that 
men  are  subject  to,  a  conclusion,  indeed,  wliich  M. 
Guyau  accepts,  but  which  we  believe  the  world  at  large 
will  not  accept.  For  it  is  absurd  to  speak  of  the  law 
that  impels  the  plant  to  grow  as  the  same  in  kind  which 
impels  a  man  to  help  the  poor.  The  laws  of  plants  are 
unconscious  necessities,  those  that  we  include  under 
"  Duty  "  are  conscious  necessities.  The  laws  of  plants, 
and  likewise  those  of  animals,  are  necessities  to  which 
they  are  impelled  independently  of  themselves — the  law 


252  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

which  impels  a  man  to  help  the  poor  is  a  necessity  to 
the  fulfilment  of  which  he  determines  himself. 

(c)  We  have  already  shown  that  man  is  ordained  by 
nature  to  a  definite  end,  and  also  that  duty  is  the  con- 
sequent necessity  laid  on  the  will  of  taking  the  means 
necessary  to  the  attainment  of  this  end.  There  is,  then, 
no  necessity  for  imagining  equivalents  for  duty.  Duty 
is  itself  a  demonstrable  fact  and  law,  and  admits  of  no 
equivalent. 

(d)  We  now  go  on  to  show  that  in  no  sense  can  we 
admit  these  five  equivalents  of  M.  Guyau  as  substitutes 
for  duty. 

(i)  Life,  its  overflow  and  expansion,  are  not  a  sub- 
stitute for  duty.  We  admit  a  fundamental  expansion 
of  the  will  to  good.  But  this  is  irresistible,  and  it  is 
not  duty  but  the  basis  of  duty.  For  besides  the  physical 
irresistible  necessity  which  moves  the  will  to  desire  good 
we  have  proved  the  existence  of  another  necessity  which 
physically  is  not  irresistible,  and  it  is  for  this  moral 
necessity  that  M.  Guyau  must  supply  a  substitute  if  he 
would  provide  equivalents  for  duty. 

Besides  the  expansion  of  the  will  to  good  we  admit 
also  the  existence  of  other  natural  expansions — those, 
namely,  of  the  other  appetites,  sensuous  and  rational ; 
but  these  are  not  an  equivalent  for  duty,  for  they  im- 
pose no  necessit}^  on  the  will,  and,  therefore,  they  are 
not  capable  of  giving  rise  to  a  moral  necessity  such  as 
depends  on  the  rational  appetite  of  will.  But  duty  is 
certainly  a  necessity  of  some  kind  laid  on  the  will.  Life 
and  its  expansion,  therefore,  are  not  a  substitute  for 
duty. 

(;<j)  The  second  supposed  equivalent — that  of  the  id(^e- 
force — is  also  outside  our  conception  of  duty.  The  man 
who  stands  upon  a  giddy  height  and  feels  inclined  to 
throw  himself  down,  is  moved  to  do  so  by  an  id6e-force. 
But  we  do  not  regard  such  motor  power  as  the  same  in 
kind  as  what  is  spoken  of  as  the  necessity  of  duty.  In 
fact,  it  oppn:(':'  duty,  for  a  man  is  bound  to  avoid  com- 


ON  DUTY  253 

mitting  suicide,  however  strong  the  idee  force  impclUng 
him  to  it.  Besides,  it  is  absurd  to  claim  that  all  ideas 
are  idees-forces.  The  idea  "  two  "  or  "  house  "  is  not 
an  idee-force,  because  it  has  no  tendency  to  produce 
action. 

(3)  The  third  equivalent — the  tendency  of  sensibility 
to  develop  into  altruism — is  neither  an  equivalent  of 
duty  nor  an  actual  fact.  Altruism,  in  so  far  as  it  is  a 
duty  at  all,  is  only  one  of  our  duties,  and,  therefore, 
should  not  be  described  as  an  equivalent  of  duty. 
Again,  in  sensibility  as  such  there  is  no  germ  of  altruism. 
Intellect  tends  to  be  altruistic,  as  we  shall  see  later  in 
our  chapter  on  Utilitarianism,  for  intellect  is  able  to 
grasp  the  community  of  nature  between  one's  self  and 
others.  But  sense  as  such  is  incapable  of  any  such 
conception,  and  it  cannot  develop  into  altruism.  Crea- 
tures of  sense  may,  indeed,  become  possessed  by  nature 
of  certain  special  appetites  or  kind  affections  like  that 
of  parental  affection.  But  sense  itself  cannot  become 
altruistic. 

(4)  The  fourth  equivalent  of  Guyau  falls  very  far 
short  of  supplying  the  place  of  duty  in  the  maintenance 
of  morality.  No  man  has  a  natural  tendency  to  struggle 
n gainst  passion  except  in  so  far  as  he  conceives  it  to  be 
his  duty  to  do  so — that  is,  in  so  far  as  he  sees  that 
passion  unchecked  is  necessarily  an  evil,  and,  therefore, 
to  be  avoided.  It  is  sheer  nonsense  to  speak  of  men  in 
general  as  resisting  passion  for  the  sake  of  the  risk  and 
struggle  of  it,  or  even  in  order  to  appear  to  themselves 
master  of  their  appetites.  The  mere  desire  to  master 
oneself  could  not  long  maintain  a  high  level  of  morality 
in  this  world. 

(5)  The  fifth  equivalent — viz.,  that  of  the  "  Ideal  " 
which  we  form  for  ourselves,  but  which  has  no  ex- 
istence in  reality — is  no  substitute  for  our  sense  of  duty. 
Were  men  persuaded  that  there  was  no  law  binding 
them  to  be  good,  and  no  end  which  they  were  really 
meant  to  attain,  they  would  not  have  the  same  incentive 


254  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  be  good  as  that  which  comes  of  the  sense  of  duty  and 
the  firm  conviction  of  an  hereafter. 

In  conclusion  we  may  remark  that  these  five  supposed 
equivalents  are  not  really  equivalents  or  substitutes  for 
duty,  because,  whereas  duty  when  understood  is  recog- 
nised as  imperative,  the  more  a  man  understands  these 
equivalents  the  more  he  is  likely  to  despise  them  and  to 
refuse  to  regulate  his  conduct  according  to  them. 

Appendix — Kant's  Deduction  of  Liberty  from 
Moral  Obligation 

We  saw  in  a  previous  chapter  that  liberty  is  a  neces- 
sary pre-condition  of  moral  obligation.  But,  inasmuch 
as  a  necessary  pre-condition  must  always  exist  before 
that  to  which  it  is  a  pre-condition  can  become  real,  it 
follows  that  the  will  must  be  free  before  it  could  be 
subject  to  moral  obligation.  Now,  directly  and  funda- 
mentally, this  proposition  that  the  will  must  be  free 
if  it  be  subject  to  moral  obligation  coiicerns^  the 
^tological  order  only,  not  the  psychological  order  or 
the  order  of  our  ideas.  But  an  interesting  question 
arises  concerning  the  relation  of  freedom  and  moral 
obligation  in  the  psychological  order  or  the  order  of 
knowledge — namely,  could  we,  even  though  there  were 
no  other  proof  of  freedom,  infer  the  freedom  of  the  will 
from  the  fact  that  it  is  subject  to  moral  obligation  ? 
Our  answer  to  this  question  will  depend  on  the  way  in 
which  moral  obligation  is  made  known  to  our  Reason. 
If  obligation  were  made  known  to  us  by  intuition  so 
that  we  could  see  it  with  our  intellects  as  we  see  colours 
with  our  eyes,  then,  since  freedom  is  a  necessary  pre- 
requisite of  obligation,  we  should  be  justified  in  making 
the  inference  that  since  obligation  is  a  reality  freedom 
also  must  be  real.  We  might  then  adopt  the  simple 
formula  in  which  Kant  epitomises  his  whole  theory  of 
the  relation  of^eedom  to  moral  obligalioh— "  I  ought, 
'XJakrciore  I  can."     On  tlic  other  hand,  if  obligation  be 


ON  DUTY  255 

not  known  to  us  by  intuition,  if  its  existence  must  be 
established  by  reasoning  from  premiss  to  conclusion, 
and  if,  in  addition,  freedom  be  in  any  way  contained 
in  the  notion  of  obligation,  then  it  would  be  illogical 
to  make  the  deduction  that  since  the  will  is  subject 
to  moral  obligation,  it  must  be  free,  just  as  it  would  be 
illogical  to  make  the  inference  that  since  the  prisoner  is 
guilty  he  must  be  real,  on  the  ground  that  no  man  could 
be  guilty  except  he  were  real. 

Now,  we  proved  in  the  present  chapter  against  the 
express  teaching  of  Kant  that  moral  obligation  is  not 
known  to  us  by  introspection  or  by  any  kind  of  intui- 
tion, and,  therefore,  we  may  conclude  that  the  Kantian 
formula  which  deduces  the  freedom  of  the  will  from 
obligation — "  I  ought,  therefore  I  can  " — is  founded  on 
a  false  psychological  assumption,  and  that  it  cannot  be 
accepted  as  a  genuine  proof  of  freedom.  As  it  would 
be  absurd  to  deduce  the  axioms  of  Euclid  from  the  forty- 
seventh  proposition,  they  being  pre-suppositions  of  it, 
and  contained  in  the  very  notion  of  its  terms,  so  it  would 
be  illogical  to  conclude  the  existence  of  freedom  from 
moral  obligation.  Freedom  is  a  pre-supposition  of 
moral  obligation,  an  intrinsic  pre-supposition — that  is, 
it  enters  into  the  conception  of  obligation,  and,  therefore, 
we  must  assume  the  freedom  of  the  will  before  we  can 
establish  obligation.* 

♦  A  theory  approaching  Kant's  is  that  of  the  pragmatists  that — 
though  freedom  is  not  provable  by  speculative  reason,  it  is  yet  neces- 
sary, since  without  it  there  can  be  no  morality,  and  morality  is  a  need 
of  life  (see  Prof.  James'  "The  Will  to  Believe  ").  On  purely  intel- 
lectual grounds,  Prof.  James  contends,  freedom  is  not  only  unprovable, 
but  wholly  unacceptable,  to  reason.  But  on  moral  grounds  it  is  a 
necessary  postulate  of  the  practical  reason.  "  While  I  freely  admit," 
he  writes,  "  that  the  pluralism  and  restlessness  are  repugnant  and 
irrational  in  a  certam  way,  I  find  that  the  alternative  to  them  is 
irrational  in  a  deeper  way.  The  indttenninism  offends  only  the  native 
absolutism  of  my  intellect — an  absolutism  which,  after  all,  perhaps 
deserves  to  be  snubbed  and  kept  in  check.  But  determinism  .  .  . 
violates  my  sense  of  moral  reality  through  and  through." 


CHAPTER  IX 
THE  KANTIAN   FORMALISM 

"  The  Grecian-Roman  philosophy  was  not  a  genuine  moral  system, 
but  only  an  egoistic  Pseudo-Ethic  ;  the  philosophy  of  the  middle 
ages  was  not  an  autonomous  morality,  but  only  a  heteronomous 
pseudo-morality." — Harimann  (Pessimism). 

We  have,  outlined  in  the  above  passage,  the  two  sup- 
posed defects  of  the  ancient  and  mediaeval  Ethic  re- 
spectively— viz.,  that  in  the  ancient  Grecian  Ethic  the 
good  was  that  which  pleased  and  made  one  happy,  and 
that  in  the  mediaeval  Ethic  the  law  of  good  was  repre- 
sented not  as  a  law  of  our  inner  Reason,  but  either  as 
the  law  of  the  Supreme  Being  or  as  that  of  some  other 
authority  external  to  and  above  us,  such  as  church, 
state,  or  master.  To  this  twofold  "  error "  modern 
Ethics  opposed  the  twofold  theory  of  "  Formalism," 
and  the  "  Autonomy  of  the  Reason."  Let  us  here  see 
what  is  to  be  said  on  the  theory  of  Formalism.  We 
shall  in  a  later  chapter  *  discuss  the  question  of 
Autonomy. 

"  Formalism  "  is  the  theory  that  no  action  is  moral 
which  is  done  for  pleasure  or  happiness  or  from  any 
other  motive  but  that  of  duty  or  law.f  We  connect 
this  theory  with  Kant's  name  rather  than  with  that  of 
any  other  Ethician  because  it  seems  to  us  that,  perhaps, 

*  Chapter  on  Law. 

t  Besides  the  theory  of  pure  formalism  advocated  by  Kant  there 
are  other  partly  formalistic  theories  that  approach  Kant's  theory  with 
varying  degrees  of  closeness.  Almost  identical  with  Kant's  theory  is 
the  well-known  view  of  the  Stoics  in  ancient  times  and  of  Whowcll  in 
modem  times,  that  to  be  morally  good  an  act  should  be  done  for  the 
sake  of  virtue,  and  that  virtue  is  its  own  reward.  Less  purely  formal 
is  the  theory  of  Sidgwick,  that  though  "  duty  for  duty's  sake  "  is 
necessary  as  a  general  spring  of  action,  it  is  not  an  indispensable 
moral  criterion  for  our  individual  acts.  Less  formal  still  is  the  view 
of  Shaftesbury,  that  though  wc  may  use  our  selfish  feelings  for  scUish 
ends  wc  should  use  our  benevolent  feelings  for  benevolent  ends. 

256 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  257 

with  the  single  exception  of  Hutcheson,  he  is  the  only 
"  formalist  "  who  works  out  the  theory  of  the  exclusion 
of  pleasure  from  moral  action  to  its  full  logical  con- 
clusion. To  be  moral  an  act,  according  to  Kant,  should 
be  done  for"  the  sake  of  law  or  duty,  not  for  pleasure, 
or  happiness.  Secondly,  it  must  be  done  for  the  sake 
of  law  as  such  and  not  for  the  sake  of  the  content  of 
the  law  {i.e.,  because  what  it  enacts  is  to  our  liking), 
nor  for  the  sake  of  the  lawgiver.  Thirdly,  it  must  be 
done  out  of  respect  for  law,  not  for  love  of  it.  A  moral 
act  then,  according  to  Kant,  is  one  which  is  done  out 
of  respect  for  law  or  duty  as  such.  Hutcheson  says 
practically  the  same  thing  when  he  claims  that  regard 
even  to  the  approbation  of  Conscience  taints  the  virtue 
of  our  act.  In  our  criticism,  we  shall  consider  the  first 
of  Kant's  conditions  only,  for  it  is  the  principal  condition, 
viz.,  that,  to  be  moral,  an  act  should  be  done  for  duty 
and  not  for  pleasure. 

Our  examination  of  this  theory  will  consist  of  two 
parts : — 

(a)  Consideration  of  arguments  against  the  theory  of 
formalism. 

{b)  Consideration  of  the  principal  arguments  in  its 
favour. 

(a)  Disproof  of  the  Theory  of  Formalism 
(i)  We  first  of  air  maintain  that  this  very  rigorous 
demand  upon  our  moral  nature  is  not  a  thing  that  we 
are  prepared  to  accept  without  some  rational  proof. 
For  (a)  it  is  not  a  principle  that  appeals  all  at  once  to 
our  acceptance ;  and  {b)  the  task  that  it  imposes  is  a 
very  arduous  one.  {a)  We  have,  for  instance,  been 
accustomed  to  call  the  cheerful  giver — i.e.,  the  man  who 
gives  because  he  loves  the  poor — the  moral  man  par 
excellence,  and  not  the  man  who  gives  out  of  respect 
for  law.*     Also  [b]  to  exclude  pleasure  wholly  as  motive 

*o()b'  €(XTiv  a7a^6j  6  /ttrj  x^-^^"  ^'I's  AcaXats  irpd^eSiv    .    .    .    ovt  iXevd^pioy 
t6i>  /utj  xa'Poi'T*  ■'■"'S  iXevdiplois  irp<i.^£<nv  (Nicb.  Eth.  1.,  8,  12). 
Vol.  I — 17 


258  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of   human    action   is    to    demand    something   which   is 
quite  above  human  nature.     This  view  of  morals,  there- 
fore, is  both  starthng  and  rigorous.     Whether  the  proofs 
of  this  theory  are  rational  or  sufficient  to  force  it  upon 
our  acceptance  in  spite  of  its  novelty  and  the  difficulty 
of  its  observance,  we  shall  enquire  later. 
f    (2)  We  contend  that  the  idea  of   "  duty  for  duty's 
/  sake "   is   not    necessarily  implied   in   the   scientific   or 
• .      Y  technical  conception  of  a  morally  good  act. 
/\  '  \       jjjig  y^iw  \)Q  evident  from  the  conception  of  goodness 
^^  as  developed  in  the  preceding  pages.     A  morally  good 

^^         1    act,  we  saw,  is  one  which  is  directed  by  Reason  to  our 
Ki^'  I    last  end.     Provided,  then,  that  all  the  ends  that  we  seek 


X' 


in  any  particular  act  are  such  as  lead  us  to  our  final  end, 
our  act  is  morally  good.  The  final  end,  then,  is  the 
proper  motive  of  a  moral  act,  and  any  action  may  be 
brought  under  that  motive  and  be  morally  good  if  the 
ends  involved  in  it  be  such  as  really  promote  our  final 
end.  We  saw  also  that  any  act  will  promote  our  final 
end  which  accords  with  the  natural  objects  of  our 
faculties. 

Hence  duty  or  law  is  not  a  necessary  motive  of  every 
moral  action. 

(3)  It  is  obvious  that  if  such  acts  alone  are  morally 
good  as  are  done  for  the  sake  of  duty,  then  only  such 
acts  are  good  as  are  actually  obligatory.  Hence  works 
of  supererogation  could  not  possibly  be  morally  good 
from  their  very  definition  as  supererogatory,  since  works 
of  supererogation  are  not  our  duty,  and,  therefore,  they 
could  not  be  done  out  of  the  motive  of  duty.  We 
believe,  however,  that  to  exclude  works  of  supereroga- 
tion from  the  sphere  of  moral  action  would  be  to  go 
dead  against  the  common  sense  of  mankind.  F"or 
common  sense  affirms  that  he  who  is  bound  to  give 
five  poimds  to  the  poor,  and  yet  gives  two  hundred 
pounds,  is  morally  a  better  man,  ceteris  paribus,  than 
he  who  barely  fulfils  his  obligation. 

It  has  been  said,  however,  by  some  followers  of  Kant 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  259 

that  works  of  supererogation  are  at  least  allowed  *  by 
law,  and  that  a  man  who  does  an  act  because  it  is 
allowed  by  law  really  does  it  for  the  sake  of  the  law  or 
of  duty,  and  that,  consequently,  works  of  supereroga- 
tion can,  even  on  the  Kantian  theory,  be  brought  under 
the  motive  of  duty.  We  maintain,  however,  that  mere 
lawfulness  is  not  a  motive  of  action — that  is,  that  we 
could  not  possibly  do  an  act  merely  because  it  was  lawful, 
that  the  man  who  thinks  of  the  lawfulness  of  an  act 
may  do  it,  indeed,  with  deference  to  law,  but  that  he 
does  not  do  it  on  account  of  its  lawfulness.  Lawfulness, 
or  "  allowability  "  \^  de  se  di  mere  negation,  signifying 
nothing  more  than  that  the  law  does  not  oppose  a  par- 
ticular action,  and  no  man  could  possibly  act  from 
such  a  motive.  A  man  cauld  not,  for  instance,  be 
drawn  to  eat  his  dinner  merely  because  it  was  lawful. 
A  man  may  eat  for  eating's  sake  or  to  please  others, 
but  an  end  he  must  have,  to  act  at  all,  and  mere  allow- 
ability is  not  a  sufficient  end.  Neither  could  a  man  give 
money  merely  because  it  was  lawful.  He  might  give  it 
to  relieve  the  poor,  or  because  he  had  too  much  of  it, 
or  for  some  ulterior  motive  or  ambition,  but  he  could 
not  give  it  from  the  sole  idea  that  it  is  lawful.  Mere 
lawfulness,  therefore,  can  never  constitute  the  purpose 
of,  though  it  may  constitute  a  condition  of  action.  That 
is,  I  may  first  ascertain  that  an  act  is  lawful,  and  then 
do  it  for  some  other  reason.  But  I  could  not  do  it 
simply  because  it  was  lawful. 

Works,  therefore,  of  supererogation  must,  on  the 
present  theory,  stand  completely  outside  the  category 
of  morality.  They  are  not  a  duty,  and  hence  could 
not  be  done  for  duty's  sake. 

(4)  On  the  theory  of  Formalism  all  moral  acts  must 
be  equally  moral,  since  on  this  theory  the  sole  ground  of 
the  morality  of  an  act  is  the  motive  which  inspires  it,  and 
there  is  on  this  theory  only  one  possible  moral  motive — • 

*  Wc  cannot  veri'v  this  view,  nor  can  we  remember  where  we 
have  seen  it  stated 


26o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

namely,  the  fulfilling  of  duty.  He  who  pays  a  greater 
sum  because  he  has  to  pay  it  is  no  better  on  this  theory 
than  the  man  who  pays  less,  for  all  just  do  what  they 
have  to  do,  and  because  they  have  to  do  it. 

(5)  On  the  Kantian  theory  there  is  no  room  for  merit 
with  our  fellowmen  since  no  man  merits  with  another 
by  the  mere  doing  of  what  he  is  obliged  to  do.  I  do 
not  merit  with  other  men  by  paying  what  I  owe  them, 
because  to  pay  what  I  owe  is  a  strict  duty,  and  no 
thanks  is  due  for  its  fulfilment. 

(6)  If  to  do  an  act  because  it  subserves  a  useful  pur- 
pose will  not  make  an  action  morally  good,  then  to  do 
it  because  it  is  injurious  will  not  render  an  action 
morally  bad.  The  converse  is  also  true.  If  to  do  a 
good  act  I  must  do  it  not  merely  with  respect  for,  but 
out  of  respect  for,  and  on  account  of,  law — i.e.,  if  goodness 
depends  on  my  attitude  of  will  to  law,  then  to  do  an  evil 
action  I  must  act  not  merely  with  disrespect  but  from 
very  disrespect  of  and  hatred  to  law.  This,  we  need 
hardly  say,  is  altogether  at  variance  with  our  moral 
conceptions  generally,  and  the  consequence  of  it  must 
be  to  render  the  whole  moral  law  and  system  nugatory. 
For  no  criminal  acts  for  the  simple  purpose  of  violating 
a  law,  but  rather  to  please  or  to  enrich  himself  in  spite 
of  law,  and  such  a  will  would  not  on  this  theory  be 
morally  bad.  This  argument,  too,  tells  equally  well 
against  Shaftesbury's  as  against  the  Kantian  formula. 
If,  in  order  that  the  human  will  be  good,  it  must  desire 
a  virtuous  act  because  it  is  virtuous,  or  for  the  sake  of 
virtue,  then  in  order  that  a  man  be  morally  bad,  one 
must  desire  evil  for  the  sake  of  vice,  and  because  it  is 
malicious.  On  such  a  theory  there  is  no  act  that  might 
not  be  morally  condoned,  since  any  act,  however  evil, 
may  be  done  for  the  pleasure  which  it  affords,  or  for  its 
usefulness,  or  for  some  other  end  besides  mere  vicious- 
ness,  whereas  if  Formalism  be  true  only  such  acts  are 
bad  as  are  done  out  of  Ihc  very  motive  of  viciousnoaa. 
Nay,  since  no  man  could  desire  an  evil  action  merely 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  261 

because  of  the  evil  of  it,  there  could  be,  on  this  theory, 
no  such  thing  as  moral  evil  in  the  world,  even  though 
there  might  be  moral  good.  This,  again,  is  a  view  of 
morals  to  which  the  world  in  general  will  not  readily 
subscribe. 

(7)  We  have  seen  already  that  the  exclusion  of  happi- 
ness from  the  motives  of  human  action  is  quite  as 
hopeless  a  task  as  the  exclusion  of  object.  The  will, 
we  have  already  seen,  must  desire  happiness  and  cannot 
help  desiring  it.  This  cardinal  principle  of  the  Aris- 
totelian philosophy  as  admitted  in  the  most  formal  and 
explicit  way  by  Kant  himself.  "  There  is  one  end," 
he  writes,*  "  however,  which  may  be  assumed  to  be 
actually  such  to  all  rational  beings  ....  and  therefore 
one  purpose  which  they  not  merely  may  have,  but 
which  we  may  with  certainty  assume  that  they  all 
actually  have  bj^  a  natural  necessity,  and  this  is  happi- 
ness." Again, t  "  To  be  happy  is  necessarily  the  wish 
of  every  finite  creature,  and  this  therefore  is  inevitably 
a  determining  principle  of  its  faculty  of  desire."  The 
conclusion  is  obvious  :  if,  in  order  that  an  act  be  moral 
it  is  necessary  to  eliminate  momentarily  from  our  minds 
the  desire  for  happiness,  then  moral  acts  are  clearly 
impossible,  for  so  has  nature  constituted  us  that  the 
desire  for  happiness  cannot  be  eliminated.  It  is  a  neces- 
sary element  in  every  act  of  will. 

The  objection  here  urged  against  the  Kantian  principle 
is  of  very  great  importance,  and  it  finds  frequent  men- 
tion in  Kant's  writings.  In  justice  to  Kant  we  feel 
bound  to  indicate  the  chief  ways  in  which  he  attempts 
to  solve  it. 

rant's  solutions 

(a)  Kant  admits  that  the  necessity  of  the  desire  for 
happiness  renders  it  very  difficult  to  elicit  a  purely  moral 
act.     But  the  difficulty  of  eliciting  such  an  act  does  not.  he 

*  Metaphysic  of  Morals  (Abbot),  page  32. 

I  "  Analytic  of  Pure  Prac.  Reason,"  page  112 


262  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS  ' 

says,  alter  our  definition  of  it,  nor  relieve  us  of  the  necessity 
of  performing  it,  just  as  "  friendship  would  still  be  a  com- 
mand of  Reason,  even  though  there  might  never  have  been 
a  true  friend."  * 

Reply — We  are  not  concerned  here  with  definitions  but 
with  the  question  whether  we  ought  to  do  moral  acts  in 
Kant's  sense.  Our  reply  is  that  we  ought  not  because  we 
cannot.  It  is  a  psj^chological  impossibility.  Acts  of  friend- 
ship, with  which  Kant  compares  morality,  no  matter  how 
difficult,  are  sometimes  possible.  If  they  were  not  possible 
there  could  be  no  law  of  Reason  enjoining  them. 

ip)  Kant's  second  solution  is  as  follows  :  The  psycho- 
logical necessity  we  are  under  of  desiring  happiness  and  the 
moral  necessity  or  law  which  urges  us  to  exclude  happiness 
from  the  motives  of  acts  do  not  stand  opposed,  since  the  two 
necessities  dwell  in  different  sides  or  departments  (if  we  may 
use  the  term)  of  our  Being.  The  first  belongs  to  us  as  pheno- 
mena, or  sense  beings — the  second  belongs  to  us  as  "  in- 
telligible," as  noumena.  Hence  the  psychological  necessity 
referred  to  of  desiring  happiness  does  not  negative  the  com- 
mand of  Reason  to  elicit  purely  moral  acts  f  and  to  exclude 
the  desire  for  happiness. 

Reply — Even  if  we  grant  the  reality  of  the  distinction 
between  noumenon  and  phenomenon  it  is  still  evident  that 
since  it  is  psychologically  impossible  to  eliminate  the  desire 
for  happiness,  therefore,  the  command  of  Reason  to  exclude 
it,  if  such  a  command  exists,  is  a  vain  and  meaningless  com- 
mand. For,  from  what  side  or  department  of  our  nature  is 
this  desire  to  be  excluded  ?  It  cannot  be  excluded  from  the 
noumenal  side  since,  on  Kant's  theory,  it  does  not  dwell 
there.  On  the  other  hand,  it  cannot  be  excluded  from  the 
phenomenal  side,  because  it  is  there  by  a  necessity  of  nature, 
and,  therefore,  the  command  to  exclude  it  would  be  of  no 
avail.  The  law,  therefore,  to  exclude  happiness  is  a  vain 
and  meaningless  law  and  cannot  be  sustained.  Besides, 
there  is  the  practical  difficulty  how  we  are  to  allow  the  desire 
for  happiness  to  dwell  in  the  phenomenal  side  whilst  ex- 
cluding it  from  the  noumenal. 

(c)  A  third  attempted  solution  is  found  in  the  Dialectic 
of  Practical  Reason. J  The  psychological  necessity  to  desire 
happiness  and  the  command  of  Reason  to  exclude  it  refer 

*  Metaphysic  of  Morals,  page  24 
I  ibid,  page  72. 
;  ibid,  pagr  204. 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  263 

to  two  ditferent  objects,  and,  therefore,  they  are  not  opposed. 
For,  the  psychological  necessity  relates  to  happiness  as  end 
of  action,  i.e.,  we  must  desire  and  cannot  help  desiring 
happiness  as  end  ;  whereas  the  moral  necessity  or  the  com- 
mand of  Reason  to  exclude  this  motive  from  action  relates 
to  happiness  as  principle  of  action,  i.e.  we  must  not  make 
happiness  the  principle  of  our  act.  Hence,  when  it  is  said 
that  a  man  should  act  from  duty,  this  means  that  he  should 
make  duty  the  principle  of  his  act,  but  his  act  may  still 
be  directed  towards  happiness  as  end. 

Reply — The  distinction  drawn  by  Kant  between  end  (or 
what  he  sometimes  calls  spring)  and  principle  of  action  is 
wholly  imaginary.*  In  relation  to  our  wills,  the  spring  or 
end  of  action  and  the  principle  are  one  and  the  same.  The 
only  principle  of  will-activity,  the  only  thing  that  determines 
the  will  to  act  is  the  end  which  it  desires,  the  end  which 
Reason  puts  before  it  as  desirable.  We  may,  of  course, 
distinguish  between  proximate  and  remote  or  ulterior  ends  of 
action.  Thus  if  we  give  money  to  a  poor  man  in  order  to 
gain  glory  for  ourselves  we  desire  proximately  to  reheve 
the  poor  man,  but  remotely,  and,  we  may  say,  principally, 
we  desire  renown  for  ourselves.  But  everything  that  we 
desire,  or  which  moves  us  to  action,  is  desired  and  moves 
us  as  an  end,  as  a  thing  to  be  attained.  Hence  our  difficulty 
remains — it  is  as  happiness-producing  that  motives,  whether 
the  motive  be  duty  or  sympathy  or  anything  else,  determine 
us  ;  and,  consequently,  a  command  of  Reason  to  exclude  the 
desire  for  happiness  and  to  act  from  the  motive  of  duty  only 
would  be  a  meaningless  command.  Again,  even  though  the 
distinction  of  end  and  principle  could  be  made  good  in  theory, 
it  would  be  impossible  to  observe  it  in  practice.  No  man 
could  make  happiness  or  anything  else  the  chief  end  of  his 
action  and  prevent  it  from  becoming  the  principle  of  his 
act.  Hence  the  injunction  to  exclude  happiness  as  principle 
whilst  admitting  it  as  end  is  impracticable. 

{d)  Finally,  an   attempt  is  made  to  harmonise  the  two 


♦  One  point  of  distinction,  according  to  Kant,  between  end  and 
principle  is  that  '  end  '  is  an  object  of  love,  '  principle  '  of  respect  ; 
and  he  gives  as  the  distinguishing  mark  of  respect  as  opposed  to  love, 
that  respect  involves  "  an  inward  reluctance  of  the  will  towards 
law."  From  this  it  would  seem  to  follow  that  acting  out  of  respect 
for  law,  to  the  exclusion  of  love,  is  the  same  thing  as  actmg  out  of 
reluctance  to  law — a  curious  motive,  indeed,  for  moral  action,  and, 
to  our  thinking,  also  an  impossible  motive  psychologically.  Schiller's 
witty  description  of  the  moral  man  in  Kant's  theory  is  well  known — 
"  he  who  despises  ♦he  law  and  with  horror  fulfils  it." 


264  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

necessities  in  the  various  devices  by  which  Kant  attempts 
to  find  room  for  happiness  in  the  moral  act  whilst  excluding 
it  as  the  end  aimed  at.  Thus  it  is  admitted  that  happiness 
is  often  a  means  to  virtue  and  may  be  sought  as  means,* 
that  it  can  be  experienced  as  a  result  of  the  purely  moral 
act  which  therefore  excludes  its  being  made  the  motive  of 
our  act  (in  which  case  it  is  spoken  of  as  moral  happiness, 
not  pathological  f),  and  finally  we  are  told  that  morality, 
although  excluding  happiness  as  motive,  does  not  exclude 
"  worthiness  to  be  happy  "  and  in  this  way  happiness  can 
be  admitted  into  the  moral  act.| 

But  none  of  these  answers  are  really  relevant  to  the  problem 
we  have  raised,  how,  viz.,  a  moral  act  is  possible,  since,  as 
Kant  himself  admits,  happiness  is  desired  in  every  human 
act.  What  is  necessarily  desired  in  every  human  act  is  a 
necessary  end  of  action. 

(8)  According  to  Kant  the  only  moral  principle  of 
action  is  law  or  respect  for  law  ;  law  in  the  case  being 
a  command  of  Reason.  His  proofs  we  shall  examine 
later  on,  but  at  present  we  wish  it  to  be  understood  that 
the  law  of  Reason  is  a  command.  Command,  however, 
is,  according  to  Kant,  a  genuine  moral  principle,  not 
on  account  of  the  legislator  who  issues  it,  and  not  on 
account  of  the  matter  of  the  command,  but  simply  as 
command,  as  law,  as  legislation.  For  we  must  do  the 
act,  he  tells  us,  not  out  of  respect  for  the  lawgiver  or 
on  account  of  what  the  law  ordains,  but  out  of  respect 
for  law  as  such.  But  in  law,  when  we  abstract  from 
"  lawgiver,"  and  from  the  matter  of  the  laws,  there  is 
nothing  left  but  the  act  or  command  of  the  legislator — 
that  is,  there  is  nothing  left  but  legislation  itself.  Legis- 
lation or  command,  therefore,  as  principle  of  action  is, 
on  the  present  theory,  the  primary  source  of  the  morality 
of  our  action.  But  how,  we  ask,  can  legislation  as  such 
be  a  determinant  of  morality  ?  Is  not  legislation  itself 
subject  to  moral  criticism  ?  May  not  legislation  be 
good  or  bad  ?     May  not  the  commands  even  of  any 

•  "  Analytic,"  page  187 
t  "  Dialectic,"  page  213 
i  ibid,  page  227, 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  265 

rightful  legislator  be  bad,  and  how,  then,  can  legislation 
be  the  ultimate  source  of  moral  good.  This  or  that 
command  coming  from  this  or  that  legislator  may  be 
good  ;  but  legislation  as  such  is  not  necessarily  good. 
It  cannot,  therefore,  be  the  chief  principle  of  moral 
action. 

It  may  be  answered  that  legislation  which  is  bad  is 
really  not  legislation  at  all,  and  that,  consequently,  law 
or  legislation,  in  the  true  sense  of  the  word,  is  neces- 
sarily a  good  motive.  We  reply — bad  legislation  is  not 
legislation  at  all,  just  in  so  far  as  it  cannot  bind  us  in 
conscience — that  is,  just  in  so  far  as  its  matter  is  bad, 
but  it  is  legislation  in  the  sense  that  it  is  the  command 
of  an  authoritative  and  rightful  legislator,  and  in  this 
sense  it  is,  according  to  Kant,  the  rightful  principle  of 
action.  But,  we  repeat,  as  command  it  may  be  either 
good  or  bad.  Legislation,  then,  as  such,  in  sense  of 
command  as  such,  is  not  the  ultimate  principle  of 
morality. 

(q)  Law  itself  should  be  subordinated  to  the  end  which 
it  is  naturally  intended  to  promote — viz.,  the  common 
good.  The  end  of  law  ip  the  advancement  of  the 
common  good,  and,  therefore,  to  make  moral  good 
consist  in  acting  out  of  respect  for  law,  and  not  in 
acting  from  the  motive  of  the  good  which  the  law  is 
originally  meant  to  secure,  is  to  invert  the  natural 
order  of  things — to  make  the  means  principal,  and  such 
a  proceeding  would,  if  the  illustration  will  be  allowed, 
be  about  as  absurd  as  to  say  that  a  dancer  ought  to  aim 
at  acting  out  of  respect  to  the  word  of  his  master  rather 
than  with  a  view  to  executing  a  graceful  movement.* 

•  We  may  here  be  allowed  to  notice  an  argument  which  has  been 
made  much  of  by  many  of  Kant's  opponents,  but  which  to  our  mind 
involves  a  mis-statement  of  the  Kantian  theory,  and  therefore  cannot 
be  regarded  as  a  logical  answer  to  it.  The  argument  rests  on  wliat  is 
known  as  the  paradox  of  Stoicism,  and  we  give  it  prominence  here 
simply  because  of  its  historical  importance.  Briefly  put,  this  argu- 
ment is  as  follows  :  "  Before  you  can  have  regard  to  the  virtue  of 
an  act,  the  act  itself  must  be  virtuous  "  (Hume,  "  Enquiry,"  page  479). 
Again,  Green  writes  :   "No  act  can  be  virtuous  or  morally  good  unless 


266  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


(b)  Arguments  of  the  Formalists 

We  shall  now  examine  the  principal  arguments  of  the 
formaUsts.  It  is  not,  indeed,  easy  to  get  Kant's  argu- 
ments together,  or  to  put  them  succinctly,  since  he 
himself  seems  to  have  written  them  just  as  they  occurred 
to  him  without  order  and  often  with  much  seeming  in- 
consistency. The  following  two  arguments,  however, 
must  be  considered  : — 

First.  Formalism,  or  "  duty  for  duty's  sake,"  is  the 
creed  of  the  crowd.  It  is  the  common  or  the  vulgar 
idea  of  morality,  the  idea  which  receives  "  the  thorough 
assent  of  even  common  reason." 

Secondly.  The  ground  or  principle  of  morality  must, 
according  to  the  testimony  of  our  conscience,  possess 
two  distinctive  attributes — ^first,  it  must  be  of  categorical 
value,  of  value  in  itself  and  not  merely  as  means  to  some- 
thing else,*  secondly,  it  must  be  of  value  for  all  men.f 
Now  (a)  external  objects  are  not  such  a  good,  because 
they  are  desirable  and  desired  only  as  a  means  to  pleasure. 
Hence  the  moral  good  must  lie  within  us,  it  must  not  be 
external.  (6)  But  it  cannot  consist  in  inner  pleasure, 
because  pleasure  is  only  a  feeling  of  sense  and  therefore 

there  be  in  human  nature  some  motive  to  produce  it,  distinct  from  the 
sense  of  its  morality."  The  argument  is  this — the  doing  of  an  act  for 
the  sake  of  virtue  cannot  itself  be  the  principle  on  which  the  moral 
virtuousness  of  an  act  depends,  since  it  already  supposes  the  act  to 
be  virtuous.  The  Kantian  position  is,  therefore,  a  usieron  proteron 
and  a  paradox. 

But  this  really  is  not  an  answer  to  Kant.  Kant  and  Whewell  both 
grant  that  before  we  can  desire  a  virtuous  act  on  account  of  its  virtue 
the  act  must  first  be  materially  good.  But  they  claim  that  if,  over 
and  above  the  materially  good  act,  you  are  also  to  have  a  formally 
good  act  or  a  virtuous  or  moral  will,  then  the  will  must  wish  the  act 
in  question  simply  because  it  is  virtuous  or  good,  and  for  no  other 
reason.  There  is  here  no  paradox  and  no  usieron  proteron.  The 
formally  virtuous  will  and  the  materially  good  object  or  end  are  two 
distinct  things.  The  fomially  good  act  presupposes  an  act  materially 
good,  but  it  docs  not  prcsupjK).sc  formal  goodness,  and,  therefore,  it 
il  no  paradox  to  assert  that  in  order  that  an  act  should  bo  formally 
good  or  virtuous  we  should  do  it  on  account  of  the  virtuousness  or 
goodness  that  it  contains  considercd  materially. 

*  "  Fund.  Princ.  of  Met.  of  Morals,"  pages  58-59,  and  63. 

t  Ibtd.  pages  25  and  44 ;  also  "  An.  of  Prac.  Reason,"  page  ii2 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  267 

like  all  feeling  it  differs  with  different  men.  The  moral 
principle  therefore  must  consist  in  something  within  us 
but  above  the  senses,  in  some  motivating  power  of  the 
Will  or  Practical  Reason.  But  the  only  motivating 
power  of  the  Practical  Reason  is  law  or  command,  and 
therefore  this  is  the  principle  of  morality,  and  it  is  both 
categorical  in  worth,  and  valid  for  all  men.  We  must 
therefore  act  for  the  sake  of  law.* 

Let  us  examine  these  arguments  separately,  (i) 
Formalism  has  the  thorough  assent  of  even  the  common 
Reason.  This  is  the  main  ground  of  Formalism — the 
ground  which  at  one  time  secured  to  Kant's  doctrine  a 
more  or  less  general  acceptance.  As  proof  that  pleasure 
or  utility  or  effects  of  any  kind  are  not  a  true  motive 
of  morality  Kant  writes  :  "  A  good  will  is  good  not 
because  of  what  it  performs  or  effects,  not  by  its  aptness 
for  the  attainment  of  some  proposed  end,  but  simply 
by  virtue  of  the  volition — that  is,  it  is  good  in  itself  ; 
and  considered  by  itself  is  to  be  esteemed  much  higher 
than  all  that  can  be  brought  about  by  it  in  favour  of 
any  inclination,  nay,  even  of  the  sum  total  of  inclina- 
tions." This,  Kant  maintains,  is  the  common  and  the 
vulgar  conception  of  morals.  Let  us  see  whether  this 
is  true.  We  have  ourselves  italicised  the  words  "  that 
is  "  in  the  quotation,  for  it  is  to  the  transition  which 
Kant  attempts  to  effect  at  this  point  that  we  wish  to 
draw  the  reader's  attention.  We  grant  most  willingly 
that  the  "  common  reason "  will  regard  that  will  as 
good  which  has  wished  well  and  morally,  independently 
altogether  of  its  being  able  to  reduce  its  volition  to 
reality,  and  independently  also  of  that  which  it  actually 
"  effects."  He,  for  instance,  who  would  wish  to  come 
to  the  aid  of  the  distressed  but  cannot  do  so  is  quite  as 
moral  as  he  who  actually  aids  them.  And,  on  the  other 
hand,  he  who  has  the  will  to  do  good,  but  really  does 

*  The  most  connected  and  condensed  statement  of  the  argument 
given  above  is  to  Ix;  found  in  "  An.  of  I^ire  Prac.  Reason,"  pages  107- 
108  (Abbot's  revised  fourth  edition). 


268  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

evil,  either  by  accident  or  by  mistake,  is  morally  quite 
as  good  as  he  who  does  the  good  in  fact.     In  that  sense, 
indeed,  "  a  good  will  is  good,  not  by  virtue  of  what  it 
effects,  but  simply  by  virtue  of  the  volition."     But  in 
admitting  this  we  have  admitted  no  more  than  that  it 
is  the  internal  act  of  the  will  which  is  good  primarily 
and  essentially,  and  that  external  actions  are  morally 
good  only  in  so  far  as  they  are  connected  with  the  inner 
intention  or  motive,  and  make  with  it  a  complete  human 
act.     So  far  we  are  quite  at  one  with  Kant.     The  will 
is  good  (and,  we  may  also  add,  is  bad)  independently 
"  of  what  it  performs  or  effects,"  independently  also  of 
its  "  aptness  for  the  attainment  of  some  proposed  end  " 
— its  aptness  namely,  actually  to  do  that  which  it  desires 
to  do  ;   and  independent^  finally  "  of  what  can  he  brought 
about  {i.e.,  effected  in  favour  of  or    in    correspondence 
with)  its  inclinations  or  even  the  sum  total  of  its  inclina- 
tions."    All  this  is  true.     But   Kant  had  no  right   to 
argue  on  the  ground  of  these  commonplace  propositions 
that  the  will  is  therefore  good  in  itself,  independently  of 
its  wish,  or  of  what  it  wishes,  or  of  its  inclination,  or  of 
the  sum  total  of  its  inclinations.     The  world,  according 
to  Kant,  does  not  judge  a  man  good  or  bad  by  what  he 
effects  outwardly,  and  that  is  quite  true.     But  the  world 
certainly  judges  a  man  to  be  good  or  bad  according  to 
his  inner  wishes  and  desires  and  by  what  he  desires.     A 
man  is  not  necessarily  either  good  or  bad  who  never 
robs.     But  we  call  him  bad  if  we  know  that  he  harbours 
the  desire  to  rob.     We  do  not  call  a  man  good   or  bad 
who  has  never  killed  another.     But  we  call  him  bad  if 
it  was  his  intention  to  do  so.    We  neither  call  a  man 
selfish  nor  benevolent  who  does  not  give  money,  since 
he  may  have  none  to  give.     But  wc  call  him  .selfush  if 
he  does  not  desire  to  give  it,  and  benevolent  if  he  would 
give  it  were  it  in  his  power  to  do  so.     The  world,  there- 
fore, judges  of  the  morality  of  our  acts  by  the  ends  that 
we  desire.     It  does  not  account  the  will  good  "  in  itself  " 
apart  from  its  ends  and  desires. 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  269 

In  the  common  Reason,  therefore,  there  is  nothing 
that  makes  for  Formalism,  according  to  which  a  man 
would  not  be  accounted  good  who  desired  only  good 
ends.  On  the  contrary,  the  common  Reason  is  dead 
against  it,  since  the  common  Reason  judges  of  morality 
according  to  the  objects  of  our  desires. 

Again,  in  treating  of  benevolence,  we  are  told  by 
Kant  that  no  act  of  benevolence  can  be  accounted  moral 
unless  "  all  sympathy  be  extinguished  with  the  lot  of 
others."  While  still  maintaining  the  power  to  help,  we 
must,  he  tells  us,  if  our  act  is  to  be  moral  "  be  not 
troubled  by  their  trouble,"  but  be  insensible  to  it,  he 
being  alone  moral  who  succeeds  in  helping  them, 
"  having  torn  himself  out  of  this  dead  insensibility  to 
perform  an  action  without  any  inclination  to  it  but 
simply  from  duty."  *  He  should,  indeed,  if  he  would 
be  consistent  with  his  own  principle,  have  said  instead 
■ — "  When,  having  failed  to  tear  himself  out  of  this 
dead  insensibility,  and,  therefore,  whilst  still  insensible 
to  their  misery,  he  nevertheless  performs  an  action 
without  any  inclination  to  it,  but  simply  from  duty." 
This  view  of  morality  is  not,  we  submit,  the  view  taken 
of  it  by  men  at  large,  it  is  not  the  "  vulgar  morality  " 
or  what  "  the  common  Reason  believes." 

Indeed,  the  more  we  examine  into  the  matter  the 
more  we  shall  be  convinced  that  the  settled  conviction 
of  the  world  is  not  Formalism — on  the  contrary,  that 
Formalism  offends  against  our  commonest  moral  sensi- 
bilities. The  plain  man's  view  of  morality  may  be 
contrasted  with  Formalism  as  follows  :  According  to 
Formalism  morality  belongs  to  our  wills  independently 
of  objects  or  ends,  and  our  wills  are  moral  when  the 
act  springs  from  the  motive  of  law  or  duty.  The  plain 
man's  view  is  (a)  that  it  is,  indeed,  the  good  will  to  do, 
and  not  the  deed,  which  is  the  principal  determinant 
of  moral  worth  ;  but  (6)  that  the  will  is  morally  good 
when  all  its  ends,  proximate  and  remote,  are  good,  and, 
therefore,  that  goodness  and  badness  in  the  human  will 
*  Abbot,  vage  14. 


270  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

are  determined  by  the  objects  which  we  desire  ;  (c)  that 
a  bad  end  vitiates  everything  ;  (d)  that  a  purely  selfish 
end,  though  it  does  not  vitiate  action,  may  still  rob  it 
of  its  benevolent  character  and  will  rob  it,  as  a  conse- 
quence, of  merit  ;  [e)  that  the  desire  for  happiness  in 
every  human  breast  vitiates  no  action,  that  pleasure  is 
good  or  bad  according  to  the  object  in  which  we  find  it ; 
(/)  that  duty  itself  is  just  one  of  those  ends  or  objects 
in  which  a  man  may  place  his  happiness  ;  (g)  that  duty 
is  not  the  only  moral  end  or  motive,  that,  in  every  act, 
as  there  is  a  positive  love  of  happiness,  so  there  must 
be  also  just  such  a  love  of  duty  as  keeps  us  from 
violating  duty,  but  that  duty  is  not  the  only  moral 
end  or  moral  principle.  These  are  simple  conceptions, 
and  they  are  easily  put  into  practice.  Under  the  law 
of  Formalism,  on  the  contrary,  the  world  must  simply 
come  to  a  standstill,  since  men  could  not  act  in  every 
case  out  of  the  pure  respect  for  law.  For  happiness  is 
an  ordinary  spring  of  human  action,  and  it  is  a  spring 
only  in  so  far  as  it  is  a  motive  of  action. 

(2)  In  his  second  proof  Kant  claims  that  the  true 
moral  motive  must  be  of  categorical  value  or  of  worth 
in  itself  and  not  as  means  merely  ;  also,  that  it  should 
be  of  universal  value,  i.e.,  of  value  for  all  men.  We 
shall  allow  these  two  conditions  of  the  true  moral  motive 
to  stand.  Let  us  see  to  what  conclusion  they  will  lead 
us.  He  contends  that  objects  outside  us  cannot  be  the 
supreme  motive,  i.e.,  that  the  act  is  not  moral  if  done 
for  their  sake,  because  objfects  outside  of  us  are  willed 
and  are  of  value  only  as  a  means  to  pleasure.  On  the 
other  hand,  pleasure  or  happiness  cannot  be  the  moral 
motive  because  though  of  value  and  desired  in  itself, 
and  not  as  a  mere  means  to  something  else,  it  yet  is  not 
of  value  for  all  men,  since  what  gives  pleasure  to  one 
man  will  not  give  it  to  another.  Now  the  conclusion 
that  forces  itself  on  us  is  quite  the  opposite  of  this. 
There  are,  as  we  shall  see  in  our  chapter  on  Hedonism, 
objects   which   are   not   desired   as   a   mere   means   to 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  271 

pleasure,  and  there  is  one  object  which  though  most 
desirable  could  never  be  desired  as  a  means  to  anything 
else,  viz.,  the  final  objective  end  ;  it  is  also  of  value 
to  all  men.  Hence  if  Kant's  two  conditions  are  true, 
the  final  objective  end  is  the  true  supreme  moral  motive. 
Again,  happiness  is  desired  by  all  men,  and  there  is  one 
happiness  that  all  men  must  desire,  viz.,  the  subjective 
final  end,  or  the  possession  of  the  infinite  good.  As  we 
have  shown,  this  final  happiness  cannot  be  wished  as  a 
mere  means.  Hence,  granted  Kant's  two  conditions,  we 
are  led  to  the  conclusion  that  an  act  should  be  morally 
good  if  it  leads  to,  and  is  desired  as  leading  to,  the  final 
end  objective  and  subjective,  which  is  the  view  of  morals 
which  we  have  expressed  from  the  beginning  of  this 
work. 

On  the  other  hand,  if  the  Kantian  conditions  hold 
true  then  the  law  of  Reason  cannot  be  the  supreme  moral 
motive.  It  is  wanting  at  least  in  the  first  of  the  required 
qualifications.  The  laws  of  human  Reason  are  all  mere 
means  ;  they  are  means  to  the  securing  of  happiness  or 
welfare.  They  are,  therefore,  not  of  value  in  and  for 
themselve. 

Granted,  therefore,  the  Kantian  conditions,  we  find 
that  they  themselves  exclude  what  is  to  him  the  only 
true  moral  motive,  viz.,  the  law  of  the  human  Reason. 


NOTE  ON   KANT  S   ARGUMENT 

It  has  been  sometimes  claimed  that  Kant  attempted  to 
establish  his  principle  (that  we  ought  to  do  duty  for  duty's 
sake)  in  a  third  way — namely,  through  the  concept  of  free- 
dom— his  argument,  it  is  said,  being  that,  since  the  will  is 
free  and  since  freedom  excludes  all  motivation  of  the  will 
from  sense,  and  therefore  excludes  all  motivation  by  pleasure, 
the  moral  motive  must  be  that  of  duty.  But  this  is  not  a 
true  statement  of  the  Kantian  position.  His  position  on  the 
point  is,  it  seems  to  us,  after  a  full  examination  of  it,  as 
follows  :  He  does  not  first  establish  the  freedom  of  the 
will  and  from  that  deduce  Formalism  as  a  conclusion,  but  he 
first  postulates  morality  in  the  sense  of  duty  for  duty's  sake. 


272  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

as  something  given,  something  we  know  through  intuition,  and 
then  he  postulates  freedom  as  a  necessary  condition  of  that. 
And  so  he  avoids  what  he  himself  tells  us  *  looks  like  a 
vicious  circle  "  from  which  we  find  it  (at  first  sight)  im- 
possible to  escape,"  the  apparent  circle  being  that  "  in  the 
order  of  efficient  causes  we  assume  ourselves  free  in  order, 
that  in  the  order  of  ends  we  may  conceive  ourselves  as  subject 
to  moral  laws,  and  then  conceive  ourselves  as  subjected  to 
these  laws,  because  we  have  attributed  to  ourselves  freedom 
of  the  will."  We  must  admit  that  Kant  successfully  avoids 
this  circle,  for  his  argument  is  that  we  start  out  from  the 
obligation  to  do  our  duty  for  duty's  sake  as  something 
revealed  in  our  inner  consciousness,  and  then  having  postu- 
lated freedom  in  the  noumenal  world  as  a  necessary  condition 
of  such  obligation,  Kant  simply  returns  to  see  how  through 
noumenal  freedom  that  same  moral  obligation  which  was 
previously  given  us  as  real  and  existent  in  our  consciousness 
is  possible.     In  this  there  is  no  vicious  circle. 


OTHER  ARGUMENTS  FOR  FORMALISM 

In  Hartmann  and  Whewell  f  we  find  two  distinct 
arguments  for  the  present  theory.  According  to  Hart- 
mann there  is  in  man  an  innate  respect  for  law,  and  an 
innate  impulse  to  fulfil  the  law  apart  altogether  from 
the  consideration  of  pleasurable  ends,  so  that  it  would 
seem  natural  and  right  that  this  instinctive  respect 
should  be  made  supreme  in  every  human  action. 

Reply — ^We  do  not  admit  that  nature  has  supplied 
mankind  with  an  innate  respect  for  anything,   but  we 

*  Abbot,  page  69. 

t  Hegel's  argument  for  Stoicism  runs  (page  127,  "  Phil,  of  Right  "). 
"  Since  the  good  is  the  essence  of  the  will  of  the  particular  subject  it 
is  his  obligation.  As  the  good  is  distinct  from  particularity,  and  par- 
ticularity occurs  in  the  subjective  will,  the  good  has  at  the  outset 
only  the  character  of  universal  abstract  essence.  This  abstract 
universal  is  duty.  Hence,  duty  as  is  required  by  its  character  must 
be  done  for  duty's  sake." 

Fichte's  argument  is  briefly  the  following  :  There  is  in  man  a 
natural  impulse  to  perfect  independence  of  himself.  Hence,  the  im- 
pul.sc  of  the  ego  is  towards  self-determination,  towards  independence 
of  external  ends,  ends  that  1  do  not  give  myself,  but  wliich  are  given 
me.  In  its  formal  and  full  jxirfi-ction,  howcvfr,  this  independence 
to  which  the  soul  is  impelled  is  the  complete  realisation  of  duty  for 
duty's  sake.  As  Fichtc  puts  it,  the  ego  must  pursue  freedom  (from 
objects)  simply  because  it  is  ego. 


THE  KANTIAN  FORMALISM  273 

do  admit  that  we  have  an  innate  love  of  the  good,  in 
the  sense  that  the  will  cannot  help  wishing  the  good. 
But  let  us  suppose  that  we  are  endowed  by  nature  with 
this  innate  respect  for  law  of  which  Hartmann  speaks, 
and  even  with  an  innate  impulse  to  fulfil  the  law  apart 
from  the  consideration  of  ends — what  follows  ?  It 
follows  merely  that  we  are  bound  in  all  things  first 
and  before  all  to  observe  the  law,  and  to  do  nothing 
in  contravention  of  it,  to  do  all  according  to  law.  It 
does  not  follow  that  we  should  do  all  for  the  sake  of 
law. 

Whewell's  argument  is  the  following :  "  Moral 
goodness  is  that  quality  of  an  act  which  puts  it  in  con- 
formity with  the  supreme  rule  of  virtue,  which  belongs, 
therefore,  to  man  as  man — that  is,  to  the  whole  man ; 
and  which  must  have,  therefore,  for  its  principle  the 
supreme  rule  itself — that  is,  be  done  out  of  the  love  of 
virtue." 

Reply — Again  our  answer  is  that  we  cannot  from  the 
fact  that  moral  virtue  belongs  to  man  as  man  deduce 
the  conclusion  that,  therefore,  we  must  do  all  things  for 
the  sake  of  virtue,  but  only  that  all  that  we  do  ought 
to  be  virtuous — i.e.,  that  what  we  do  ought  to  accord 
with  virtue.  One  might  as  well  say  that  because 
eating  belongs  to  us  as  animal  we  should  on  that  ac- 
count always  eat  in  order  to  satisfy  our  animal  nature. 
We  may  eat  for  any  purpose  we  like,  provided  we  do 
not  injure  our  animal  nature. 

We  believe  that  we  have  now  adduced  all  the  proofs 

worth    noting    in    defence    of    the    Kantian    theory    of 

Formalism.     In  general  this  theory  of  duty  for  duty's 

sake  is  not  defended  by  argument,  but  is  assumed  as 

a  postulate,  which  does  not  need  to  be  proved,  since  it 

represents  the  noblest  and  purest  of  all  moral  systems. 

But  we  have  shown  that  Formalism  is  anything  but  a 

pure  system  either  in  itself  or  in  its  consequences,  since 

to  do  a  thing  for  the  sake  of  law  is  to  do  a  thing  for  the 
Vol.  I— 18 


274  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

sake  of  that  which  may  be  either  bad  or  good.  Kant's 
view  has  often  been  extolled  as  a  noble  and  a  generous 
theory  because  of  its  exclusion  of  the  selfish  element 
from  human  action.  But  the  "  self "  is  necessary  in 
every  act.  For  the  "  self"  is  the  principle  of  the  human 
act,  and  action  is  possible  to  us  only  on  the  condition  of 
its  bringing  us  happiness.  Selfishness  in  this  sense  we 
can  never  exclude  from  human  action. 

To  sum  up  this  long  and  complex  argument,  we  reject 
the  present  theory — the  theory,  namely,  that  an  act 
to  be  morally  good  should  be  done  for  the  sake  of  duty, 
first,  because  of  the  arguments  adducible  in  disproof  of 
it — it  demands  too  much  of  human  nature,  it  is  not 
contained  in  the  idea  of  the  moral  good,  it  does  not 
allow  for  the  morality  of  works  of  supererogation,  it 
reduces  all  individual  acts  to  a  dead  level  of  morality, 
it  excludes  merit  with  our  fellow-men,  it  makes  moral 
evil  impossible,  it  conflicts  with  the  natural  desire  of 
the  will  for  happiness,  it  takes  no  account  of  the  possi- 
bility of  bad  legislation.  Secondly,  we  reject  it  because 
the  arguments  used  in  support  of  it  are  fallacious. 
Formalism  is  not  the  creed  of  the  crowd.  On  the  con- 
trary, it  violates  our  commonest  moral  susceptibilities. 
Also  it  is  built  on  the  false  assumptions  that  all  objects 
are  a  means  to  pleasure,  and  that  there  is  no  common 
law  of  happiness  for  different  men,  no  object  which 
will  ^ive  happiness  to  aU. 


CHAPTER  X 

ON  HEDONISM 

"  Hedonism  "  is  the  theory  that  pleasure  *  is  the  final 
end  of  man.  Recent  writers  on  Ethics  distinguish  two 
systems  of  Hedonism — that  of  egoistic  and  that  of 
universalistic  Hedonism.  The  first  is  the  doctrine  that 
the  end  of  each  man  is  his  own  personal  pleasure.  The 
second  is  that  the  end  of  the  individual  is  the  pleasure 
of  the  whole  race.  But  many  Ethical  writers  use  the 
word  "  Hedonism "  to  signify  the  first  theory  only, 
and  Utilitarimism  to  signify  the  second.  It  is  in  its 
purely  egoistic  sense  that  we  shall  use  the  term  Hedon- 
ism in  this  chapter.  The  theory,  therefore,  which  we 
are  now  about  to  examine  is  the  theory  that  the  end  of 
each  man  is  his  own  pleasure,  and  that  every  act  is  good 
which  promotes  that  pleasure.  In  the  next  chapter  we 
shall  discuss  Utilitarianism. 

There  are  many  forms  of  the  Hedonistic  theory,  for 
"  pleasure  "  has  many  meanings.  It  may  range  in  its 
varieties  of  signification  from  the  gratification  of  man's 
merely  animal  instincts  to  the  happiness  which  the  soul . 
enjoys  in  contemplating  its  Creator.  We  might  thus 
form  an  ascending  scale  of  theories  of  Hedonism,  each 
degree  being  further  removed  than  its  predecessor  from 

•  On  page  53  we  distinguished  between  objective  end  or  the  thing 
which  is  desired,  subjective  end  or  happiness  (f{ daifj.ov(a) ,  i.e.,  the 
attaining,  and  in  some  cases  retaining,  of  the  end  desired  or  the  satis- 
faction of,  desire,  and,  thirdly,  pleasure  (t}5o«'^)  or  the  glow  of  feeling 
which  in  some,  and  only  some,  cases  accompanies  the  attainment  of 
th'e  end  desired.  Hedonism,  as  our  definition  given  above  shows,  is 
the  theory  that  pleasure  in  this  sense  is  the  final  end  of  man.  Most 
Hedonists  however,  draw  no  very  clear  distinction  between  attaining 
an  end  and  the  pleasurable  feeling  accompanying  or  following  from 
that  act.     Often,  too,  they  speak  of  this  feeling  as  happiness. 

27s 


276  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

material  self-indulgence,  and  nearer  to  the  highest  and 
most  purely  intellectual  pleasure  of  which  a  rational 
creature  is  capable.  A  few  examples  will  suggest  how 
such  a  scale  might  be  constructed.* 

(i)  There  is  the  crude  Hedonism  of  Hobbes'  "  State 
of  Nature,"  as  described  by  him  in  the  Leviathan. 
"  Whatsoever,"  f  he  says,  "  is  the  object  of  any  man's 
desire  that  is  it  which  he  for  his  part  calleth  good."  In 
the  State  of  Nature,  therefore,  every  end  was  good. 
And  in  this  State  of  Nature  not  only  was  such  object 
called  good,  but  it  was  really  good,  and  there  was  no 
other  good.  There  could  be  no  cruder  form  of  Hedon- 
ism than  this.  It  recognised  no  controlling  law  what- 
soever in  pleasure  or  desire. 

(2)  The  Hedonism  of  Aristippus  (leader  of  the 
Cyrenaic  School  of  Philosophy  in  the  ancient  Greek 
world)  at  least  recognised  some  law  of  preference  in 
pleasure.  It  denied  that  purely  bodily  pleasure  was 
man's  end,  and  gave  the  preference  to  mental  pleasure. 
But  Aristippus  insisted  that  pleasure  is  the  end  of  man. 
This  is  a  higher  type  of  theory  than  Hobbes',  but  it  does 
not  make  a  qualitative  distinction  between  pleasures  as 
our  next  example  (Mill)  does,  for  Aristippus  held  that 
the  difference  between  bodily  and  mental  pleasure  was 
one  of  quantity  only. 

(3)  Mill  goes  farther  than  Hobbes  or  Aristippus,  since 
he  asserts  a  qualitative  distinction  between  pleasures  as 

♦  Egoistic  theories  have  not  grown  more  refined  with  time.  Per- 
haps the  most  offensive  of  all  Egoistic  theories  was  that  put  forward 
as  late  as  1844  by  Max  Stimcr  in  his  work  "  Der  Einzige  und  scin 
Eigenthum  " — a  work  in  which  the  individual  is  regarded  as  not  only 
the  end  of  his  own  action  but  as  the  only  thing  in  the  world.  To  the 
individual,  according  to  Stimcr,  the  world  is  only  a  dream — it  exists 
for  him  alone.     It  is  his  property.     He  has  no  duties  towards  it. 

I  In  Aristotle's  theory  also,  "  good  "  is  the  "  object  of  appetite." 
But  Aristotle  recognises  a  hierarchy  of  appetites  and  of  ends,  and, 
just  as  in  the  case  of  any  particular  project  we  regard  a  means  as 
gctod  only  in  so  far  as  it  leads  us  to  our  end,  and  count  any  course, 
nowever  pleasurable  in  itself,  a  wrong  and  evil  means  which  leads 
us  from  our  end,  so,  also,  though  the  good  is  the  object  of  appetite, 
wc  count  any  object,  however  p!ea.surable,  as  bad  if  it  leads  us  from 
our  final  end. 


ON  HEDONISM  277 

man's  end — an  ethically  preferential  scale  of  pleasures, 
the  higher  pleasure  counting  more  than  a  lower  of  even 
greater  strength  and  duration.  Such  a  S5^stem  is  more 
refined  necessarily  than  one  that  recognises  as  the 
criterion  of  the  good  mere  strength  and  duration,  &c., 
in  pleasure, 

(4)  A  still  higher  form  of  Hedonism  is  that  adopted 
by  those  philosophers  who  claim  special  consideration 
for  a  special  high  kind  of  pleasure,  a  pleasure  which  it 
is  asserted  outweighs  all  other  kinds — the  pleasure  of  a 
good  conscience. 

(5)  A  higher  form  still  is  that  which  Butler  advocates 
— the  Hedonism  which  includes  in  its  calculus  of 
pleasures  those  which  we  are  to  receive  in  heaven  as'  a 
reward  of  good  action.  His  theory  has  been  called  a 
theory  of  "  long-sighted  selfishness." 

An  attempt  to  make  an  exhaustive  classification  of 
Ethicians  according  to  the  scheme  which  we  have  drawn 
up  here  will  present  many  difficulties.  For  instance, 
some  of  the  most  famous  Ethical  theories  are  not 
worked  out  consistently  by  their  authors,  and  at  some 
points  will  appear  to  belong  to  one  grade,  at  some 
points  to  another  grade.  Thus,  Spinoza  starts  with 
Hedonism  pure  and  simple,  and  ends  as  a  Stoic,  for, 
according  to  Spinoza,  though  pleasure  is  the  end,  our 
pleasure  must  be  to  realise  the  soul — i.e.,  to  desire  virtue 
for  virtue's  sake.  Butler  is  a  hedonist,  and  yet  he  tells 
us  that  if  we  seek  pleasure  it  will  fly  from  us.  But  the 
scheme  will  be  useful  as  showing  the  variety  of  views 
included  under  Hedonism. 

It  may  be  well  to  give  the  reader,  at  tliis  point,  a  brief 
historical  account  of  some  views  of  hedonists.  A  fuller 
knowledge  of  the  views  of  hedonists  can  be  got  by  the 
student  in  Sidgwick  s  little  "  History  of  Ethics,"  from  which 
we  have  taken  nearly  all  the  contents  of  this  note. 

(i)  The  SocRATic  Schools. — {a)  Aristippus  taught  that 
virtue  is  the  pleasure-producing.  There  are  no  qualitative 
differences  in  pleasures.  Yet  mental  pleasures  are  better 
than  bodily— because  intenser.     (6)  Antisthenes  taught  that 


278  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

{Measure  is  evil.     Virtue  is  spiritual  independence  of  body  or 
of  pleasure. 

(2)  Plato. — In  the  Protagoras  he  insists  that  pleasure  is 
the  good.  In  the  Phcedo  he  goes  to  the  opposite  extreme, 
saying — it  cannot  be  good,  since  all  pleasure  has  pain  mixed 
with  it.  In  the  Republic  and  the  Laws  he  takes  a  middle 
view,  maintaining  that  pleasure  is  not  the  "  good,'  but  that 
pleasure  and  the  good  harmonise.  The  best,  he  tells  us,  is 
also  the  "  pleasantest." 

(3)  Aristotle. — Pleasure  is  an  accident,  but  an  inseparable 
accident,  of  all  natural  weU-being,  but  it  is  not  the  end.  The 
end  is  function. 

(4)  Stoics. — Pleasure  is  not  the  end,  because  it  is  only  a 
result  of  a  natural  impulse  to  an  end.  To  the  wise  man 
pleasure  is  not  even  a  good.  But  though  positive  pleasure 
is  not  a  good  worth  striving  for,  negative  pleasure — i.e., 
the  serenity  of  virtue — is  worth  striving  for. 

(5)  Epicureans. — The  pleasure  of  the  individual  is  the 
only  good.  Body  is  the  source  of  all  pleasure.  But  mental 
pleasures  though  not  specifically  distinct  from  bodily  are 
greater  than  any  others,  because  mind,  besides  present 
pleasures,  has  also  the  pleasures  of  memory  and  of  antici- 
pation.    The  pleasure  of  our  whole  life  is  our  end. 

(6)  HoBBES. — The  theoretical  ends  of  action  are  pleasure 
and  self-preservation.  The  practical  rule  of  action  for  the 
gaining  of  these  ends  is  the  sovereign's  will. 

(7)  CuDWORTH. — True  happiness  is  the  "  pleasure  which 
the  soul  derives  from  the  sense  of  virtue." 

(8)  Cumberland  was  the  first  to  substitute  for  the 
individual  the  common  good  (consisting  of  happiness  and 
perfection)  as  end  of  all.  From  his  time  Hedonism  in  Eng- 
land was  more  Universalistic  than  Egoistic. 

(9)  Locke. — Our  own  pleasure  is  the  end,  but  as  subject 
to  law. 

(10)  Shaftesbury  was  the  first  philosopher  to  build  an 
Ethics  on  the  distinction  of  two  impulses  in  man — one  of 
self-love,  the  other  of  benevolence.  The  "  good  "  is  their 
harmony.  He  could  only  be  called  a  hedonist  in  so  far  as 
he  claimed  an  equal  prominence  for  the  selfish  and  benevolent 
impulses. 

(11)  Butler. — There  are  two  regulative  principles  in  man 
— self-love  and  conscience.  If  they  conflict,  conscience  must 
jdeld.  Yet  self-love  is  not  so  reliable  as  conscience,  and  on 
that  score  conscience  may  sometimes  not  yield  to  self-love. 

(12)  HUTCHESON. — A   purely   self-regarding   act   is   never 


ON  HEDONISM  279 

morally  good.  It  is  at  best  indifferent.  Yet  private  happi- 
ness and  benevolence  must  harmonise.  To  this  extent  he  is 
a  hedonist.  Unlike  Shaftesbury,  he  denies  that  there  is  in 
the  purely  benevolent  impulses  any  touch  of  self-love. 

(13)  Hume,  in  his  later  works,  admits  that  there  are  purely 
disinterested  impulses  in  men,  but  denies  that  they  can  be- 
come active  except  through  self-love.  Moral  consciousness 
is  only  pleasurable  emotion. 

(14)  Reio. — There  are  two  regulative  principles  in  man — 
self-love  and  conscience.  Self-love  can  never  be  subordinate 
to  conscience.  Yet  if  they  conflict  we  are  in  the  dilemma 
whether  it  is  better  to  be  a  fool  or  a  knave. 

Other  writers  often  mentioned  in  connection  with  Hedonism 
— v.g.,  Paley,  Bentham,  Mill — are  Utilitarians,  not  Hedonists. 
Their  Utilitarianism,  however,  is  built  on  Hedonism. 

Besides  the  differences  of  hedonists  on  the  nature  of 
the  pleasure  that  constitutes  our  end,  there  are  other 
differences  amongst  them,  one  of  which  differences  will 
be  prominent  in  this  present  chapter,  when  we  come  to 
make  a  formal  criticism  of  Hedonism.  It  has  been  held 
by  some  (Psychological  hedonists)  that  pleasure  is  the 
only  end  which  man  is  capable  of  desiring  ;  by  others 
(Ethical  hedonists)  that  pleasure  is  the  only  end  which 
man  ought  to  desire,  although  it  is  possible  for  him  to 
desire  other  things. 

We  propose  in  this  section  to  prove  that  pleasure  is 
not  even  that  which  ought  to  be  the  sole  end,  and  from 
this  it  will  follow  manifestly  that  pleasure  is  not  man's 
only  possible  end. 

Our  proof  that  pleasure  is  not  the  only  end  which  we 
"  ought  "  to  desire  will  consist  in  showing  that  pleasure 
is  not  our  sole  natural  end.  If  we  have  other  natural 
ends  beside  pleasure  it  is  impossible  that  pleasure  is  the 
only  end  which  ought  to  be  sought. 

{a)  Pleasure — Not    the    Sole    Natural    End    of 

Desire 

This  proposition  directly  contradicts  the  fundamental 
assumption  of  all  forms  of  Hedonism.    A  remarkable 


28o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

defence  of  this  proposition — one  of  the  subtlest  passages 
in  Scholastic  Philosophy — is  to  be  found  in  "  Summa 
Contra  Gentiles  "  (Book  III.,  Chap.  26).  The  defence 
forms  part  of  the  series  of  arguments  by  which  St. 
Thomas  Aquinas  proves  the  thesis  that  the  attainment 
of  happiness  (and  by  happiness  he  means  the  attainment 
of  our  final  natural  end)  consists  in  an  act  of  intellect, 
not  of  will.  Now,  since  pleasure  resides  in  the  will, 
and  is  the  principal  act  of  will,  some  of  the  arguments 
by  which  St.  Thomas  establishes  his  thesis  consist  in 
proving  that  the  final  natural  end  of  man  is  not  pleasure. 
It  is  these  latter"  arguments  that  we  shall  here  reproduce, 
and  we  shall  take  them  in  the  following  order  : — 

(i)  Argument  derived  from  the  fact  that  the  will's 
object  or  end  is  prior  to  the  will's  pleasure. 

(2)  Argument  derived  from  the  fact  that  the  will's 
object  or  end  is  a  thing  distinct  from  the  "  rest  "  or 
quiescence  that  follows  on  the  attainment  of  the 
object. 

(3)  Argument  derived  from  the  distinction  between 
true  and  false  pleasure. 

(4)  Argument  derived  from  the  equal  or  indifferent 
Ethical  value  of  the  means  employed  if  pleasure  were 
the  final  end. 

(5)  Argument  from  analogy  of  Nature's  general  use 
of  pleasure  as  a  means  only. 

ST.    THOMAS   AQUINAS'    ARGUMENTS 

I.  Argument  derived  from  the  fact  that  the  will's 
object  or  end  is  prior  to  the  will's  pleasure.    ■  x-j.  j.  i  10,^2  ^  ) 

In  this  argument  St.  Thomas  proves  that  not  only  is 
pleasure  not  our  sole  natural  end,  but  that  it  cannot  be 
our  primary  end.  » 

Every  power  that  is  moved  to  its  act  by  objects  is 
subject  to  the  law  that  object  precedes  act  as  mover  pre- 
cedes movement,  not  necessarily  in  the  order  of  time, 
but  psychologically  in  the  order  of  willing.     To   make 


ON  HEDONISM  281 

our  meaning  plain  we  shall  give  some  examples.  The 
object  of  vision  precedes  the  act  of  vision,  not  in  time 
necessarily,  but  in  the  meaning  given  above — that  is, 
we  see  the  object  before  we  know  that  we  see  it.  Simi- 
larly we  know  the  object  of  intellect  before  we  under- 
stand the  act  of  intellect.*  Now,  the  will,  like  vision 
and  intellect,  is  moved  to  its  act  by  objects.  There- 
fore, the  object  of  will  precedes  the  act  of  the  will,  in 
the  sense  that  the  will  must  desire  the  object  before  it 
can  desire  its  own  act  in  which  pleasure  is  contained. 
But  the  primary  object  of  will  is  also  its  last  end,  since 
the  primary  object  is  sought  for  its  own  sake,  which  is 
our  very  definition  of  the  final  end.f 

Therefore,  far  from  pleasure  being  our  sole  natural 
end,  we  have  shown  that  an  object  distinct  from  pleasure 
must  be  desired  before  the  desire  for  pleasure  becomes 
possible,  and  this  object  is  a  natural  object  of  desire. 
We  may  also  infer  that  the  final  natural  end  of  man 
cannot  be  pleasure,  but  something  distinct  from  pleasure, 
since  the  final  end  must  be  the  primary  object  of  our 
desire. 

This  theory  may  be  objected  to  by  reasoning  as 
follows  ;  A  man  may  reflect  on  his  own  act  and  take 
the  ends  or  objects  of  nature  in  any  order  he  likes. 
Therefore,  though  in  the  order  of  nature  we  must  first 
know  or  desire  the  object  of  a  faculty  before  we  can 
know  or  desire  the  pleasure  attaching  to  the  act  of  the 
faculty,  we  may,  nevertheless,  by  this  power  of  reflec- 
tion which  belongs  to  all  knowing  subjects,  reverse  the 
order  of  nature  and  make  the  act  of  desire  or  the  pleasure 
of  the  act  our  principal  and  primary  end.  Hence 
pleasure  can  become  our  primary  end. 

The  answer  to  this  difficulty  is  to  be  found  in  argu- 
ment 3  of  the  "  Summa  Contra  Gentiles."  It  is  as 
follows :     Such   a   reversal   of   the   order   of   nature   is, 

*  "  S.  Theol.,"  1.,  Q.  LXXXVIL,  Art.  3. 

t  Means  are  sought  not  lor  their  own  sake  but  as  leading  to  the 
end,  and  they  are  sought  always  in  a  secondary  and  later  act. 


282  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

indeed,  possible  to  man.  But  this  fact  in  no  way 
interferes  with  our  thesis  that  the  primary  and  natural 
object  of  the  will  is  some  good  distinct  from  the  will 
or  any  quality  of  the  act  of  the  will.  The  intellect, 
St.  Thomas  tells  us,  in  order  to  act — that  is,  in  order 
to  understand — must  understand  some  object.  And 
to  know  its  act — that  is,  to  know  that  it  understands — 
would  be  quite  impossible  did  it  not  first  understand 
some  object  distinct  from  its  own  act.  And  as  the 
desire  of  the  will  from  which  our  first  pleasure  is  to 
result  must  be  the  desire  of  some  object,  therefore,  the 
will,  like  the  intellect,  could  not  in  its  first  act  *  desire 
its  own  act,  or  any  condition  or  quality  of  its  own  act. 
Therefore,  as  pleasure  is  a  quality  of  the  will's  act, 
pleasure  cannot  be  our  primary  end.  The  first  desire, 
then,  must  regard  some  object  which  is  outside  the  will. 
This  object  will  be  the  natural  end  of  will.  If  later  by 
reflection  we  make  pleasure  our  principal  end,  the  object 
outside  the  will  must  still  remain  principal  and  final  in 
the  order  of  nature. 

A  few  words  on  the  limits  of  this  power  of  reflection 
of  which  St.  Thomas  speaks  will  not  be  out  of  place. 
An  intellectual  being  is  gifted  with  the  full  power  of 
reflection  on  his  own  acts,  and  hence  an  intellectual 
being,  having  once  had  his  first  desire  determined  by 
some  outer  object,  may,  afterwards,  completely  break 
up  the  order  of  nature,  make  pleasure  his  principal  end, 
and  seek  objects  as  means  to  pleasure.  A  man  may, 
for  instance,  determine  that  to-morrow  he  will  have  a 
pleasant  day,  and  then  think  out  the  objects  that  will 

•  And  not  only  our  first  act  of  will  but  also  all  subsequent  un- 
reflecting acts  have,  as  their  object,  something  other  than  pleasure. 
This  theory  of  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  concerning  the  primary  and 
natural  object  of  the  will  is  supported  by  many  recent  ethicians, 
notably  by  Ed  von  Hartmann  in  "  Ethische  Studien."  "If  we 
consider  the  will,"  he  writes,  page  136,  "  with  its  concrete  and  varied 
content,  we  shall  find  that  the  more  instinctive,  naive  and  unreflecting 
the  will  is,  the  less  do  pleasure  and  pain  enter  into  our  conscious  ends. 
...  If  pleasure  and  pain  do  result  from  action,  they  are  only  acci- 
dental bye-phenomena  of  the  instinctive  will,  not  essential  factors  ia 
the  content  of  conscious  desire." 


ON  HEDONISM  283 

best  promote  his  pleasure.  Still,  the  order  that  obtains 
in  his  first  act  will  for  the  most  part  obtain  in  those 
subsequent  acts  which  may  be  described  as  spontaneous, 
natural,  and  unreflecting.  In  such  acts  man's  desire  is 
mostly  for  objects,  not  for  pleasure.  The  desire  for 
pleasure  comes  from  reflection.  But  sense  does  not 
enjoy  this  full  power  of  reflection.  Some  senses,  indeed, 
have  no  power  of  reflection  whatsoever.  The  eye,  for 
instance,  cannot  know  that  it  sees.  Nevertheless,  even 
a  pure  sense-being  like  the  dog  or  the  horse  can  in  some 
measure  reflect  upon  itself,  and  so  an  animal  may  desire 
its  own  pleasure.  But  the  act  of  sense,  like  that  of 
intellect,  must  primarily  and  fundamentally  regard  an 
outer  object,  and  its  first  act  in  time  must  regard  an 
outer  object  alone.  The  animal,  as  we  have  already 
pointed  out,  is  first  drawn  to  its  food — not  to  the 
pleasure  which  food  affords.  In  the  first  movement  of 
appetite  the  animal  has  not  as  yet  experienced  pleasure, 
and,  therefore  it  could  not  desire  pleasure.  Now,  the 
object  of  its  first  act  is  the  fundamental  natural  object 
of  the  appetite.  And  hence  the  primary  natural  end  of 
the  sensuous  appetites  cannot  be  pleasure.  But  when 
experience  has  taught  the  animal  that  allied  to  food 
and  other  objects  is  pleasure,  it  may  'in  all  its  future 
acts  be  drawn,  not,  indeed,  to  pleasure  purely  and 
simply  (for  sense  is  not,  like  intellect,  analytic,  and, 
therefore,  it  cannot  separate  in  thought  pleasure  from 
the  object),  but  to  the  whole  experienced  psychosis — 
object  and  imagined  pleasure  in  one.  What  prominence 
the  pleasure  may  assume  in  that  whole  complex  object 
it  is  not  easy  to  say  ;  but  all  observation  would  lead  us 
to  the  opinion  that  to  the  animal  the  object  remains 
always  principal,  that  the  imagination  of  the  hungry 
dog  is  fixed  more  on  the  food  than  on  the  pleasure  which 
is  to  be  got  by  eating,  no  matter  how  vivid  its  imagina- 
tion of  pleasure  may  be.  Even  in  man  when  animal 
passion  is  at  its  strongest,  and  man  is  under  the  sway 
of  sense,   when,   for  instance,  in  his  anger  he  seeks  to 


284  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

revenge  himself  on  an  opponent,  it  is  not  the  pleasure  to 
come  that  mostly  occupies  his  mind  but  the  object  or 
end  which  he  wishes  to  attain.  But  intellect  can  analyse 
the  sense  psychosis  and  pursue  the  sense  pleasure  for  its 
own  sake. 

It  is  not  true,  then,  as  some  have  stated,  that 
pleasures  cannot  be  imagined  or  pursued  for  their 
own  sake.  Pleasures  may  be  sought  both  by  animal 
and  by  man,  but  the  seeking  of  pleasure  is  not  the 
primary  natural  object  of  appetite  whether  sensuous 
or  intellectual. 

II.  Argument  derived  from  the  will's  object  as  distinct 
from  the  "  rest  "  or  quiescence  that  follows  on  the  attain- 
ment of  the  end. 

There  are  three  possible  acts  of  an  appetitive  faculty 
—love,  desire,  and  pleasure.  None  of  these  can  be 
either  the  primary  end  of  the  faculty  or  the  final  end 
(summum  bonum)  of  man.  Love  and  desire  could  not 
be  the  end  because  they  are  natural  tendencies  towards, 
and  naturally  progress  into,  pleasure.  They  are  essen- 
tially relative.  Pleasure,  on  the  other  hand,  is  the 
feeling  of  "  rest  "  *  which  follows  on  the  attainment  of 
the  end.  It  is  the  "  quies  appetitus  in  bono  possesso  " — 
in  bono  possesso  (whether  this  possession  be  present 
actual  possession,  or  only  the  recollection  of  possession 
in  the  past,  or  the  imagination  of  a  possession  in  the 
future).  This  feeling  of  rest  that  follows  on -attainment 
presupposes  the  attainment  of  the  end  desired.  It  is 
not,  therefore,  itself  the  end. 

The  proposition  that  the  primary  end  of  the  will  is 
not  the  feeling  of  "  rest  "  that  results  from  the  action 
of  the  will  is  only  a  particular  case  of  the  more  universal 
statement  that  the  "  end  "  of  movement  is  not  the 
"  rest  "  that  supervenes  on  movement.  The  "  end  " 
of    physical     movement     is    place — not     merely     rest  ; 

•  It  must  be  rcmcmlx^rod  that  by  quies  or  rest  St.  Thomas  Aquinas 
dofs  I  ot  mean  mere  cessjilion  from  movement  or  action,  but  rest  in 
an  end  attained,  and  still  possessed,  and  chmg  to  (adhacsio). 


ON  HEDONISM  285 

physical  movement  could  not  begin  if  mere  rest  were 
its  end,  for  a  body  rests  as  much  before  starting  as  at 
the  end.  This  is  true  also  of  the  will's  movement. 
St.  Thomas  tells  us  that  "  if  the  -principal  aim  of  nature 
were  to  secure  (the  subjective  state  of)  pleasure  for  the 
will  (pleasure  being  the  "  rest  "  of  the  appetite  in  the 
attainment  of  a  good  desired)  nature  would  never  have 
given  the  inclination  to  the  will "  (that  is,  the  in- 
clination towards  its  end).  This  brings  us  once  more  to 
the  conclusion  that  pleasure  is  not  man's  primary 
natural  end. 

III.  The  third  argument  is  derived  from  the  distinc- 
tion between  true  and  false  pleasures.  "  Everything," 
writes  St.  Thomas,  "  has  the  truth  of  its  nature  by 
having  the  constituents  of  its  substance.  For  a  real 
man  differs  from  a  painted  man  by  the  constituents  of 
the  substance  of  man."  Now,  pleasure  is  defined  as  the 
"  rest  of  an  appetite  in  the  possession  of  a  good,"  and, 
therefore,  a  true  pleasure  implies  not  only  the  "  rest  " 
of  an  appetite,  but  "  rest  "  in  a  true  good — these  being 
the  constituents  of  pleasure.  Now,  as  mere  states  of 
the  appetite — that  is,  as  "  mere  rest  " — all  pleasures 
are  equally  true.  All  pleasures  imply  the  repose  of 
an  appetite  in  something.  Merely  as  a  state  of  the 
appetite,  as  quiescence,  the  pleasure  of  drunkenness  is 
as  true  as  the  pleasure  of  wisdom.  But  pleasures  are 
distinguished  as  true  or  false  according  as  the  appetite 
rests  in  a  true  or  a  false  good — that  is,  according  as  it 
rests  in  a  good  which  leads  to  our  final  end,  and,  there- 
fore, truly  perfects  our  nature,  or  leads  away  from  the 
final  end,  and,  therefore,  destroys  our  nature.  The 
pleasure  of  drunkenness  is  a  false  pleasure,  because  the 
good  of  it  is  only  apparent — i.e.,  it  leads  to  the  loss  of 
our  final  end,  and  consequently  leads  to  our  destruction. 
That  of  wisdom  is  a  true  pleasure  because  it  leads  to 
our  final  end  and  perfects  us  in  relation  to  the  final  end. 
And  as  the  final  natural  end  of  man  is  always  and 
necessarily  the  true  good,  and  excludes  evil,  it  follows 


286  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

that  pleasure,  which  may  be  either  true  or  false,  cannot 
be  man's  final  end.* 

The  following  analogy  t  rnay  help  us  to  understand 
St.  Thomas'  distinction  between  true  and  false  pleasures. 
All  movement  is,  as  movement,  a  real  progress  towards 
something.  Still  there  is  a  distinction  of  real  and 
apparent,  or  right  and  wrong  progress  according  as  it 
is  or  is  not  progress  towards  the  particular  end  which 
we  wish  to  attain.  The  man  who  while  intending  to  go 
East  by  mistake  goes  West  is  not  progressing  truly. 
Hence,  mere  "  movement  "  as  such  could  not  be  the  end 
of  one  who  wishes  to  reach  an  end,  since  movement 
may  not  be  true  progress  for  such  a  person.  So,  also, 
"  pleasure  "  as  such,  being  neither  true  nor  false,  cannot 
be  the  natural  end  or  object  of  desire. 

IV.  The  fourth  argument  is  derived  from  the  equal  or 
indifferent  ethical  value  of  the  means  employed  if  pleasure 
were  the  final  end.  Let  us  suppose  for  a  moment  that 
pleasure  is  the  sole  natural  end,  and  that,  therefore, 
the  first  law  of  nature  is  to  seek  for  pleasure,  making 
all  other  ends  a  means  to  pleasure.  Under  these  cir- 
cumstances a  man  would,  in  the  exercise  of  a  faculty, 
fully  satisfy  the  claims  of  nature  if  he  could  succeed  in 
sustaining  the  pleasure  apart  from  the  realisation  of  the 
object  or  objective  end  of  the  faculty.  If,  for  instance, 
pleasure  were  the  end  of  man,  then  a  man  would  fully 
Batisfy  the  intentions  of  nature  by  sustaining  (were  it 
possible)  the  pleasures  of  the  stomach  apart  from  eating  ; 
or  sustaining  the  pleasure  of  the  sexual  faculty  apart 
from  the  end  of  that  faculty — the  good  of  the  race. J 

•  St.  Thomas  goes  on  to  show  that  the  distinguishing  of  true  from 
false  pleasures  belongs  not  to  will  but  to  intellect,  from  which  he  con- 
cludes not  only  that  pleasure  is  not  our  imal  end,  but  that  our  final 
end  consists  in  the  good  of  the  intellect.  With  this  aspect  of  St. 
Thomas'  argument  we  have  here  nothing  to  do, 

t  The  analogy  is  our  own,  not  St.  Thomas'. 

J  Wc  sometimes  find  Hedonism  described  as  a  low  and  brutal 
system  of  morals,  because  of  the  code  to  which  it  leads.  It  would 
lead,  it  is  stated,  to  lying,  fornication,  &c.,  because  in  many  cases 
these  acts  bring  only  pleasure,  and  tliey  would,  therefore,  on  the 
theory  of  Hedonism,  be  justifiable.     To  our  mind   there  is  always 


ON  HEDONISM  287 

But  the  result  would  necessarily  be  the  starvation  and 
death  of  the  individual  in  the  one  case,  and  the  disap- 
pearance of  the  race  in  the  other — results  that  cannot 
be  in  accordance  with  the  intentions  of  nature,  since  the 
clear  purpose  of  nature  is  that  we  may  live.  St.  Thomas 
puts  the  argument  very  briefly  :  "  If  delight  were  the 
last  end,  it  would  be  desirable  of  itself.  But  that  is 
false,  for  it  makes  a  difference  what  delight  is  desired, 
considering  the  object  from  which  the  delight  ensues  ; 
for  the  delight  which  follows  upon  good  and  desirable 
activities  is  good  and  desirable,  but  that  which  follows 
upon  evil  activities  is  evil  and  to  be  shunned.  Delight, 
therefore,  has  its  goodness  and  desirabiUty  from  some- 
thing beyond  itself.  Therefore,  it  is  not  the  final  end — 
happiness."  * 

V.  Argument  from  Nature's  general  use  of  pleasure  as 
a  means  only. 

"  The  right  order  f  of  things  coincides  with  the  order 
of  nature,  for  natural  things  are  ordained  to  their  end 
without  mistakes.  But  in  natural  things  delight  (or 
pleasure)  is  for  activity,  and  not  the  other  way  about : 
for  we  see  that  nature  has  attached  delight  to  those 
activities  of  animals  which  are  manifestly  ordained  to 
necessary  ends,  as  in  the  use  of  food,  which  is  ordained 
to  the  preservation  of  the  individual,  and  in  the  inter- 
course of  the  sexes,  which  is  ordained  to  the  preserva- 
tion of  the  species  :  for  if  delight  were  not  in  attendance, 
animals  would  abstain  from  the  aforesaid  acts.  It  is 
impossible,  therefore,  for  delight   to  be  the  final  end." 

this  difficulty  in  such  arguments  as  these — that  they  take  it  for  granted 
that  only  our  present  code  is  lofty  and  good,  that  lying  or. fornication 
are  low  and  cannot  be  good,  a  thing  which  the  ethician  really  cannot 
take  for  granted,  but  ought  to  prove  But  the  true  inner  brutality 
of  Hedonism  is  here  brought  out  by  St.  Thomas  without  any  such 
illogical  presuppositions.  The  only  presupposition  in  the  case  (it  can 
scarcely  be  called  a  presupposition)  is  that  nature's  primary  end  can 
neither  consist  in  nor  include  the  destruction  of  the  race.  But  to 
represent  as  justifiable  the  sustaining  of  the  pleasures  of  our  faculties 
apart  from  the  realisation  of  their  ends,  must  inevitably  lead  to  the 
degradation  and  ruin  of  the  race. 

*  "  Happiness  "  here  means  object  of  desire — summum  bonum. 

I  From  Father  Rickaby's  translation  of  "  Summa  Contra  Gentiles." 


288  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Briefly,  if  in  the  natural  physical  order  pleasure  is  but 
a  means,  it  cannot  be  more  than  means  in  the  natural 
moral  order.  But  it  is  plain  that  in  the  order  of  animal 
life  pleasure  is  only  a  means  to  function.  Hence 
pleasure  cannot  be  man's  final  end. 

We  have  said  that  pleasure  is,  in  the  order  of  nature, 
a  means  to  function.  But  it  is  only  in  the  case  of 
sensitive  and  rational  beings  that  function  is  promoted 
by  pleasure,  and  even  in  their  case  the  law  holds  only 
in  regard  to  some  functions.  There  are  organic  func- 
tions, such  as  those  of  plant  life,  the  acts  of  growth  of 
animals  and  men,  and  some  of  the  acts  of  nutrition 
that  are  carried  out  entirely  without  the  use  of  pleasure 
even  as  one  of  nature's  means.  Hence  pleasure  is  not 
even  an  indispensable  means  to  functioning.  Much 
less  could  it  be  our  end.  And  even  when  pleasure 
attaches  as  means  to  a  function  it  does  not  always 
attach  to  what  is  principal,  but  often  only  to  something 
which  is  itself  a  means  to  the  principal  function.  Thus 
the  pleasure  of  food  attaches  as  a  means  not  to  the 
function  of  growth  and  nutrition,  but  to  that  which  is 
only  a  means  to  growth  and  nutrition — namely,  eating. 
It  is,  therefore,  in  the  order  of  nature  merely  a  means 
to  a  means. 

The  animal  does  not  know  that  pleasure  is  but  a 
means.  But  man  knows  that  pleasure  secured  in  this 
world  is,  in  the  order  of  nature,  only  a  means,  and  that 
if  we  take  the  whole  series  of  ends  into  account,  it  is  a 
means  to  the  final  end  ;  and  his  knowledge  of  this  fact 
imposes  on  him  an  obligation  of  using  pleasure  in  sub- 
ordination to  his  final  end  as  a  rational  being. 

By  these  five  arguments  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  estab- 
lishes our  thesis  that  pleasure  cannot  be  man's  sole 
natural  end.  On  the  contrary,  that  an  object  distinct 
from  pleasure  is  also  a  natural  end,  that  this  object 
is  prior  to  pleasure,  and  that  an  object  and  not  a  pleasure 
is  the  natural  final  end  of  man. 


ON  HEDOxNISM  289 

Some  arguments  of  moderns  in  support  of  this  doctrine 
will  be  noticed  later  (page  295). 

(6)  Some  Arguments  in  Favour  of  Hedonism 
Examined 

psychological  hedonism  and  ethical  hedonism 

In  the  preceding  section  we  gave  the  substance  of 
St.  Thomas  Aquinas'  refutation  of  the  general  theory 
that  pleasure  is  man's  final  end.  We  will  now  discuss 
the  case  in  favour  of  the  Hedonistic  theory,  and  we  will 
consider  this  case  chiefly  as  advocated  in  its  two  forms 
of  Psychological  and  Ethical  Hedonism, 

Psychological  Hedonism  is  the  theory  that  pleasure  is 
not  only  the  natural  end  of  man,  but  that  it  is  the  sole 
object  of  desire — the  only  thing  that  we  are  capable  of 
desiring.  It  is.  Mill  tells  us,  because  pleasure  is  the 
sole  object  of  desire  that  we  believe  it  to  be  a  desirable 
end,  and  the  only  desirable  end.  "The  only  proof," 
writes  Mill,*  "  capable  of  being  given  that  an  object  is 
visible  is  that  people  actually  see  it.  .  .  .  In  like 
manner,  I  apprehend,  the  sole  evidence  it  is  possible 
to  produce  that  anything  is  dssirable  is  that  people 
actually  do  desire  it.  .  .  .  No  reason  can  be  given 
why  the  general  happiness  is  desirable  except  that  each 
person,  so  far  as  he  believes  it  to  be  attainable,  desires 
his  own  happiness."  f  Later  in  the  same  chapter  Mill 
emphasises  the  fact  that  pleasure  is  the  sole  object  of 
desire,  and  that  if  we  desire  other  things  it  is  because 
they  are  associated  with  pleasure  or  are  part  of  pleasure. 
"  The  principle  of  Utility,"  he  writes,  "  does  not  mean 
that  any  given  pleasure,  as  music,  for  instance,  or  any 
given  exemption  from  pain,  as,  for  example,  health,  are 
to  be  looked  upon  as  means  to  a  collective  something 
termed  happiness,  and  to  be  desired  on  that  account. 

*  "  Utilitarianism,"  Chapter  IV. 

t  Mill  here  makes  the  transition  from  Psychological  Hedonism  to 
Utilitarianism.  With  this  transition  we  have  here  no  concern,  but 
only  with  the  theory  that  each  man  desires  his  own  happiness. 

Vol.  I — 19 


290  THE  SCIENCE  OF   ETHICS 

They  are  desired  and  desirable  in  and  for  themselves  ; 
besides  being  means  they  are  a  part  of  the  end.  Virtue 
according  to  the  Utilitarian  doctrine,  is  not  naturally 
and  originally  part  of  the  end,  but  it  is  capable  of 
becoming  so."  Professor  Rashdall  also  writes  :  *  "In 
the  writings  of  Bentham  and  his  followers  the  ethical 
doctrine  that  actions  are  right  or  wrong  according  as 
they  do  or  do  not  tend  to  produce  maximum  pleasure  is 
founded  upon  the  psychological  theory  that  as  a  matter 
of  fact  nothing  is  or  can  be  desired  except  pleasure." 

We  now  propose  to  criticise  this  theory  by  establish- 
ing three  propositions  which  treat  the  question  in  its 
widest  comprehension  . — 

(i)  It  is  possible  to  desire  pleasure. 

(2)  Pleasure  is  not  the  only  possible  object  of  desire. 

(3)  Pleasure  is,  however,  a  necessary  condition  of  all 
desire. 

(i)  It  is  possible  to  desire  pleasure. 

We  have  seen  that  by  reflection  upon  our  actions  we 
can  break  up,  in  our  thoughts,  the  order  of  nature  and 
seek  for  the  ends  of  nature  in  any  order  that  we  like. 
Hence,  though  in  the  order  of  nature,  object,  as  distinct 
from  will  and  pleasure,  is  our  primary  end,  and  happi- 
ness only  a  secondary  end,  we  can  by  reflection  and  the 
power  of  analysis  that  belongs  to  intellect  make  happi- 
ness or  pleasure  a  primary,  though  not  the  primary 
natural  end  of  an  act  of  the  will.  This  is  evident  from 
consciousness.  It  is  possible  for  any  man  to  do  a  thing 
merely  for  the  sake  of  the  pleasure  it  affords  him.  A 
man  may,  for  instance,  determine  to  have  a  day's 
pleasure  and  then  consider  what  objects  will  best  pro- 
mote his  pleasure.  Hence  pleasure  is  a  possible  object 
of  desire. 

But  the  general  principle  that  it  is  possible  to  desire 
pleasure,  although  evidently  true,  is  not  accepted  without 

*  "  Theory  of  Good  and  Evil,"  page  7.* 


ON  HEDONISM  291 

reservation  by  some  Ethicians.  Two  exceptions  are 
made  to  it  by  some  writers  who  profess  to  prove  that 
the  desire  for  pleasure  is  absolutely  impossible  in  the 
great  majority  of  our  acts — a  theory  which  is  extremely 
anti-hedonistic,  for  if  pleasure  is  an  impossible  object 
of  desire  in  the  great  majority  of  our  acts,  then  pleasure 
is  not  the  only  possible  nor  the  only  lawful  object  of 
desire.  These  two  exceptions  are  based,  one  {a)  on  the 
nature  of  the  will's  deliberate  choice  between  different 
pleasures,  the  other  0)  on  the  self-defeating  character  of 
the  desire  for  pleasure. 

(a)  The  first  of  these  exceptions  is  the  theory  of  Pro- 
fessor Rashdall  and  others  that  where  desire  results 
from  deliberation  or  choice  (and  most  acts  are  acts  of 
choice)  it  is  impossible  that  pleasure  should  be  the  end 
of  desire.  For  to  choose  amongst  pleasures  is  to  be 
determined  by  something  other  than  pleasure,  just  as 
to  choose  between  two  men  is  to  be  determined  by 
something  other  than  humanity.  (6)  The  second  is  the 
theory  of  Butler,  who  insists  that  pleasure  cannot  be  a 
prominent  end  of  desire,  and  that  in  most  cases  it  can- 
not be  an  end  at  all,  for  to  make  pleasure  the  end  would 
be  to  defeat  the  purpose  of  the  desire.  To  desire 
pleasure  would  be  to  lose  it.  To  attain  pleasure  there 
must  be  some  other  object  of  desire  distinct  from 
pleasure.  This  inner  self-contradiction  of  "  desire  for 
pleasure "  is  known  as  the  Hedonistic  Paradox.  We 
will  examine  these  two  arguments. 

[a)  Professor  Rashdall  contends  that  that  in  which 
pleasures  differ  cannot  be  pleasure.  We  answer  that 
this  proposition  can  only  be  accepted  with  a  distinction. 
That  in  which  pleasures  differ  is  not  pleasure  (in  general), 
for  all  pleasures  are  contained  in  the  genus  pleasure. 
As  pleasure,  pleasures  do  not  differ.  But  pleasures 
differ  as  pleasures  *  as  this  and  that  pleasure,  and  that 

*  When  we  speak  of  pleasures  (in  the  plural)  we  still  refer  to  the 
subjective  state  of  pleasure.  Some  writers  when  they  speak  of 
pleasures  (in  the  plural)  refer  not  to  subjective  states,  but  to  pleasurable 
objects. 


292  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

in  which  they  differ  is  a  pleasure-difference.  Colours 
do  not  differ  as  colour,  since  all  colours  are  contained 
under  the  genus  "  colour,"  but  they  differ  as  this  colour 
and  that  colour,  or  as  colours.  And  the  difference 
between  them  is  a  colour-difference — that  is,  it  is  not 
something  distinct  from  colour.  So  also  pleasures  differ 
by  a  pleasure-element,  by  a  greater  or  less  in  pleasure, 
or  by  some  other  pleasure-element.  Hence,  though  in 
choosing  between  pleasures,  our  wills  do  not  make  the 
preference  on  the  ground  of  pleasure  (in  general),  they 
may  still  be  moved  b}^  pleasures.  And  this  is  all  that 
Mill  as  a  hedonist  contends  for.  The  will  is  not  neces- 
sarily determined  by  a  "  collective  something  called 
pleasure,"  but  it  is  determined  by  this  or  that  pleasure 
or  by  pleasures. 

(b)  Pleasure,  Butler  tells  us,  so  far  from  being  the 
natural  object  of  the  will,  disappears  from  us  the 
moment  we  make  it  an  object.  Let  a  man,  says  Butler, 
in  hunting,  fix  his  mind  on  the  pleasure  which  the  race 
affords  him,  and,  as  if  by  magic,  the  pleasure  vanishes. 
To  feel  pleasure  in  hunting  we  must  pursue  the  quarry 
and  fix  our  mind  upon  it  and  upon  the  scene  around 
us,  the  horses,  the  race,  the  hallooing,  upon  anything 
in  fact  but  that  inner  feeling  of  the  mind  called  pleasure. 
To  seek  for  pleasure  is  to  lose  it.  This  opposition  be- 
tween making  pleasure  our  end  and  success  in  obtaining 
pleasure  is  known  as  the  Hedonistic  Paradox.  The 
obvious  conclusion  from  it  in  reference  to  the  question 
we  are  at  present  treating  is  that  since  it  is  certain  that 
we  do  not  in  most  of  our  acts  defeat  our  own  desire  for 
pleasure,  pleasure  is  not  and  cannot  be  the  object  of 
most  of  our  acts. 

This  is  an  interesting  theory,  and  deserves  examina- 
tion. Our  view  is  that  the  desire  for  pleasure  does  not 
defeat  itself,  that  it  is  quite  possible  for  a  man  to  intend 
pleasure — that  is,  make  pleasure  the  end  of  his  act,  and 
Btill  gain  pleasure.  A  man  may,  to  use  Butler's  own 
example,  successfully  make  the  hunt  a  means  to  pleasure 


ON  HEDONISM  293 

— that  is,  he  may  determine  upon  having  a  day's 
pleasure,  and  select  hunting  as  the  best  and  most 
opportune  way  of  securing  it,  and  still  derive  pleasure 
from  the  hunt.  But  though  we  may  in  any  act  intend 
pleasure  and  attain  it,  still  in  some  acts  to  attend  to  the 
pleasure  we  receive  might  make  pleasure  impossible,  for 
it  might  make  the  act  impossible  which  gives  us  pleasure. 
When  the  act  which  gives  us  pleasure  is  a  complex  one 
and  requires  all  our  attention  for  its  proper  performance, 
it  would  be  impossible  for  us  to  do  the  act  as  it  should 
be  done,  and  attend  to  the  pleasure  it  gives  us.  Simpler 
acts,  like  the  beholding  of  a  beautiful  scene,  the  percep- 
tion of  a  sweet  perfume,  &c.,  do  not  exclude  attention  to 
the  pleasure  they  afford.  Now,  we  believe  that  Butler, 
in  his  example  of  the  hunt,  confounded  these  two  things 
— the  intending  of  pleasure  and  attention  to  it  at  the 
moment  of  receiving  it.  The  hunt  is  a  complex  act,  and 
it  requires  the  fullest  attention  of  the  individual.  To 
attend  to  the  pleasure  of  the  hunt  would  of  necessity 
prevent  our  hunting  properly,  for  to  hunt  properly  we 
must  give  all  our  attention  to  the  objects  around  us. 
But,  as  we  have  said,  a  man  may  gain  great  pleasure 
from  hunting  even  though  he  intended  the  pleasure 
principally  and  used  the  hunt  as  a  means  to  pleasure.* 

*  We  would  direct  the  reader's  attention  to  Spencer's  strange 
criticism  of  the  hedonistic  paradox.  Butler's  contention  is  that 
naturally  we  seek,  not  pleasure  within  us,  but  object  outside  us. 
The  pleasure  within  arises  from  the  pursuit  of  object  without.  Spencer 
maintains  that  the  pleasure  within  arises  not  from  something  without, 
but  from  something  within — i.e.,  our  own  action.  It  is  not  the  fox 
or  the  stag,  he  tells  us,  that  gives  us  pleasure,  but  the  pursuing  of 
them.  He  writes — "  Recognising,  then,  the  truth  that  the  pleasures 
of  pursuit  are  much  more  th  sc  derived  from  the  efficient  use  of  means 
than  those  derived  from  the  end  itself,  we  see  that  the  fundamental 
paradox  of  Hedonism  disappears." 

His  criticism  is,  we  maintain,  irrelevant.  To  Butler  it  makes  no 
difference  whatsoever  whether  the  pleasure  arises  from  the  fox  or 
from  the  huntmg  of  it.  He  merely  contends  that  if  you  fix  your 
mind  upon  the  pleasure  mstead  of  upon  the  quarry  or  the  hunting 
of  it,  the  pleasure  vanishes. 

In  the  text  we  quote  only  one  form  of  the  hedonistic  paradox  ;   but 
there  are  many  other  forms  of  it.     For  instance  (a)  Green  maintains 
that  pleasure  arises  in  us  from  our  attaining  something  that  we  desire 
that,   therefore,  which  is  desired  must  be  attained  before  pleasure 


294  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

It  is  not  true,  therefore,  that  in  most  acts  to  seek  for 
pleasure  would  defeat  its  own  end. 

(2)  Pleasure  is  not  the  sole  possible  object  of  desire. 

In  the  earlier  pages  of  this  chapter  we  gave  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas'  proofs  that  pleasure  is  not  our  sole  natural 
end.  From  this  it  follows  that  the  will  is  capable  of 
desiring  other  ends,  other  objects.  Therefore,  pleasure 
is  not  the  sole  object  of  desire. 

We  have  also  shown  that  pleasure  is  not  the  primary 
natural  object  of  the  will.     The  primary  natural  object 

ensues.  Hence  pleasure  cannot  be  the  object  of  desire.  This  argu- 
ment is  very  much  akin  to  that  of  St.  Thomas,  given  page  269.  It  is 
not  wholly  invalid,  [b)  Muirhead  insists  that  though  pleasure  can 
move,  it  cannot  be  the  object  aimed  at.  "  Let  us  admit,"  he  writes, 
"  for  argument's  sake  that  the  idea  of  the  course  of  action  chosen — 
v.g.,  by  the  martyr — gives  him  greater  pleasure  than  the  idea  of  any 
other  course.  But  to  make  this  admission  is  one  thing,  to  contend 
that  in  choosing  that  course  he  chooses  his  own  pleasure  is  quite 
another.  Indeed,  the  one  contention  is  exclusive  of  the  other.  If 
the  pleasure  that  moves  us  be  excited  by  the  idea  of  an  act,  it  cannot, 
at  one  and  the  same  moment,  be  excited  by  the  idea  of  pleasure.  The 
idea  of  a  pleasure  may  of  course  move  us,  but  then  the  pleasure 
becomes  an  object  of  desire,  and  must  in  turn  excite  a  present  pleasure. 
It  follows  then  that  the  pleasure  which  moves  (if  it  be  pleasure  which 
moves)  cannot  be  the  pleasure  aimed  at."  This  recalls  Leslie  Stephen's 
remark,  that  "  it  is  more  accurate  to  say  that  my  conduct  is  deter- 
mined by  the  picasantest  judgment  than  to  say  it  is  determined  by 
my  judgment  of  what  is  pleasantest.'*' 

To  answer  Professor  Muirhead  we  may,  for  clearness'  sake,  formu- 
late his  argument  :  action  x  would  produce  pleasure  y.  I  form  an 
idea  a  of  action  x,  and  this  idea  produces  in  my  mind  pleasure  b. 
This  pleasure  b  is  quite  distinct  from  pleasure  y.  The  former  attaches 
to  idea  a,  the  latter  to  action  or  end  x.  That  which  determines  my 
will  is  not  y  but  b,  whereas  Hedonism  makes  y  the  determining  factor. 
Answer. — Plainly  Professor  Muirhead  fails  to  see  that  the  plea.sure  t- 
which  attaches  to  the  idea  a  is  only  pleasure  y  anticipated,  and  repre- 
sented in  consciousness.  An  idea  apart  from  the  object  it  represents 
has  no  pleasure  in  it.  The  pleasure  of  an  idea  is  only  the  mental 
representation  of  the  pleasure  which  is  to  flow  later  on  from  the  object 
realised.  The  will,  therefore,  may  be  drawn  by  a  future  pleasure 
now  consciously  represented.  The  fact  that  that  pleasure  has  now  to 
be  represented  in  consciousness  before  it  can  bcxome  an  end  to  the 
will  docs  not  i)rovc  that  the  future  pleasure  is  not  that  which  draws 
the  will.  Every  end  that  draws  us,  tlirough  our  minds,  must  first 
be  represented  in  consciousness  no  matter  iiow  directly  it  draws  us. 
Hence,  though  future  pleasure  must  now  be  represented  in  idea,  it 
is  the  future  pleasure  that  is  our  end  \vlun<:ver  we  are  moved  by 
pleasure,  and  not  the  present  idea  or  any  quality  or  condition  of  it. 


i? 


ON  HEDONISM  295 

of  the  will  is  an  object  outside  the  will.  Pleasure, 
therefore,  cannot  be  the  sole  object  of  desire. 

Besides  these  arguments,  derived  a  priori  from  the 
nature  of  the  will  and  its  object,  an  interesting  a  pos- 
teriori argument  from  experience  has  been  used  by 
Sidgwick,  Rashdall  and  other  moderns  to  prove  the 
proposition  that  pleasure  is  not  the  sole  object  of  desire. 
These  writers  aflfirm  that  it  is  the  clear  teaching  of 
experience  that  there  are  innumerable  other  objects  of 
desire  besides  pleasure. 

According  to  Professor  Rashdall,*  "  no  pleasures  .  .  . 
are  explicable  on  the  hypothesis  of  psychological 
Hedonism  except  those  of  a  purely  sensual  character 
and  .  .  .  aesthetic  pleasures."  As  examples  of  desires 
which  are  not  for  pleasure  he  instances  the  avenging 
of  a  wrong  and  the  relief  of  the  sick.  "  It  is  not  the 
representation  of  my  being  pleased  in  the  future  which 
makes  the  idea  of  the  sick  man  relieved  or  of  the  wrong 
avenged  pleasant  to  me  and  so  moves  my  will ;  my 
desire  is  that  the  actual  objective  result  shall  be 
achieved."  Also  "  hunger  is  neither  a  desire  for  the 
pleasure  of  eating,  nor  (in  its  less  acute  forms)  a  desire 
to  avoid  the  pains  of  inanition  ;  but  it  is  not  quite  the 
same  thing  as  a  disinterested  desire  of  food  for  food's 
sake.  It  is  simply  an  impulse  to  eat."  f  He  also 
claims  that  many  of  the  desires  of  animals  and  of  human 
infants  are  desires  for  objects  other  than  pleasure. 

Sidgwick  also  instances  desires  for  other  objects  than 
pleasure.  Thus,  such  acts  as  have  for  their  end  the 
mere  pursuit,  as  opposed  to  the  attainment,  of  some- 
thing are  not  as  a  rule  directed  to  pleasure.  "  In  such 
cases,"  he  writes,  "  it  is  peculiarly  easy  to  distinguish 
the  desire  of  the  object  pursued  from  the  desire  of  the 
pleasure  of  attaining  it."  J  Again,  whilst  allowing  for 
the  possibility  of  benevolent  actions  being  grounded  in  a 

•  "  Theory  of  Good  and  Evil,"  Vol.  I.,  page  i8. 

t  Ibid.,  page  24. 

t  "  Methods  of  Ethics,"  page  48 


296  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

desire  for  pleasure  or  for  the  averting  of  sympathetic 
pain,  he  yet  insists  that  "  the  impulse  to  beneficent 
action  produced  in  us  by  sympathy  is  often  so  much  out 
of  proportion  to  any  actual  consciousness  of  sympathetic 
pleasure  and  pain  in  ourselves  that  it  would  be  para- 
doxical to  regard  this  latter  as  the  object."  He  also 
quotes  with  approval  Lecky's  statement  that  reflection 
on  our  moral  consciousness  seems  to  show  that  the 
"  pleasure  of  virtue  is  one  which  can  only  be  obtained 
on  the  express  condition  of  its  not  being  the 
object  sought."  The  desire  for  posthumous  fame  he 
also  regards  as  a  desire  for  something  other  than 
pleasure. 

Our  own  view  is  that,  taking  first  the  case  of  adults, 
whilst  it  is  always  possible  that  pleasure  may  play  a 
more  important  part  in  their  desires  than  mere  intro- 
spection is  able  to  reveal,  it  seems,  nevertheless,  un- 
doubtedly true  that  in  some  acts,  like  that  of  the  angry 
man  seeking  to  avenge  himself,  the  dominant,  if  not 
the  only,  desire  present  seems  to  be  a  desire  not  for 
personal  pleasure,  but  for  the  achievement  of  some 
object — in  this  case,  the  infliction  of  pain  on  an  enemy. 
Acts  of  benevolence,  too,  seem  to  involve  a  desire  for 
something  other  than  our  own  pleasure. 

But  whatever  may  be  said  of  adults,  it  is  certain  that 
the  first  desires  of  animals  ani  human  infants  are  always 
for  some  object  other  than  pleasure,  for  it  is  only  after 
repeated  action  that  the  animal  and  the  young  infant 
axe  able  to  associate  pleasure  with  certain  actions,  and 
to  do  these  acts  for  the  sake  of  pleasure.  But  these 
facts  are  not  known  to  us  by  introspection  or  experience, 
but  by  a  priori  reasoning  on  the  impossibility  of  these 
first  desires  being  for  pleasure. 

The  complete  and  satisfactory  proof,  then,  that 
pleasure  is  not  the  sole  object  of  desire  is  a  priori  as 
we  showed  at  the  beginning  of  this  chapter,  but  it  is 
confirmed  by  the  arguments  from  experience  given 
above. 


ON  HEDONISM  297 

(3)  Pleasure  is  a  necessary  condition  of  all  desire. 

Pleasure  is  a  condition  of  desire  because  we  have 
shown  that  pleasure  is  the  rest  or  quiescence  which 
follows  on  the  attainment  of  the  object — that  is,  on  the 
fulfilment  of  the  desire.  Every  object  of  desire  will, 
when  attained,  give  rest  to  the  appetite  which  desires 
it,  and  rest  in  the  possession  of  a  desired  object  is 
pleasure.  Therefore,  pleasure  is  a  necessary  conse- 
quence of  the  fulfilment  of  desire  and  a  necessary  con- 
dition of  desire  itself,  so  that  it  would  be  impossible 
for  a  man  to  desire  a  thing  if  he  knew  that  it  could  not 
give  him  rest  or  pleasure.  But  though  pleasure  is  a 
condition  it  is  not  (as  we  have  shown)  necessarily  the 
object  of  all  desires. 

But  it  is  well  to  remember  that  there  is  no  object 
which  we  are  absolutely  unable  to  desire,  for  there  is 
one  appetite  the  object  of  which  is  any  good  or  good  in 
general — viz.,  the  human  will.  Any  object  can  in  some 
sense  or  under  some  aspect  respond  to  that  appetite. 
And,  therefore,  any  object  may  be  desired,  for  every 
object  can  give  some  rest  at  least  to  this  appetite  of 
will.  In  desire  we  may  not  indeed  think  of  pleasure ; 
yet  the  element  of  pleasure  will  always  remain  an 
attendant  condition  of  the  object,  because  that  object 
responds  to  the  appetite,  and  is,  therefore,  capable  of 
giving  the  appetite  rest  or  quiescence. 

The  hedonistic  hysteron  proteron.  Bearing  in  mind 
what  we  have  just  proved,  that  all  ends  presuppose  the 
capacity  to  please,  we  find  it  hard  to  agree  with  Pro- 
fessor Rashdall's  argument  against  Psychological 
Hedonism,  that  instead  of*  pleasure  being  always  the 
cause  of  desire,  desire  is  often  the  cause  of  pleasure.* 
"  The  Hedonistic  Psychology,"  he  writes,  "  involves 
a  hysteron  proteron ;  it  puts  the  cart  before  the 
horse.  In  reality  the  imagined  pleasantness  is  created 
by  the  desire,  not  the  desire  by  the  imagined  pleasant 

•  "  Theory  of  Gtood  and  Evil,"  page  15. 


298  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

ness."  Professor  Rashdall  instances  cases  of  the 
pleasures  of  knowledge  and  of  benevolence.  It  is,  he 
tells  us,  because  I  desire  knowledge  that  I  find  it 
pleasant,  and  it  is  because  I  desire  to  see  people  happy 
that  the  disbursement  of  money  becomes  pleasant  to 
me.  I  find  knowledge  and  benevolence  pleasant  be- 
cause I  desire  them.  Now,  with  this  statement  we 
cannot  agree.  If  an  object  is  pleasant,  it  is  pleasant 
to  me  not  because  I  desire  it,  but  because  it  either 
answers  to  a  disposition  in  me  or  because  it  is  a  means 
to  something  that  will  answer  to  a  disposition.  We 
have  in  knowledge  an  instance  of  the  first  of  these  two 
kinds  of  objects.  Knowledge  answers  a  disposition  or 
appetite  in  some  men,  and,  therefore,  do  they  desire  it.* 
Benevolence  is  an  example  of  the  second.  Disburse- 
ment of  money  is  not  desirable  of  itself.  It  is  desirable 
only  as  a  means  to  that  which  answers  to  the  inner  dis- 
position of  benevolence — viz.,  the  happiness  of  others. 
But  it  is  not  the  desire  of  disbursement  which  causes 
the  pleasure  of  disbursement.  The  desire  of  disburse- 
ment itself  arises  from  the  fact  that  disbursement  is  a 
means  to  an  end,  which  end  suits  the  disposition  of  the 
benevolent  man.  And  the  pleasure  of  disbursement 
arises  from  the  attainment  of  or  moving  towards  that 
end.  The  desire  to  disburse  money,  therefore,  is  itself 
a  result  and  not  a  cause.  It  is  not  the  cause  of  the 
pleasure  of  benevolence.  And  hence  these  cases  do  not 
disprove  the  theory  of  Psychological  Hedonism  that 
desire  is  caused  by  the  hope  of  pleasure.  That  theory, 
however,  we  claim  to  have  disproved  on  other  grounds. 
In  concluding  our  review^  of  Psychological  Hedonism 
we  repeat  that  it  is  untrue  ;  for  pleasure  is  not  the 
natural  and  original,  much  less  the  sole,  object  of  desire. 
In  the  order  of  nature  pleasure  is  never  the  primary 

•  We  speak  now  of  the  actual  desire  of  knowledge.  When  the 
Hedonist  speaks  of  desire  being  always  for  pleasure  he  means  the 
actual  desire,  and  not  mere  general  liking.  It  is  in  this  sense  Prof. 
Rashdall  must  use  the  word  if  his  argument  is  to  be  pertinent  to  his 
subject. 


I 


ON  HEDONISM  299 

end  of  an  appetite.  And  if  we  consider  the  acts  of  an 
appetitive  faculty  in  the  order  of  time  the  first  act  in 
this  order  can  never  have  pleasure  for  its  direct  object, 
because  the  desire  for  the  pleasure-giving  object  must 
come  before  the  desire  for  pleasure  itself.  But  though 
pleasure  is  not  the  natural  or  first  object  of  desire  it 
may,  to  a  being  capable  of  reflecting  on  his  own  acts 
and  conditions  intellectually,  become  an  object  of  desire, 
and  similarly  to  a  sensible  being  by  associations  of 
feeling.  But  no  object  can  become  an  object  of  desire 
unless  it  be  pleasure-giving  in  the  sense  of  suiting  some 
disposition  or  appetite,  which  convenientia  is  the  ob- 
jective condition  of  desire.  But  it  is  not  that  which 
we  desire.  To  adopt  an  illustration  from  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas — to  be  known,  an  object  must  first  be  know- 
able  ;  but  it  is  not  its  knowability  that  is  known.  So, 
also,  to  be  desired,  an  object  must  answer  to  some  dis- 
position or  appetite  in  a  man,  and  be,  therefore,  pleasant, 
but  the  suitability  and  the  pleasantness  are  not  what  we 
naturally  desire. 

ETHICAL  HEDONISM 

This  theory  is  thus  formulated  by  Professor  James 
Seth  :  *  "  Pleasure  is  the  only  thing  desirable,  though 
it  is  not  the  only  object  of  desire  ;  it  is  the  only  thing 
worth  choosing,  though  it  is  not  the  only  thing  chosen." 
The  theory  of  Ethical  Hedonism,  though  formulated  so 
simply,  we  have  very  great  difficulty  in  understanding. 
For  the  question  suggests  itself — Do  the  "  desirability  " 
and  the  "  worth  "  or  "  value  "  spoken  of  by  Professor 
Seth  really  signify  an  Ethical  desirability — a  moral 
value,  or  is  the  value  spoken  of  a  psychological  value — 
i.e.,  a  value  which  consists  in  the  capability  of  an  object 
to  satisfy  actual  desire,  as  good  foods,  for  instance,  or 
health  are  things  that  are  capable  of  satisfying  appetite  ? 

*  "  Ethical  Principles,"  page  117.  Professor  Seth  does  not  adopt 
the  theory.  On  the  contrary,  he  subjects  it  to  a  most  searching 
criticism. 


300  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Perhaps  the  distinction  might  be  better  brought  out 
thus — Do  "  desirable  "  and  "  worth  choosing  "  signify, 
first,  what  one  ought  to  desire,  or  secondly,  "  what  a 
sensible  or  normal  man,  or  what  in  their  sensible 
moments  all  men,  will  desire  ?  "  If  the  first  (and  the 
name  "  Ethical  Hedonism  "  would  lead  us  to  believe 
the  first  is  the  true  supposition),  then  the  system  is 
disproved  by  all  that  we  have  written  to  show  that 
pleasure  is  not  our  natural  end,  for  surely  if  we  ought 
to  desire  anything  we  ought  to  desire  our  natural  end.  If 
the  second,  then  it  has  been  disproved  by  what  we  have 
said  on  Psychological  Hedonism,  for  we  have  shown 
that  not  only  will  a  sensible  man  desire  other  things 
than  pleasure,  but  that  nature  itself  has  made  us  desire 
something  other  than  pleasure.  We  will  take  this 
second  meaning  and  discuss  it.  It  seems  to  be  the 
meaning  in  which  Sidgwick  understood  the  theory, 
and  he  states  it  for  us  as  follows  :  He  says  that  though 
we  may  desire  other  things  than  pleasure,  still,  when  we 
"  sit  down  in  a  calm  moment,"  the  only  thing  that  seems 
to  have  an  absolute  value  for  a  man  (he  means — the 
only  thing  about  which  we  feel  we  need  not  ask — what 
is  it  for  ?)  is  pleasure.*  Now,  we  believe  that  this 
theory  of  Sidgwick 's  as  thus  formulated  will  not  bear 
examination  any  more  than  the  theory  that  pleasure  is 
the  only  thing  one  can  desire.  It  is  quite  true  that  we 
can  always  ask  :  "  What  is  an  object  f or  ?  "  "  What  is 
food  for  ?  "  "  What  is  eating  for  ?  "  "  Why  I  should 
bother  about  friends  ?  "  and  that  consequently  the  value 
of  these  things  is  relative  to  something  else.  But  we 
contend  that  their  value  is  not  their  conduciveness  to 
pleasure,  and  consequently  that  pleasure  is  not  what 
in  a  calm  moment  we  always  desire.  For  the  very 
same  questions  which  we  ask  concerning  objects  can 
be  asked  also  about  pleasures.     The  man  who  enjoyed 

•  "  Methods,"  Book  III.,  Chapter  XIV. 

Followers  of  Sidgwick  may  object  to  our  calling  his  sense  of  "  value  " 
a  psychological  sense,  but  we  believe  that  this  is  his  meaning.  At  all 
events,  we  explain  what  wc  mean  by  "  psychological. " 


ON  HEDONISM  301 

his  drink  last  night  may  ask  to-day — "  What  good  was 
that  pleasure  ?  "  Pleasures,  then,  have  not  an  absolute 
value  any  more  than  objects.  There  is  just  one  pleasure 
about  which  we  cannot  rationally  ask  the  question — 
"  What  is  it  for  ?  "  or  "  What  good  is  it  ?  " — viz.,  the 
pleasure  of  our  final  happiness.  But  neither  can  we 
rationally  ask  that  question  about  the  final  objective 
good  in  the  attainment  and  possession  of  which  we 
shall  attain  to  perfect  happiness.  These  two  ends, 
then,  have  an  absolute  value,  and  in  a  calm  moment 
we  must  recognise  this.  Hence  St.  Thomas  Aquinas' 
brief  but  weighty  argument  (in  the  article  from  which 
we  have  borrowed  so  much  in  the  present  chapter) — "  It 
is  a  foolish  thing  to  ask  what  pleasure  is  for,  not  because 
pleasure  is  our  end  (it  is  not  our  end),  but  because  it  is 
a  concomitant  of  our  final  end  "  (and,  therefore,  is  not 
to  be  regarded  as  mere  means  to  something  else).  Here 
St.  Thomas  is  speaking  of  the  final  happiness  of  man. 

We  admit,  however,  that  even  when  there  is  no  ques- 
tion of  the  final  end  it  would  often  be  a  meaningless 
thing  to  enquire  what  pleasures  are  for.  Thus,  if  on 
being  asked  why  we  spend  our  time  at  Mathematics  we 
answer — for  our  own  pleasure,  nobody  insists  on  the 
further  enquiry — and  what  is  the  pleasure  of  solving 
mathematical  problems  for  ?  The  pleasure  in  this  case 
is  simply  the  result  of  an  end  attained.  But  from  the 
fact  that  pleasure  in  this  case  is  not  a  means  to  anything 
it  does  not  follow  that  it  has  an  absolute  value  or  that  it 
is  the  end  of  our  action.  The  waste  steam  of  a  loco- 
motive is  not  a  means  to  anything,  yet  it  has  no  value 
and  is  not  the  end  desired.  Pleasure  in  this  case  is  a 
necessary  result  of  an  end  attained,  but  pleasure  is  not 
necessarily  the  end  which  we  desire  to  attain. 

And  even  if  we  grant  that  in  such  cases  pleasure  has 
an  absolute  value,  if  it  is  desirable  on  its  own  account, 
we  contend  that  there  are  other  objects  also  which  are 
desirable  on  their  own  account,  and  are  felt  to  have  an 
absolute  value  even  in  our   calmer  moments.     As  we 


302  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

have  already  seen,  before  pleasure  could  become  an 
object  of  desire,  other  objects  distinct  from  pleasure 
must  have  been  objects  of  our  desires,  and  they  are 
desired  for  their  own  sake  and  not  as  means.* 

To  conclude  our  remarks  on  Ethical  Hedonism — 
Ethical  Hedonism,  if  it  means  the  theory  that  pleasure 
ought  to  be  desired  in  all  our  actions,  has  been  dis- 
proved by  all  those  arguments  which  show  that  pleasure 
is  not  our  natural  end.  If,  however,  it  means  that 
pleasure  is  the  only  thing  that  a  rational  man  does  value, 
the  theory  is  only  another  form  of  Psychological  Hedon- 
ism, and  it  is  disproved  by  all  that  we  have  said  in 
contravention  of  that  theory. 

(c)  The  Hedonistic  Criterion  of  Good  Examined 

PLEASURE   NOT  THE   ULTIMATE   CRITERION   OF  THE  GOOD 

In  the  Hedonistic  system  pleasure  fulfils  two  functions 
in  regard  to  morality.  First,  it  is  represented  as  man's 
final  end,  and,  therefore,  as  that  through  which  acts  are 
made  good.  Secondly,  it  is  made  the  criterion  of  the 
good — that  by  which  we  know  that  an  act  is  good.  Of 
these  functions  the  second  is  dependent  on  the  first  in 
the  hedonistic  system.  It  is  because  pleasure  is  repre- 
sented as  our  end — as  that  which  makes  actions  good — 
that  a  resulting  surplusage  of  pleasure  over  pain  is  made 
the  test  of  goodness. 

We  have  already  criticised  pleasure  as  the  final  end, 
and  have  shown  that  it  is  not  the  final  end,  from  which 
it  follows  that  acts  are  not  good  or  bad  merely  through 
their  pleasurable  or  painful  consequences.  We  now  go 
on  to  show  that  pleasure,  or  a  surplusage  of  pleasure 
over  pain,  is  not  the  criterion  of  the  good.     Our  first 

•  When  a  man  answers  the  question,  "  Why  do  you  do  so-and-so  ?  " 
with  the  reply,  "  I  do  it  for  the  pleasure  of  it,"  he  docs  not  always 
mean  that  pleasure  was  an  object  of  conscious  desire,  but  only  that 
he  socks  the  object  for  its  own  sake  and  not  as  a  means  to  something 
else,  or  that  such  an  object  suits  his  dispositions  and  corresponds  to 
an  appetite  within  him. 


ON  HEDONISM  303 

argument  in  this  connection  should  naturally  be  that 
since  pleasure  is  not  the  sole  natural  object  of  desire  it 
cannot  be  the  primary  criterion  of  the  good.  This 
point,  however,  we  shall  not  develop  further  here  since 
we  have  already  said  so  much  on  pleasure  as  our  end. 
The  point  on  which  we  shall  most  insist  in  favour  of 
our  thesis  now  is  that,  if  pleasure  were  the  ultimate 
criterion  of  the  good,  it  would  be  necessary  to  predict 
pleasure  as  the  consequence  of  an  act  in  order  to  judge 
that  the  act  is  moral.  We  should,  therefore,  be  able 
to  tell,  at  least  in  regard  to  most  acts,  whether  the 
consequences  will  be  pleasurable  or  painful — that  is, 
whether  their  final  resultant  will  be  a  surplusage  of 
pleasure  or  of  pain.  But  this,  we  contend,  cannot  be 
known  except  in  very  few  cases.  We  conclude,  there- 
fore, that  pleasure  or  a  surplusage  of  pleasure  over  pain 
is  not  the  ultimate  criterion  of  the  good. 

This  argument  of  ours  demands  fuller  explanation 
and  proof.  We  have  said  it  would  be  necessary  to 
predict  the  pleasure-result ;  it  would  be  necessary  to 
do  this  with  certainty.  Otherwise  pleasure  could  not 
be  the  ultimate  criterion  ;  for  the  ultimate  criterion  is 
the  ultimate  test,  and  should  be  practicable  and  capable 
of  being  applied  with  certainty.  But  if  the  pleasure 
were  uncertain,  our  test  could  not  be  applied  with 
certainty. 

Moreover,  we  say  that  it  would  be  necessary  not  only 
to  tell  the  surplusage  of  pleasure  or  pain  in  the  case  of 
a  class  of  acts  considered  in  general,  but  also  to  predict 
the  consequences  of  each  individual  act,  in  individuo  et 
in  concreto  considered  in  relation  to  the  individualising 
circumstances.  To  illustrate  this  distinction  we  may 
take  the  example  of  murder  or  lying.  The  problem  of 
telling  the  resultant  pleasure  or  pain  of  murders  or  lies 
in  general  is  quite  a  different  problem  from  that  of  pre- 
dicting the  surplusage  of  pleasure  or  pain  that  will 
ultimately  result  from  a  particular  murder  or  a  par- 
ticular lie. 


304  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Now,  our  statement  that  on  hedonistic  principles  it 
would  be  necessary  to  be  able  to  predict  the  conse- 
quences of  the  individual  act  requires  proof  because 
it  is  in  direct  conflict  with  the  teaching  of  certain 
hedonists  who  say  it  is  enough  if  they  are  able  to  tell 
the  consequences  of  a  line  of  action  in  general,  for 
example,  of  lying  in  general,  or,  which  is  practically 
the  same  thing,  to  tell  what  would  happen  if  lying  were 
generally  allowed  ;  and  that  they  should  not  be  ex- 
pected to  tell  the  consequences  of  the  individual  act, 
for  example,  of  a  particular  individual  lie.  They  hold 
that  the  ordinary  man  wiU  be  quite  safe  in  following 
such  general  moral  axioms  {axiomata  media  they  are 
called)  as  that  lying  and  murder  and  stealing  tend  to 
bring  pain  rather  than  pleasure,  and  leaving  the  effects 
of  the  individual  circumstances  completely  out  of 
account. 

Our  case  against  this  reading  of  Hedonism  is  as 
follows  :  To  the  hedonist  pleasure  is  not  merely  the 
criterion  of  good — it  is  also  the-  cause  of  good — that  is, 
it  is  that  through  which  acts  are  constituted  good.  An 
act  is  good  according  to  the  hedonists  because  of  the 
pleasure  it  yields.  Now,  just  as  no  individual  can  be 
a  man  unless  the  nature  humanity  be  in  him  individu- 
ally (humanity  being  that  which  constitutes  us  men),  and 
just  as  an  individual  object  cannot  be  a  tree  unless 
fibres,  sap,  trunk  be  present  in  the  indiivdual  (these 
being  the  things  that  constitute  anything  a  tree),  so 
if  pleasure  and  pain  be  the  constitutive  element  of 
morality,  if  what  makes  an  act  good  is  the  pleasure 
it  causes,  then  no  individual  act  can  be  regarded  as 
good  unless  individually  it  produces  a  surplusage  of 
pleasure,  and  no  individual  act  as  bad  unless  individu- 
ally it  produces  a  surplusage  of  pain.  Were  pleasure 
and  pain  on  the  hedonistic  theory  mere  criteria  of 
morality  we  would  allow  that,  since  the  tendency  to 
pain  which  is  characteristic  of  stealing  in  general  or  of 
most   acts  of  stealing   is  a   good   general   test   of   the 


ON  HEDONISM  305 

morality  even  of  this  particular  act  of  stealing,  then 
this  act  is  most  probably  bad,  since  it  will  probably 
bring  pain.  But  since  hedonists  regard  pleasure  and 
pain  as  more  than  a  criterion,  since  they  regard  pleasure 
as  the  final  end,  and  pleasure  and  pain  as  the  very 
things  that  make  an  act  good  or  bad,  then  if  we  are  to 
determine  truh'  the  morality  of  a  particular  act  we 
must  determine  the  consequences  of  this  act  in  par- 
ticular, otherwise  we  should  not  succeed  in  determining 
the  morality  of  this  act.  And  if  it  be  found  that  a 
particular  act  of  stealing  or  of  lying  produces  pleasure 
only,  or  a  surplusage  of  pleasure  over  pain,  then  no 
matter  what  may  be  the  general  tendency  of  stealing 
or  lying,  we  do  not  know  how  a  consistent  hedonist 
can  say  that  this  particular  act  of  stealing  is  anything 
but  good.  To  apply,  therefore,  to  this  case  the  principle 
that  steahng  in  general  leads  to  pain,  and  to  neglect 
the  fact  that  this  particular  act  is  certain  (I  suppose  a 
case  in  which  it  is  certain)  to  yield  a  surplusage  of 
pleasure  is  inconsistent  and  illogical.  It  is  illogical 
because  it  is  inconsistent — inconsistent,  that  is,  with 
the  hedonistic  principle  that  pleasures  and  pains  are 
the  things  that  make  an  act  good  or  bad. 

We  repeat,  therefore,  that  if  the  hedonist  is  to 
determine  truly  the  morality  of  acts,  he  is  bound  to 
determine  the  pleasurable  or  painful  consequences  of 
individual  acts. 

Having  established  our  position  that  on  the  hedonist 
theory  it  would  be  necessary  to  predict  with  certainty 
the  pain  or  pleasure  resulting  from  individual  acts,  we 
now  return  to  the  proof  of  the  minor  premiss  of  our 
argument — namely,  that  the  pleasure  results  cannot  be 
known  except  in  a  very  few  cases.  Now,  there  are 
two  methods  of  determining  surplusage  in  order  to 
fit  pleasure  to  be  a  workable  test,  and  it  will  be  neces- 
sary to  show  that  in  both  systems  we  fail  to  determine 
the  resultant  effect  of  action  in  terms  of  pleasure  or  of 
pain.     First,  there  is  the  method  of  simple  experience  ; 

Vol.  I — 20 


3o6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

secondly,  there  is  the  scientific  method  of  discovering 
the  cause  of  pleasure  and  deducing  from  this  cause  the 
pleasurable  and  painful  results  of  action. 

We  shall  first  prove  that  simple  experience  or 
SIMPLE  INTROSPECTION  Cannot  yield  us  certainty  on 
the  pleasurable  and  painful  effects  of  individual  acts. 
Of  this  proposition  the  following  are  the  proofs  :  (i) 
Most  feelings  defy  measurement  altogether.  The 
pleasure  we  get  from  telling  the  truth,  for  instance,  is 
not  a  thing  we  can  pick  out  in  our  consciousness  in 
such  a  way  as  tp  be  able  to  determine  and  measure  it. 
We  can  separate  off  heat  and  electric  currents  from 
the  movements  to  which  they  are  attached,  and  by 
which  they  are  caused  ;  we  can  examine  these  pheno- 
mena separately,  and  devise  means  for  measuring  them, 
but  no  similar  separation  and  comparison  for  purposes 
of  measurement  can  be  made  by  our  consciousness  in 
the  case  of  pleasures  and  pains.  With  most  of  our 
actions,  whether  good  or  bad,  much  of  the  pleasure 
may  never  rise  into  conscious  notice  at  all,  or  at  least 
to  a  degree  which  is  calculable.  On  the  other  hand, 
where  an  action  does  produce  intense  pleasure  or  pain, 
the  effect  is  as  a  rule  so  complicated  and  lawless  that 
to  trace  it  through  all  its  ramifications  and  discover 
the  resultant  pleasure  or  pain  is  a  sheer  impossibility. 
(2)  And  if  after  much  trouble  the  pleasures  of  an  action 
could  be  traced  there  would  still  remain  the  difficulty 
of  balancing  the  pleasures  against  the  pains  and  saying 
on  which  side  the  advantage  lay.  The  pleasures  of 
some  actions  can,  no  doubt,  be  compared  with  the  pains. 
I  might  know,  for  instance,  that  the  pleasure  of  eating 
sweets  would  be  more  than  counterbalanced  by  the 
pains  of  toothache,  but  if  I  tell  a  lie  to  save  expense, 
and  thereby  lose  the  friendship  of  my  neighbour,  how 
am  I  to  compare  the  pain  of  losing  my  friend  with  the 
pleasure  of  saving  money.  (3)  There  is  no  known 
standard  by  which  I  am  to  know  the  quantitatively 
relative  value   of   pleasures  even  amongst   themselves. 


ON  HEDONISM  307 

Thus,  intensity  and  duration  are  often  in  inverse  ratio, 
and  how  shall  we  compare  the  one  element  with  the 
other  in  making  our  calculus  of  pleasures  ?  (4)  Most 
pleasures  resist  examination  except  in  memory,  and  in 
memory  it  is  difficult  to  recall  intensity  or,  indeed, 
anything  else  that  will  afford  much  ground  for  calcula- 
tion or  comparison.  Present  pleasures  are  equally 
elusive.  To  examine  them  may  even  involve  their 
disappearance,  for  enjoyment  and  present  investigation 
of  our  feelings  seem  unable  to  go  well  together.  (5)  It 
is  quite  impossible  to  say  where  the  line  of  pleasures 
connected  with  an  act  has  its  ending.  Who  can  say 
whether  the  pleasures  and  pains  we  experience  as  old  men 
are  or  are  not  connected  with  our  actions  when  young  ? 
The  pleasures,  particularly  that  we  may  have  lost  by 
failing  to  follow  lines  of  action  that  were  open  to  us, 
are  never  even  roughly  determinable.  (6)  Pleasures 
depend  so  much,  not  only  on  the  act  we  do,  and  for 
which  we  can  account,  but  also  on  our  own  humours 
for  which  we  cannot  account  (that  which  pleases  us 
to-day  bringing  us  nothing  but  displeasure  to-morrow), 
that  anything  like  a  fixed  table  of  the  pleasures  of 
action  would  seem  to  be  of  its  very  nature  impossible. 
(7)  And  pleasure  depends  not  on  our  humours  only, 
but  also  on  the  thousand  and  one  accidents  of  life,  a 
single  incident  often  turning  a  pleasure  into  pain,  a 
gain  into  a  loss,  and  vice  versa.  If  a  chance  barrier 
will  turn  aside  the  river  from  its  course,  how  much 
more  will  slight  things  alter  that  which  is  far  more 
sensitive  than  the  river — the  course  of  inner  feelings — 
of  pleasure  and  of  pain.  The  pleasure  and  pain  re- 
sultant, therefore,  of  individual  acts  is  not  determinable 
by  the  method  of  simple  introspection  or  simple  ex- 
perience. 

We    now   go    on   to    show    that    the   more    scientific 
method  *   of  determining  pleasures  by  discovering  the 

*  The  use  of  this  method  has  given  to   the  particular  kind  o£ 
Hedonism  now  under  discussion  the  name  of  Scientific  Hedonism. 


3o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

law  or  cause  of  pleasure  is  not  more  successful  than 
the  method  just  discussed  under  the  name  of  simple 
experience.  But  before  doing  so  it  will  be  necessary 
to  give  a  fuller  description  of  this  scientific  method. 
The  method  is  that  of  first  determining  the  law  or 
cause  (in  this  case,  the  physiological  cause)  of  pleasure, 
and  then  deducing  from  that  cause  or  law  the  pleasur- 
able or  painful  effects  of  an  act.  This  is  the  method 
followed  by  Spencer  *  and  the  Evolutionary  school 
generally.  These  ethicians  differ  amongst  themselves 
on  the  question  of  what  is  the  general  law  or  cause  of 
pleasure,  but  they  agree  that  unless  we  can  discover 
the  cause  of  pleasure  it  is  impossible  to  predict  the 
effects  of  action  with  anything  like  scientific  accuracy. 
Now,  the  law  or  cause  of  pleasure  most  commonly 
assigned  by  these  philosophers  is  the  promotion  of  life. 
Acts  are  pleasurable,  they  say,  in  proportion  as  they 
tend  to  promote  vitality,  painful  in  proportion  as  they 
tend  to  suppress  vitality,  and  they  add,  in  consequence, 
that  we  have  but  to  determine  whether  an  act  increases 
or  impairs  our  vitality  in  order  to  know  whether  it  will 
produce  a  surplusage  of  pleasure  over  pain.  It  is  to 
this  form  of  the  scientific  method  that  we  shall  here 
direct  our  criticisms. 

In  criticism  we  say — 

(i)  The  general  "  law  "  or  cause  of  pleasure  does  not 
seem  to  promise  very  practical  results  in  the  determin- 
ing of  the  pleasure  effects — a  point  which  will  probably 
have  suggested  itself  already  to  the  reader.  It  seems 
to  promise  even  less  than  the  simple  method  of  Hedon- 
ism explained  above — the  system,  namely,  of  those 
hedonists  who  rely  on  experience  and  common  sense 

•"I  conceive  it  to  be  the  business  of  Moral  Science,"  he  writes, 
"  to  deduce  from  the  laws  of  life  and  the  conditions  of  existence  what 
kinds  of  action  necessarily  tend  to  produce  happiness  and  what  kinds 
to  produce  unhappiness.  Having  done  this  its  deductions  are  to  be 
recognJHcd  as  laws  of  conduct,  and  are  to  Ix;  conformrd  to,  irrespective 
of  a  direct  estimation  of  happiness  or  misery  "  {"  Principles  of  Ethics," 
Vol,  I.,  page  57). 


ON  HEDONISM  309 

for  guidance  in  the  question  of  the  calculus  of  pleasures. 
For  it  seems  quite  as  difficult  to  say  whether  such  an 
act  as  lying  or  stealing  affects  vitality  well  or  ill,  as  to 
say  whether  it  will  produce  pleasure  or  pain.  Indeed, 
it  seems  to  us  that  when  Scientific  hedonists  proceed  to 
show  that  certain  acts  like  lying  and  stealing  suppress 
vitality,  they  make  no  small  use,  in  coming  to  their 
conclusion,  of  the  pleasurable  or  painful  effects  of  these 
actions — that  act  will  suppress  vitality,  they  argue, 
which  brings  pain — so  that  it  would  seem  that  to 
determine  the  pleasurable  and  painful  effects  im- 
mediately from  experience  is  even  an  easier  thing 
than  to  determine  whether  an  act  promotes  or  sup- 
presses vitality,  and  that  the  pleasurable  effects  are 
better  known  than  the  vital  effects. 

Of  course  there  are  some  acts,  like  suicide,  starva- 
tion, murder,  neglect  of  one's  children,  which  so 
evidently  concern  life  and  health  that  no  rational 
man  could  have  any  doubt  about  their  effect  on  vitality. 
But  these  cases  are  very  few — they  form  a  very  small 
portion  of  the  whole  range  of  moral  acts.  Moreover, 
such  examples  as  murder  or  the  neglect  of  one's  children 
cannot  apply  in  the  present  instance,  for  the  obvious 
decrease  of  vitality  in  these  instances  occurs  in  the 
persons  acted  on — the  person  murdered  or  the  child 
neglected — rather  than  in  the  murderer  or  the  negligent 
parent,  whereas  Hedonism  judges  of  the  morality  of 
action  not  by  its  effect  on  others,  but  by  the  painful 
and  pleasurable  effects  of  an  action  on  the  person  who 
performs  the  act. 

(2)  It  is  not  easy  to  say  how  far,  in  the  use  of  this 
scientific  method,  hedonists  pretend  to  be  able  to  pre- 
dict by  means  of  their  peculiar  "  law "  or  cause  the 
pleasurable  effects  of  individual  acts.  Leslie  Stephen 
certainly  confesses  that  a  moralist  is  bound  to  take 
account  of  individual  circumstances  in  determining 
morality,  and  to  neglect  to  do  so  he  calls  "  moral 
pedantry."     Still  we  think  that  no  Scientific  hedonist 


310  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

could  ever  hope  to  be  able  to  tell  the  effect  of  an 
individual  lie  on  the  vitahty  of  the  liar,  or  of  an  act 
of  stealing  on  the  vitality  of  the  robber.  His  bodily 
vitality  is  certainly  not  in  the  least  affected  by  it,  and 
his  acuteness  and  strength  of  mind — that  is,  his  mental 
vitality — are  not  impaired  by  the  act  in  any  way,  and 
consequently  it  would  seem  that  even  the  Scientific 
hedonists  are  open  to  the  same  criticism  that  we  have 
already  applied  to  the  direct  method  of  simple  Hedon- 
ism— namely,  that  it  can  only  predict  the  general 
tendency  of  a  line  of  action  to  produce  certain  effects, 
whereas  a  consistent  Hedonist  should,  if  his  theory  is 
to  have  any  value,  be  able  to  predict  the  effect  of  the 
individual  act,  the  morality  of  which  he  intends  to 
explain  and  determine.  But  even  when  the  Scientific 
hedonist  succeeds  in  predicting  the  general  tendencies 
of  a  particular  class  of  acts  he  does  so,  as  we  have 
already  said,  largely  by  the  light  of  ordinary  experience, 
and  not  by  his  a  priori  "  cause  "  or  "  law." 

(3)  Even  if  we  could  determine  what  acts  promote 
and  what  impair  vitality,  the  question  still  remains — 
how  far  increase  of  vitality  brings  pleasure  ?  A  low 
bodily  vitality  certainly  brings  with  it  liability  to  pain, 
but  intense  bodily  vitality — the  vitality  of  a  high 
nervous  sensibility — renders  one  also  liable  to  pain. 
A  low  mental  vitality  precludes  the  possibility  of  the 
higher  interests  and  their  pleasures.  But  very  great 
mental  vitality,  in  the  sense  of  great  mental  acuteness 
and  alertness  is  often  a  source  of  pain  more  than  of 
pleasure. 

In  one  sense  only  can  we  admit  the  general  statement 
that  increase  of  vitality  brings  pleasure — the  sense,  viz. 
that  the  natural  development  of  the  faculties  according 
to  the  laws  and  requirements  of  organism  must  on  the 
whole  bring  pleasure.  But  in  this  sense  we  make  the 
"  good  "  (the  "  good  "  being  the  development  of  our 
faculties  towards  the  natural  ends)  the  criterion  of 
pleasure,  not  vice  versa,  whereas  the  aim  of  Hedonism, 


ON  HEDONISM  311 

whether  Empirical  or  Scientific,  is  to  make  pleasure  the 
criterion  of  the  good.* 

We  think,  therefore,  that  "  Scientific  Hedonism  "  is 
not  more  promising  either  in  its  principles  or  its  results 
than  the  theory  of  Empirical  Hedonism  which  we  have 
already  rejected. 


MILL  S   DEFENCE   OF   HEDONISM.      HIS   THEORY   OF   QUALI- 
TATIVE  DISTINCTIONS   BETWEEN    PLEASURES 

One  of  the  principal  charges  usually  directed  against 
the  hedonistic  criterion  is  that,  carried  to  its  logical 
conclusions,  it  sanctions  a  low  and  brutal  code  of 
morality.  To  save  it  from  this  charge  Mill  introduced 
into  his  hedonistic  system  the  theory  of  a  qualitative 
distinction  between  pleasures. 

Pleasures,  he  contends,  do  not  differ  merely  quanti- 
tatively— they  differ  also  qualitatively.  We  may  get 
as  much  pleasure  (quantitatively  regarded)  from  murder 
as  from  philanthropy,  but  the  pleasures  of  philanthropy 
are  of  a  far  higher  order  than  those  of  murder,  and, 
therefore,  they  should  be  rated  much  higher  in  the 
calculus.  A  man  pays  more  for  one  suit  of  clothes 
than  for  another,!  though  the  two  have  the  same 
weight  ;  for  one  painting  than  another,  though  they 
represent  the  same  labour  ;  to  hear  one  song  rather 
than  another,  though  the  better  singer  may  not  have 
so  loud  a  voice.  So  with  pleasures — one  may  be 
quantitatively  greater  than  another,  and  yet  that  other 
may  be  of  a  higher  quality,  so  much  higher  as  even  to 
outbalance  the  quantitative  difference.  Hedonism, 
therefore,  does  not  mean  a  "  low  "  or  a  savage  morality, 
since  when  quahtative  differences  are  allowed  for,  the 
balance  of  pleasure  will  always  be  on  the  side  of  the 
higher  act. 

*    A  fuller  account  of  Scientific  Hedonism  and  its  defects  can  be 
found  in  Sidgwick's  "  Methods,"  page  177. 
t  The  illustrations  are  our  own. 


312  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

We  must  carefully  examine  Mill's  contention,  and  for 
that  purpose  we  shall  ask  two  questions  : — 

{a)  Are  there  such  things  in  pleasures  as  distinctions 
of  quality  ? 

(6)  If  there  are  such  distinctions  can  they  be  made 
the  basis  of  a  distinction  of  acts  into  Ethically  higher 
and  lower  ? 

(a)  Are  there  distinctions  of  quality  between  pleasures  ? 

Opponents  of  Hedonism,  and  of  Mill  in  particular, 
have  denied  the  existence  of  any  such  distinctions. 
But  we  must,  in  fairness  to  Mill,  admit  that  such  dis- 
tionctions  exist.  It  should  be  perfectly  plain  to  any 
man  who  gives  this  subject  his  honest  attention  that 
our  pleasures  differ  very  widely  in  quality.  The 
pleasures  of  hearing,  e.g.,  are  not  the  same  as  those 
of  taste.  The  pleasures  of  smell  are  of  various  qualities, 
as  various,  indeed,  as  the  odours  themselves.  In  fact, 
the  pleasure  got  from  the  scent  of  the  rose  need  differ 
from  that  given  by  the  scent  of  roast  meat  in  one  way 
only — that  is,  qualitatively  ;  in  intensity  they  may  be 
both  the  same.  Again,  we  often  compare  pleasures 
in  respect  of  quality,  and  call  one  finer  or  more  delicate 
than  another,  and,  therefore,  we  have  the  clear  testi- 
mony of  our  consciousness  that  pleasures  differ  in 
quality. 

Some  maintain  that  differences  which  are  spoken  of 
as  qualitative  differences  in  pleasure  are  differences  not 
in  the  pleasures  themselves,  properly  speaking,  but  in 
the  objects  which  give  the  pleasure — that  it  is  im- 
possible pleasures  could  differ  as  pleasure,  since  pleasure 
is  the  common  element  in  all.  Now,  this  theory  seems 
to  us  to  be  founded  on  an  ambiguity.  There  can  be 
no  doubt  that  pleasures  differ  not  only  as  regards  their 
objects  but  also  as  subjective  states.  But  these  sub- 
jective states  differ  not  as  pleasure,  since  pleasure  is 
the  common  element  in  them,  but  as  pleasures,  just  as 


ON  HEDONISM  313 

colours  differ  not  as  colour  (since  "  colour  "  is  the 
common  underlying  conception  in  all  of  them),  but  as 
colours.  But  the  difference  between  pleasures  is  a 
"  pleasure  difference,"  not  a  difference  of  something 
other  than  pleasure. 

Hence,  besides  differences  in  objects  of  pleasure, 
there  are  also  qualitative  (pleasure)  differences  between 
pleasures  themselves.* 

(6)  Our  second  question  is — Are  qualitatively  distinct 
pleasures  to  he  divided  off  into  higher  and  lower  ?  By 
higher  and  lower  we  mean  ethically,  not  aesthetically, 
higher  and  lower.  There  is  no  difficulty  in  thinking 
of  one  pleasure  as  aesthetically  more  delicate  and 
beautiful  than  another.  But  are  pleasures  capable  of 
being  formed  into  a  regular  ethical  series,  beginning  at 
the  lowest  level  of  moral  evil  and  rising  up  to  the 
highest  line  of  moral  excellence  ?  We  will  give  an 
example  of  this  Ethical  gradation  of  pleasures.  If 
murder  is  bad,  and  if  the  pleasure  I  get  from  it  be 
intense,  then  it  is  plain  that,  on  hedonistic  lines,  in 
order  to  make  up  for  this  excess  in  quantity,  the 
pleasure  of  murder  must  be  low  down  qualitatively  in 
the  scale  of  pleasures,  else  murder  would  be,  not  bad, 
but  good.  If  there  be  no  such  series  it  will  be  useless 
to  speak  of  qualitative  distinctions  in  pleasures  as  a 
means  to  distinguishing  the  moral  qualities  of  actions. 

The  first  difficulty  that  we  meet  if  we  try  to  con- 
struct an  Ethical  series  of  pleasures  is  that  pleasures 
as  pleasures  cannot  be  divided  off  into  good  and  bad. 
Pleasures  as  pleasures  considered  out  of  relation  to 
anything  else  have  no  Ethical  or  moral  character.  No 
pleasure  is  bad  in  itself — i.e.,  no  pleasure  is  bad  as 
pleasure.  Some  pleasures  are  bad  because  the  acts  of 
the  will  to  which  they  are  attached  are  bad,  and  the 

•  Prof.  Seth  maintains  that  qualitative  differences  can  be  resolved 
into  quantitative  if  we  take  into  account  the  nature  of  the  person  who 
experiences  the  pleasure.  "For  the  higher  nature,"  he  says,  "the 
higher  pleasure  is  also  the  more  intense  pleasure  "  ("  Ethical  Principles," 
page  125). 


314  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

reason  why  it  is  wrong  to  seek  certain  pleasures  is  not 
because,  the  pleasurable  feeling  is  bad  in  itself,  but 
because  the  pleasurable  feeling  is  attendant  on  an  act 
which  is  bad.*  There  would,  therefore,  be  no  difficulty 
whatsoever  in  constructing  a  scale  of  pleasures  arranged 
in  order  of  Ethically  higher  and  lower,  in  a  system  of 
Ethics  which  is  not  hedonistic,  for,  having  in  such  a 
system  arranged  the  actions  in  an  Ethical  series,  we 
might  then  arrange  the  pleasures  of  these  acts  in  a 
corresponding  series.  But  how  is  the  hedonist  to 
arrange  his  scale  of  pleasures  ?  It  is  by  the  scale  of 
pleasures  that  he  must  determine  the  morality  of  acts, 
and,  therefore,  it  is  not  open  to  him  to  arrange  his 
pleasures  in  a  scale  which  itself  depends  upon  the 
morality  of  acts.  There  is,  therefore,  nothing  left  for 
him  but  to  arrange  the  scale  of  pleasures  by  something 
in  the  pleasures  themselves.  But  since  pleasures  as 
pleasures  are  morally  neutral  this  is  impossible. 

Now,  this  proposition  that  pleasures  as  such,  and 
without  reference  to  anything  else,  are  morally  in- 
different will  not  be  accepted  by  hedonists  who  hold 
that  all  pleasure  is  morally  good,  and,  therefore,  we 
proceed  to  a  second  difficulty  which  we  think  the 
hedonists  must  recognise — namely,  that  even  if  all 
pleasures  are  morally  good,  hedonists  cannot  point  to 
anything  which  those  pleasures  contain  in  themselves — 
that  is,  apart  from  the  acts  to  which  they  are  attached 
— sufficient  to  grade  the  pleasures  in  an  Ethical  series 
of  high  and  low. 

Two  kinds  of  tests  seem  possible.  One  is  to  regard 
those  pleasures  as  higher  that  belong  to  the  higher 
faculty,  intellectual  pleasures  being  higher  than  those 
of  sense,  the  pleasures  of  the  so-called  iesthctic  senses, 
like  those  of  sight  and  hearing,  being  higher  than  those 
of  touch,  &c.  The  other  is  the  criterion  of  human 
testimony. 

The  first  is  suggested  to  us  by  Mill's  contention  that 

•  Aristotle,  "  Nich.  Eth.,"  X.,  5,  6. 


ON  HEDONISM  315 

one  had  rather  be  a  man  dissatisfied  than  a  pig  satisfied, 
the  reason  being  that  a  small  intellectual  satisfaction  is 
much  greater  than  a  great  sense  satisfaction.  But  this 
method  of  gradation  we  cannot  accept,  because  pleasures 
of  intellect  are  often  much  worse  morally  than  those  of 
sense,  and  those  of  sense  worse  than  those  of  the  vegeta- 
tive faculties,*  as  the  following  examples  will  make 
clear.  To  rejoice  at  the  downfall  of  one's  neighbour 
is  a  purely  intellectual  pleasure,  whilst  to  feel  the 
warmth  of  a  summer  breeze  is  sensuous.  But  surely 
this  latter  pleasure  is  better  than  the  pleasure  of  hatred. 
On  the  other  hand,  to  look  upon  obscenity  is  an  act  of 
the  senses,  whilst  to  eat  is  an  act  of  the  vegetative 
faculty,  and  surely  the  latter  is  the  better  of  the  two. 
An  act,  therefore,  is  not  better  because  it  proceeds 
from  the  higher  faculty,  and  consequently  the  pleasures 
of  the  higher  faculty  are  not  necessarily  better  than 
those  of  the  lower. 

The  second  test  is  explicitly  proposed  by  Mill  himself. 
When  men,  he  says,  prefer  certain  pleasures  to  certain 
others  as  a  rule,  that  is  a  sign  that  these  latter  pleasures 
are  ethically  lower.  This  seems  to  be  the  ultimate  test 
according  to  Mill — the  testimony  of  "  those  that  know." 
On  this  test  of  gradation  in  pleasure  we  would  make 
three  remarks.  First,  Mill  maintains  that  it  is  only 
those  that  have  experience  of  differences  in  quantity 
and  quality  of  pleasure  that  are  capable  of  judging  in 
this  matter.  But,  granting  for  the  moment  that  ex- 
perience can  tell  a  man  which  of  two  acts  will  bring 
him  the  greater  pleasure,  still  we  maintain  that  ex- 
perience cannot  tell  him  which  of  these  two  pleasures, 
the  greater  or  the  lesser,  is  the  higher.  There  is  only 
one  way  by  which  even  the  initiated  and  experienced 
can  tell  what  pleasures  are  higher,  and  that  way  is  by 

*  We  might  for  Ethical  purposes,  as  we  have  already  shown,  regard 
intellect  as  of  more  importance  in  the  organism  than  sense,  and  sense 
than  the  vegetative  faculty,  and  we  might  make  use  of  this  com- 
parison in  determining  morality  ;  but  they  are  not  in  themselves 
morally  better  or  worse  the  one  than  the  other. 


3i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

having  a  fixed  standard  of  higher  and  lower  with  which 
to  compare  the  pleasures  as  they  come.  But  that  is 
the  very  standard  for  which  we  are  looking,  and  until 
it  can  be  provided  Hedonism  must  fail  as  an  ethical 
criterion.  Secondly,  if  those  who  are  capable  of  judging 
do  actually  distinguish  between  the  higher  and  the 
lower,  it  is  not  directly  in  reference  to  pleasures  that 
such  distinctions  are  made,  but  rather  in  reference  to 
the  acts  to  which  those  pleasures  are  attached.  Men 
know  that  pleasures  of  benevolence  are  higher  than 
those  of  drinking  beer,  because  they  know  that  acts 
of  benevolence  are  higher  than  the  act  of  drinking  beer. 
If,  then,  men  do  prefer  some  courses  to  others  it  is 
because  they  are  persuaded  that  certain  acts  are  bad 
and  others  good,  and  the  pleasures  of  the  first  class  of 
acts  they  regard  as  bad  and  the  pleasures  of  the  other 
as  good,  and  in  the  same  degree  as  the  acts  to  which 
the  pleasures  are  attached  are  bad  and  good.  Thirdly, 
who,  on  Mill's  theory,  are  the  experienced  and  they  that 
know  ?  for  it  is  important  that  we  should  be  informed 
who  are  the  appointed  judges  of  what  is  good  or  bad 
for  us.  Mill  himself  tells  us  that  as  men  grow  older 
they  become  more  selfish,  and  that  consequently  it  is 
to  youth  we  must  look  for  these  moral  preferences  on 
which  to  frame  the  moral  law.  But  why  should  the 
practice  of  the  old  and  selfish  be  put  aside,  and  that  of 
the  young  and  spirited  be  made  the  moral  standard 
except  that  already  the  selfish  has  been  made  the  lower 
pleasure  and  the  spirited  and  generous  the  higher  ? 
But  spirited  generosity  is  not  the  hedonistic  basis  of 
morals.  On  the  other  hand,  if  the  old  are  included 
amongst  the  judges,  their  principal  quaHfication  as 
judges  will  be  their  experience,  and  if  experience  is  a 
qualification  in  the  construction  of  the  pleasure  scale, 
the  best  judges  must  be  the  gourmands  and  the  gouty 
who  have  tried  and  compared  all  pleasures  in  quantity 
and  in  quality  and  found  some  wanting  and  others  com- 
mendable.    The  best  judge  of  a  road  is,  ceteris  paribus, 


ON  HEDONISM  317 

the  man  who  has  walked  over  it ;  and  in  the  same 
way  the  best  judge  of  what  is  pleasant  should  be  the 
man  who,  in  the  matter  of  pleasure,  has  taken  nothing 
on  faith,  but  conscientiously  tried  all  pleasures  in  turn. 
This  means  making  the  opinion  of  bad  men  the  proper 
standard  of  "  good  "  and  "  evil,"  which  would  be  most 
objectionable  in  practice.  Again,  in  this  matter  we 
must,  as  ethicians,  be  prepared  to  reckon  with  those 
who  like  to  judge  for  themselves  about  right  and  wrong  ; 
and  it  would  be  a  hard  thing  if  we  should  say  to  them — 
"  Thus  have  your  fathers  judged.  It  was  for  them  to 
taste  pleasures  and  examine  them.  It  is  for  you  to 
submit  to  their  decision."  Indeed,  if  pleasure  be  the 
moral  criterion,  then  it  is  certain  that  most  people  will 
like  to  taste  and  judge  for  themselves  ;  and  we  do  not 
know  on  what  principle  of  Hedonism  one  could  rationally 
prevent  them.  But  if  we  do  allow  them  to  taste  and 
judge  for  themselves  we  are  certainly  making  crime  a 
necessary  condition  of  virtue. 

In  conclusion,  therefore,  we  summarise  our  position 
by  saying  that  pleasures  may  differ  qualitatively,  but 
that  to  divide  them  into  ethically  higher  and  lower  we 
need  a  theory  of  Ethics  other  than  the  hedonistic* 


•  To  the  arguments  stated  above  we  may  add  a  consideration  of 
some  importance,  that  the  law  that  would  bind  us  always  to  follow 
the  higher  pleasure  in  preference  to  the  lower  is  an  extravagant  law. 
Most  men  are  bound  to  no  more  than  the  good  ethically  ;  that  is, 
no  man  is  bound  to  the  highest  or  the  best.  On  Mill's  theory  every 
man  would  be  bound  to  follow  the  higher  pleasure  in  the  presence  of 
a  lower.     He  would,  consequently,  be  always  bound  to  the  best. 


CHAPTER  XI 
ON  UTILITARIANISM 

"  We  live  in  the  midst  of  a  multitude  of  beings  like  ourselves  iipon 
whose  happiness  most  of  our  actions  exert  some  obvious  and  decisive 
influence.  The  regulation  of  this  influence  is  the  object  of  moral 
science." — Shelley.  _^.. 

""aKbEFINITION 

Utilitarianism  or  Universalistic  Hedonism  may  be 
defined  as  the  theory  that  the  happiness  *  of  mankind 
at  large  constitutes  the  ultimate  end  of  the  individual 
man,  and  that  consequently  those  actions  are  to  be 
regarded  as  right  and  good  which  promote  that  happi- 
ness, and  those  actions  as  wrong  and  bad  which  tend 
to  produce  the  opposite  effect.  We  adopt  this  definition 
because  it  represents  the  commonest  form  of  the  theory 
of  Utilitarianism. 

We  are  not  unaware  that  some  modern  utilitarians 
make  the  well-being  of  society,  not  its  happiness,  the 
end  of  the  individual.  In  other  words,  there  are  utili- 
tarians who  are  not  hedonists.  Although  these  arc 
technically  outside  our  definition  we  draw  the  reader's 
attention  to  them  here,t  first,  for  completeness ; 
secondly,  because  their  system  is  confuted  by  the  argu- 
ment which  we  draw  in  the  present  chapter  from  the 
fact  that  the  individual  is  not  wholly  subordinate  to 
society,   which  is  one  of  our   two  main  objections   to 

•  The  present  chapter  goes  to  show  that  the  good  of  society  is  not 
the  end  of  the  individual,  whether  that  good  Ix;  in  the  nature  of 
pleasure  or  happiness  or  general  well-being.  We  may  therefore  be 
allowed  to  dispense  for  the  present  with  tlic  technical  distinction 
between  pleasure  and  happiness  already  explained  and  to  use  these 
words  as  roughly  equivalents  of  each  other. 

t  Many  of  these  non-hedonistic  utilitarians  belong  to  the  evolu- 
tionist school  of  cthicians,  and  their  theories  arc  criticised  in  our 
chapter  on  Evolutionist  Ethics.  Green's  is,  perhaps,  tlie  most  pro- 
minent example  in  recent  times  of  non-hedonistic  utilitarian  systems. 


(on  utilitarianism  319 

Utilitarianism  in  general,  whether  hedonistic  or  other- 
wise. Our  other  chief  objection  to  Utilitarianism — that 
it  makes  pleasure  our  sole  natural  end — can,  of  course, 
refer  to  hedonistic  Utilitarianism  alone. 

Moreover,  we  have  grouped  together  in  the  present 
chapter  all  theories  of  hedonistic  Utilitarianism,  although 
they  are  many  and  of  great  diversity — for  instance, 
Bentham's  and  Mill's  theory  that  that  act  is  good  which 
gives  the  greatest_pleasiii(-  to  tlic  ^re;itest  number  of 
sentient  beings  ;  Cumberland's  theory  that  the  pleasure 
of  human  Society  is  the  only  end  ;  Comte's  and  Fichte's 
theory  of  pure  altruism  that  the_end  of  the  individual 
is  the  happiness  of  all  other  men  exclusive  of  his  ovvn» 
regard  to  one's  self  being  considered  in  this  system,  ^f 
not  bad,  at  least  un-moral.  We  even  include  in  our 
account  thaF  very  modified  form  of  altruism  advocated 
by  SJiaftesbury  that  "  the  natural  predominance  of 
benevolence  is  good  and  the  subjection  of  selfishness  is 
virtue7'  Of  these  different  forms  of  Utilitarianism  it 
would  be  impossible  for  us  to  take  separate  account. 
Nor  is  it  necessary  that  we  should  do  so  ;  for,  if  we 
shall  succeed  in  showing  that  the  end  of  man  is  not 
the  happiness  or  well-being  of  society,  we  shall  have 
removed  what  is  fundamental  in  every  form  of  Utili- 
tarianism, and  then  these  separate  systems  fall  of 
themselves. 


X) 


p)  Utilitarianism — How  far  True 

Like  most  false  ethical  theories.  Utilitarianism  is  not 
all  wrong.  It  is  wrong  in  so  far  as  it  makes  the  general 
happiness  the  sole  end  of  man,  thereby  completely  sub- 
ordinating the  individual  to  society.  Now,  that  the 
sole  end  of  man  is  not  his  own  happiness  we  have  shown 
in  the  preceding  chapter  ;  and  almost  all  the  arguments 
there  used  might  be  applied  equally  well  here  to  prove 
that  our  end  as  individuals  cannot  be  the  happiness  of 
the  race.  But,  in  the  present  chapter,  we  must  supple- 
ment those  arguments  by  others  that  are  proper  to  the 


; 


320  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

theory  of  Utilitarianism.  That  man  is  not  wholly  sub- 
ordinated to  society  it  will  be  our  business  also  to 
establish. 

But  Utilitarianism  asserts  many  things  that  are  true, 
and  amongst  these  are  two  salient  doctrines  that  are  of 
paramount  importance  in  Ethics.  One  is  that  man  has 
a  very  special  duty  of  beneiLClence  towards  his  fellow- 
men,  a  duty  which  is  certainly  as  important  as  many  of 
his  special  duties  towards  himself.  Another  is  that  the 
general  welfare  is  in  some  sense  a  genuine  criterion  of 
moral  good.     A  word  on  each  of  these. 

"  Man,"  says  St.  Thomas  Aquinas,  "  is  not  wholly 
political  "  or  social.  But  neither  is  man  wholly  indi- 
vidual. We  are  by  nature  a  part  of  society.  Without 
society  we  could  not  develop,  and  development  is  a 
natural  need  of  man.  Hence,  society  is  a  natural 
necessity,  and  we  have  a  natural  duty  to  promote  its 
welfare.  What  that  duty  is,  and  how  far  it  extends, 
we  shall  see  in  the  second  portion  of  this  work.  At 
.  ji  present  we  may  say  that  our  duty  to  our  fellow-man 
occupies  a  very  large  portion  of  our  moral  life,  but  it 
is  not  the  whole  of  that  life. 
\/  The  second  truth  of  Utilitarianism  is  also  of  im- 
portance in  a  Science  of  Ethics — namely,  that  the 
general  good  is  a  genuine  criterion  of  the  morality  of 
human  acts.  It  will  be  remembered  that  amongst  our 
secondary  criteria  of  morality,  that  on  which  we  laid 
the  greatest  stress,  had  reference,  4ik^  the  utilitarian 
theory,  to  the  happiness  or  misery  of  society.  We 
showed  that  an  act  is  good  if,  on  being  raised  to  a 
general  rule  of  conduct,  it  benefits — bad,  if  it  injures — 
the  human  race  ;  and  though  these  racial  effects  are 
not  the  primary  criterion  of  morals,  they  afford  us  a 
genuine  secondary  criterion,  and  one  much  used  in 
^acticaljife. 

These  are  the  principal  elements  of  truth  in  Utili- 
tarianism. But  Utilitarianism  does  not  stop  at  these. 
It  represents  the  common  good  not  merely  as  one  end 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  321 

for  the  individual,  but  as  the  sole  and  all-embracing 
end.  It  makes  man  wholly  subject  to  society.  Also, 
it  represents  the  general  happiness,  not  as  a  secondary 
criterion  of  morality,  but  as  the  only  or  the  funda- 
mental criterion. 

In  the  two  following  sections  we  hope  to  disprove 
these  two  assumptions  by  showing,  first,  that  the 
general  happiness  of  society  is  not  the  final  end  of  the 
individual ;  secondly,  that  the  general  happiness  cannot 
be  the  sole  or  even  the  primary  criterion  of  good  action. 

/(cy  Disproof  of  the  Theory  of  Utilitarianism  that 
^""^   THE  General  Happiness  is  Man's  Final  End 

(i)  Our  first  argument  is  that  happiness  is  not  "^ur 
final  end — neither  the  happiness  of  the  individual  nor 
the  happiness  of  the  race.  This  has  been  abundantly 
proved  already  in  our  chapter  on  Hedonism  ;  for  of 
those  arguments  which  we  quoted  from  St.  Thomas  to 
disprove  Hedonism  many  are  proofs  that  happiness 
(not  the  happiness  of  the  individual,  but  happiness 
simply)  is  not  our  final  end,  which  arguments,  there- 
fore, tell  equally  well  against  Utilitarianism  as  against 
Hedonism.     They  need  not  be  repeated  here.        ;'  ♦    2  ^  C 

(2)  Our  second  argument  in  proof  of  the  proposition         >  >  - 
that  neither  the  happiness  nor  the  well-being  of  society  ^ 

can  be  the  final  end  of  the  individual  is  that  which  we 
have  already  proved — that  all  men  are,  ordained  to  a 
common  end  other  than  mere  society,*  an  end  which  is 

♦  This  argument  is  given  by  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  in  answer  to  an 
objection  :  "  Ultimus  finis  cujuslibet  rei,"  he  objects,  "  est  in  suo 
opere  perfecto,  unde  pars  est  propter  totum  sicut  propter  finem. 
Sed  tota  universitas  creaturarum  .  .  .  coroparatur  ad  hominem  .  .  , 
sicut  perfectum  ad  imperfectum  :  ergo  beatitudo  (in  sense  of  final 
end)  hominis  consistit  in  tota  universitate  creaturarum."  To  which 
he  replies  :  "  Si  totum  aliquod  non  sit  ultimus  finis  sed  ordinetur  ad 
finem  ulteriorcm,  ultimus  fin  s  partis  non  est  ipsum  totum  s(d  aliquid 
aliud  :  univcrsitas  autem  creaturarum,  ad  quam  comparatur  homo 
ut  pars  ad  totum,  non  est  finis  ultimus,  sed  ordinatur  in  Deum  sicut 
in  ullimum  finem  ;  unde  bonum  universi  non  est  ultimus  finis  hominis, 
sed  ipse  Deus  "  ("  S.  Theol.,"  I.,  II.,  Q.  II.,  Art.  8). 

Vol.    I 21 


322  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

above  us  all  and  above  society — namely,  the  Infinite 
Good.  It  may  not  be  out  of  place  to  repeat  here  our 
proof  of  this  proposition.  The  final  natural  end  of  any- 
thing is  the  highest  end  which  is  attainable  by  its 
highest  capacity,  or  the  adequate  object  of  its  highest 
capacity.  Thus,  the  final  natural  end  of  a  tree  cannot 
be  mere  growth,  because  the  tree  has  other  higher 
capacities  than  growth — for  instance,  the  capacities  of 
bearing  fruit  and  flower  and  seed.  The  highest  act  of 
a  tree  will  be  its  final  end.  Now,  applyinpt^fi^'^  ppnr.iplp. 
to  man  (the  principle,  namely,  thaTTKe  final  end  of 
anything  is  that  end  which  answers  to  its  highest 
capacity),  we  find  that  no  finite  thing  can  be  our  final 
end,  for  no  finite  thing  can  satisfy  our  highest  appetite 
— ^that  is,  our  will,  which  is  capable  of  desiring  the 
perfect  or  Infinite  Good.  The  Infinite  Good,  therefore, 
is  the  final  end  of  all  men,  and  of  the  society  of  men. 
Society  and  the  happiness  of  society  are  finite  things, 
and,  therefore,  the  happiness  of  society  or  its  welfare 
cannot  be  our  final  end. 

But  though  society  and  its  happiness  or  welfare  are 
not  man's  final  end,  still  we  may  repeat  that  man  is  to 
some  extent  subordinate  to  society,  and  that  he  has 
important  duties  towards  society,  duties  of  promoting 
the  happiness  of  society.  In  other  words,  the  happiness 
of  society,  though  it  is  not  man's  final  end,  is  yet  an 
end,  and  a  necessary  end,  which  each  individual  man  is 
under  an  obligation  to  promote  according  to  his  oppor- 
tunities and  his  position  in  society. 

(3)  That  which  is  naturally  destined  to  attain  or 
promote  any  end  is  means  to  that  end.  But  a  free 
person  could  not  be  mere  means  to  that  end  in  reference 
to  which  he  is  free ;  and  as  man  is  free  in  reference  to 
society  he  cannot  be  regarded  as  mere  means  to  society, 
and  hence  society  is  not  his  final  end. 

(4)  The  natural  welKbcing  of  anything  depends  upon 
the  attaining  of  its  ultimate  end.  But  the  individual 
wcU-bcing  is  to  a  laige  extent  independent  of  the  race ; 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  323 

for  even  if  the  rest  of  the  race  were  perfectly  happy, 
still  the  individual,  even  though  he  were  to  devote 
himself  to  promoting  the  social  well-being,  might,  from 
a  variety  of  natural  causes,  be  very  miserable  and  im- 
perfect, and  therefore  his  end  must  be  something  other 
than  the  mere  good  of  the  race. 

(5)  Another   argument    which,    like    that    just    given, 
depends    upon    a    former    argument,*    but    which    yet 
emphasises   a   distinct   quality   in   natural   morality,   is 
the  following  :    The  natural  end  of  a  man's  actions  con-  ^y^ 
sists  in  something  that  must  of  necessity  he  actually  attained 

if  the  proper  means  he  taken.  A  tree,  for  instance,  will 
reach  its  final  end — viz.,  it  will  come  to  leaf  and  flower 
if  all  the  natural  means  be  taken  to  that  effect,  and  all 
the  natural  and  necessary  conditions  be  fulfilled — e.g.,  if 
it  get  air  enough,  light  enough,  moisture  enough,  &c. 
But  no  action  of  men  towards  one  another,  or  towards 
society  at  large,  will  ever  make  society  perfectly  happy, 
since  there  will  always  be  something  to  be  desired  by 
society  other  than  the  good  will  or  good  services  of 
men.  If  no  finite  good  can  satisfy  the  individual, 
a  fortiori  no  finite  good  can  satisfy  society.  No  means, 
therefore,  that  individuals  can  take  will  secure  the  final 
happiness  of  society.  Therefore,  the  happiness  of  society 
cannot  be  our  natural  end. 

(6)  If  the  happiness  of  society  be  our  end,  then  our 
final  end  is  to  be  attained  here  below,  f  We  have  shown 
that  this  is  impossible  % — that  every  condition  or  dis- 
tinguishing mark  of  the  final  end  is  wanting  here  below. 

*  We  think  it  only  fair  to  call  the  attention  of  the  reader  to  the 
fact  that,  if  thoroughly  examined,  arguments  3,  4,  and  5  will  be  found 
to  throw  us  logically  back  on  the  argument  that  all  men  and  all  society 
are  ordained  to  a  common  end  beyond  society — ^namely,  the  infinite 
good.     (This  is  given  in  2  above.) 

t  Hedonists  sometimes  claim  that  a  man's  end  lies  in  the  "  here- 
after," but  utilitarians  make  no  such  claim.  According  to  utilitarians, 
our  end  is  to  be  attained  on  earth.  Society,  of  course,  may  continue 
to  be  a  human  necessity  in  heaven,  but  utilitarians  generally  do  not 
contemplate  such  a  thing.  For  the  utilitarian,  society  means  the 
society  of  men  here  below. 

X  Chapter  3. 


324  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS  ' 

First,  the  goods  of  this  Hfe  cannot  fill  up  the  capacity 
of  our  will  (quietare  appetitum).  Secondly,  they  cannot 
be  enjoyed  without  much  accompanying  evil.  Thirdly, 
once  possessed  we  are  not  sure  of  retaining  them. 
They  may  go  from  us  at  any  moment.  For  these 
reasons  no  good  of  this  world  can  be  our  final  end, 
for  no  good  of  this  world  can  fill  up  the  measure  of  our 
natural  capacities,  and  give  that  absolute  rest  (quies) 
to  our  appetites  which  is  essential  to  the  last  end. 
But  the  happiness  of  society  is  an  earthly  thing  ;  it 
is  finite,  and  leaves  much  still  to  be  desired  by  our 
wills — that  is,  leaves  our  capacities  unfilled  ;  it  is  sub- 
ject to  evil,  for  on  this  earth  there  will  always  be  evil ; 
also,  it  is  uncertain  and  unstable.  It  cannot,  therefore, 
be  our  final  end. 

(7)  There  seems  to  be  a  strong  belief  even  amongst 
utilitarians  that  it  would  be  illogical  to  accept  the  view 
that  our  end  is  the  general  happiness  unless  there  be 
some  proof  that  this  is  our  end.  "It  is  important  to 
observe,"  writes  Sidgwick,*  "  that  the  principle  of 
aiming  at  universal  happiness  is  more  genuinely  felt  to 
require  some  proof,  or  at  least  (as  Mill  puts  it)  some 
considerations  determining  the  mind  to  accept  it,  than 
the  principle  of  aiming  at  one's  own  happiness."  If  the 
individual  man  is  free,  if  he  is  to  a  large  extent  inde- 
pendent of  society,  if  he  is  capable  of  desiring  much 
more,  and  can  only  be  satisfied  with  much  more  than 
society  is  ever  capable  of  giving  him,  if  the  happiness 
of  society  cannot  satisfy  him,  if,  finally,  society,  whilst 
it  accepts  his  services,  will  not  bear  any  of  the  burden 
of  his,  perhaps,  undeserved  miseries,  then  it  seems 
rational  that  the  individual  man  should  have  a  right 
to  ask  what  proof  there  is  that  the  good  of  society  is 
his  sole  final  end,  and  what  proof  that  he  is  bound  to 
make  such  personal  sacrifices  for  society  as  this  doctrine 
of  Utilitarianism  entails.  Now,  we  submit  that  this 
theory  has  not  been  proved.     And  in  support  of  our 

•  "  Methods,"  page  418. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  325 

contention  we  shall,  in  the  second  portion  of  this 
chapter,*  set  forth  and  examine  the  chief  arguments 
advanced  by  Utilitarians  in  defence  of  their  theories. 
Meanwhile,  we  shall  examine  the  utilitarian  theory 
from  a  second  point  of  view — that,  namely,  of  its 
criterion  and  its  practicability  as  a  science  of  right 
living. 

id)  ijtilitarianism  an  impracticable  and  impossible 
^^,^  Criterion  of  Morality 

Having  seen  that  the  happiness  or  welfare  of  society 
is  not  our  final  end,  we  now  go  on  to  show  that,  even 
if  the  happiness  of  society  were  our  end,  we  could  not 
determine  with  any  degree  of  accuracy  what  acts  would 
lead  thereto,  and  that,  therefore.  Utilitarianism  is  not  a 
practical  or  possible  criterion  of  right  and  wrong.  This 
argument  need  not  be  drawn  out  to  any  length,  since 
we  have  already  prepared  the  way  for  it  in  our  chapter 
on  Hedonism. 

The  difficulty  of  applying  the  utilitarian  criterion  to 
actual  practice  turns  principally  on  the  fact  that  on  the 
utilitarian  theory  we  have  to  determine  quantity  of 
pleasure  or  of  welfare  before  we  can  judge  of  the 
morality  of  actions ;  and  this  proposition  that  the 
utilitarian  must  determine  quantity  of  pain  or  pleasure 
is  inferred  from  another  proposition — viz.,  that  an 
ethical  theory  that  judges  by  effects  merely  must  de- 
termine such  quantity,  t  Now,  in  a  theory  that  deter- 
mines morality  by  consequences  the  necessity  of  quanti- 
tatively determining  effects  must  always  arise,  because 
our  acts  have  often  most  opposed  consequences,  some 
pleasant,  some  painful,  which  it  is  necessary  to  com- 
pare and  reduce  to  a  resultant  in  order  to  know  on 
which  side  the  balance  is — on  that  of  pleasure  or  that  of 

*  Section  (e). 

t  That  Utilitananifan  j  ...gcs  morality  by  effects  merely  is  evident 
from  the  very  definition  vi   I'tilitarinri'-ni. 

; 


326  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

pain,  of  welfare  or  of  injury.  The  great  difficulty  of 
the  utilitarian  theory  is  the  difficulty  of  determining 
these  consequences. 

Concerning  this  difficulty  of  determining  the  conse- 
quences of  action  we  have  already  spoken  in  our  chapter 
on  Hedonism,  We  there  showed  the  impossibility  of 
calculating  the  pleasures  and  the  pains  which  actions 
bring  to  the  doer  of  the  action,  or  of  comparing  these 
pleasures  and  pains  with  one  another,  so  as  to  obtain 
the  resultant  feeling  in  case  we  did  succeed  in  summing 
them  separately.  The  difficulties  arising  are  many.  If 
the  method  followed  be  the  a  posteriori  method  of 
experience  and  common  sense  then  there  is  (i)  the 
difficulty  of  measuring  any  feeling  except  the  most 
intense,  (2)  the  difficulty  of  knowing  all  the  feelings 
which  result  from  actions,  (3)  of  balancing  pleasures 
against  pains,  (4)  of  comparing  pleasures  with  one 
another  so  as  to  obtain  a  sum  of  pleasures,  (5)  of  ex- 
amining present  pleasures  or  fully  recalling  remembered 
ones,  (6)  of  saying  how  far  into  our  lives  the  influence 
of  our  early  acts  extends  and  consequently  of  determin- 
ing all  the  pleasures  and  pains  these  acts  produce,  (7) 
of  determining  how  far  our  pleasures  and  our  pains 
depend  on  our  humours  and  character,  and  (8)  on  the 
accidents  of  life. 

On  the  other  hand,  if  the  method  followed  be  a  priori, 
or  what  we  have  called  the  scientific  method — the 
method,  that  is,  of  deducing  the  pleasure  and  pain- 
results  from  some  theory  of  the  cause  or  law  of  pleasure, 
then  we  have  the  insuperable  difficulty  already  referred 
to  of  determining  the  cause  of  pleasure,  and  of  knowing, 
even  if  we  should  succeed  in  determining  the  cause 
of  pleasure,  when  and  in  what  cases  this  cause  is 
realised. 

Now,  if  all  these  are  difficulties  against  the  possibility 
of  calculating  the  pleasures  and  pains  experienced  by 
the  individual  man,  the  difficulties  of  determining  the 
pleasures  and  pains  which  actions  produce  in  society  at 


ON  UTILITARIANISM 


327 


large  must  be  very  much  greater.  To  examine  our  own 
feelings  is  difficult,  but  to  examine  the  feelings  of  other 
people  is  more  difficult  still.  Equally  difficult  is  the  task 
of  comparing  the  pleasures  which  an  act  produces  in 
some  with  the  pains  which  it  brings  to  others,  and  of 
determining  the  resultant  of  these  pleasures  ind  pains. 
If,  then.  Hedonism  fails  as  a  criterion  of  conduct,  Utili- 
tarianism fails  still  more  signally.  Indeed,  it  is  only 
when  we  take  up  for  consideration  some  particular 
action,  and  try  to  determine  practically  its  consequences 
on  society,  that  we  really  come  to  understand  the  utter 
impossibility  of  using  the  utilitarian  criterion  in  the 
drawing  up  of  a  moral  code. 

But,  as  in  the  case  of  Hedonism  so  also  in  the  case  of 
Utilitarianism,  there  are  some  who  claim  that  the  diffi- 
culty of  determining  the  consequences  of  action  is 
imaginary,  since  it  depends  on  the  false  supposition 
that  it  is  necessary  to  predict  the  effect  of  an  action 
taken  in  individiw  et  in  concreio,  whereas  it  is  only 
necessary  to  determine  the  tendency  of  a  line  of  action 
in'  general,  and  apart  from  individual  circumstances, 
or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  to  determine  what  would 
actually  happen  if  such  a  line  of  action  were  allowed  in 
general.  This  theory  is  defended  by  Whewell,  Paley, 
and  many  other  utilitarians. 

Now,  we  showed  in  our  chapter  on  Hedonism  that  a 
theory  that  regards  the  goodness  and  badness  of  acts  as 
constituted  by  the  consequences  of  these  acts  cannot 
logically  ignore  the  effects  of  the  particular  act.  And 
since,  according  to  Utilitarianism,  moral  good  and  evil 
are  constituted  by  the  consequences  of  acts.  Utili- 
tarianism must  take  account  of  the  particular  as  well  as 
the  general  consequences — that  is,  of  the  actual  effect  of 
this  individual  act  on  society  in  a  particular  case,  and 
not  merely  the  general  tendency  of  such  acts  to  affect 
society  well  or  ill,  or  the  effects  that  would  follow  if 
an  act  were  generally  allowed.  Consequently,  the 
difficulty   of   predicting   the   effects   of   individual    acts 


328  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

applies  in  the  case  of  Utilitarianism,  and  hence  we 
cannot  regard  the  criterion  of  Utilitarianism  as  a  practical 
or  reliable  criterion  of  the  morality  of  acts.* 

But,  now,  let  us  for  the  moment  suppose  that  the 
difficulty  of  determining  the  consequences,  whether  par- 
ticular or  general,  has  been  overcome,  and  that  we  can 
predict  these  consequences  with  absolute  precision. 
There  will  still  remain  one  (to  our  mind)  insuperable 
difficulty  in  regard  to  the  use  of  the  utilitarian  criterion 
— namely,  the  difficulty  of  its  consistent  application  to 
moral  cases,  where  the  particular  and  the  general 
consequences  are  opposed.     We  shall  explain  this  diffi- 


*  Some  curious  results  will  be  obtained  by  the  consistent  utilitarian 
who  logically  works  out  particular  cases  by  actual  results  to  society,  not 
by  general  rules.  For  instance,  granted,  as  proved  above,  that  a  con- 
sistent utilitarian  must  judge  in  particular  cases  by  actual  results,  not 
by  general  rules  or  tendencies,  what,  following  the  utilitarian  theory, 
is  a  man  to  do  who  feels  that  he  can  steal  from  another  without  making 
society  unhappy  ?  The  owner  will,  of  course,  suffer  some  unhappiness 
in  the  loss  of  his  money,  but  the  robber  gains  equally  in  happiness  by 
acquiring  the  money,  and  if  he  be  a  poor  man  his  gain  in  happiness  will 
more  than  counterbalance  the  actual  pain  experienced  by  the  rightful 
owner.  Is  the  act  of  stealing  lawful  in  this  case  ?  If  an  act  be  lawful 
or  unlawful  because  of  the  pleasure  or  pain  it  brings  to  society,  then 
since  in  this  case  the  happiness  that  is  lost  in  one  part  of  society  is 
gained  in  another,  it  would  seem  that  the  effect  on  society  as  a  whole  is 
nil,  and  that,  so,  the  act  is  neither  good  nor  bad  but  indifferent,  and 
therefore  morally  allowable. 

This  consideration  (we  do  not  call  it  an  argument,  for,  as  we  said 
before,  we  do  not  regard  it  as  either  a  proof  or  a  disproof  of  any  theory 
of  morals  to  show  that  it  is  consistent  or  inconsistent  with  our  code) 
may  be  answered  by  the  utilitarian  saying  that  the  general  good  could 
not  possibly  be  promoted  unless  there  existed  a  law  of  distribution  of 
happiness,  and  the  first  requisite  of  proper  distribution  is  that  each 
man  be  given  and  allowed  to  enjoy  "  his  owri  "  (Cuique  suum),  and 
that  therefore,  though  the  case  of  moral  jugglery  we  have  just  given 
raises  difficulties  for  a  Utilitarianism  of  our  own  making,  it  raises 
none  for  a  genuine  theory  of  Utilitarianism  which  postulates  such  a 
law.  Still  we  submit  that  this  utilitarian  reply  is  not  altogether 
satisfactory.  For  we  grant  that  on  the  utilitarian  theory  there  should 
be  a  general  law  of  distribution — a  law  to  give  each  his  own,  if  the 
general  good  is  to  be  forwarded.  But,  nevertheless,  we  conceive  a 
case  of  some  individual  coming  to  the  utilitarian  in  the  quiet  of  his 
study  and  claiming  to  be  allowed  in  this  particular  case  to  increase 
the  sum  of  general  happiness  by  stealing  from  his  rich  master,  and  on 
utilitarian  principles  we  do  not  know  how  such  a  man  can  be  prevented 
from  stealing. 

On  this  same  problem  the  reader  might  refer  to  our  account  of 
Spencer's  theory,  page  420. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  329 

culty  by  an  example.  Let  us  suppose  a  case  of  murder, 
which,  on  account  of  the  individual  circumstances,  is 
certain  to  bring  a  surplusage  of  happiness  to  the  race 
at  large  (the  supposition  is  quite  possible  in  the  case  of 
persons  suffering  from  certain  contagious  diseases,  whose 
death,  therefore,  would  relieve  society  of  much  appre- 
hension and  much  evil  of  every  kind).  Now,  we  take 
it  that  no  utilitarian  would  regard  such  an  act  as  lawful 
or  good,  and  his  plea  for  not  allowing  it  is  that,  in  judg- 
ing the  morality  of  an  act,  we  should  take  account 
not  of  the  particular  but  of  the  general  effects — that  is, 
not  the  effects  of  this  particular  act  in  these  particular 
circumstances,  but  the  general  tendency  of  such  acts 
in  regard  to  society.  And  we  shall  allow  this  argu- 
mentation to  stand  for  the  moment.  But  if  this  be 
the  law  of  procedure  with  regard  to  the  case  of  con- 
tagious diseases,  the  utilitarian  must  adopt  the  very 
same  law  of  procedure  with  regard  to  every  other  kind 
of  evil.  Now,  lying,  all  would  admit,  tends  in  general 
to  bring  evil  consequences  to  the  race.  But  let  us 
suppose  that  a  statesman  by  telling  a  lie  could  save  the 
world  from  all  the  horrors  of  an  international  war,  is 
he  on  the  Utilitarian  theory  free  morally  to  tell  a  lie 
and  save  the  world  from  certain  universal  unhappiness  ? 
A  consistent  utilitarian  should  answer  "  No,"  since  in 
the  case  of  leprosy  and  murder  it  was  the  general  and 
not  the  particular  consequences  that  determined  the 
morality  of  the  act,  and,  as  in  these  cases,  so  also  in  the 
case  of  lying,  the  general  consequences  are  hurtful  to 
society.  We  believe,  however,  that  utilitarians  generally 
would  in  this  case  of  lying  judge  by  the  particular 
consequences  only,  and  would  not  only  allow  the  lie, 
but  even  regard  it  as  morally  necessary.  But  what, 
then,  about  the  general  tendency  of  lying  ?  Is  not  the 
"  general  tendency  "  in  this  case  thrown  to  the  winds, 
and  are  not  the  actual  effects  of  the  act  in  the  circum- 
stances made  the  binding  rule  of  conduct  ?  But  this 
act  is  an  exception,  it  will  be  said.     So,  we  answer,  was 


33d  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  other  act  an  exception,  and  so  is  every  act  an  ex- 
ception in  which  the  general  tendency  is  negatived  by 
the  actual  circumstances  of  the  case.  And  if  we  are 
bound  to  judge  by  the  actual  effects  in  this  case,  so  must 
we  judge  in  every  case  if  we  would  be  consistent  utili- 
tarians. 

This  difficulty  of  consistency  in  the  application  of  the 
criterion  of  Utilitarianism  seems  to  us  to  be  inseparable 
from  the  theory  of  Utilitarianism,  and  is  by  itself  alone 
convincing,  proof  of  the  all-round  unworkability  of 
Utilitarianism  as  an  ethical  system. 

f    («)y  Consideration  of  the  Arguments  for  the  Utili- 
V_J-^       TARiAN  Theory  that  the  Final  End  of  the 

Individual  is  the  Happiness  or  Welfare  of 

Society 

In  a  previous  section  we  showed  that  the  happiness 
or  well-being  of  society  is  not  man's  final  natural  end  ; 
and  we  promised,  towards  the  close  of  that  section,  to 
take  up  for  consideration,  later  on  in  the  present  chapter, 
the  opposing  arguments  of  the  utilitarians.  This  promise 
we  now  propose  to  fulfil. 

The  arguments  of  the  utilitarians  may  be  divided  as 
follows  :  First,  that  derived  from  Psychology,  that  in 
man  there  are  original  benevolent  impulses  ;  secondly, 
argument  drawn  from  Hedonism,  that  the  law  of  seeking 
our  own  good  includes  the  law  of  seeking  the  good  of 
all ;  thirdly,  argument  drawn  from  the  fact  that  the 
moral  law  is  "  categorical  and  objective,"  and,  therefore, 
that  it  concerns  the  good  of  the  whole  race,  not  a  mere 
part  ;  fourthly,  argument  drawn  from  the  common  con- 
ception of  Morals,  which,  -it  is  contended,  identifies 
"  good  "  with  "  universal  happiness  "  ;  fifthly,  argu- 
ment drawn  from  Pragmatism,  that  Utilitarianism  as  a 
moral  theory  is  found  to  work ;  sixthly,  argument 
drawn  from  the  theory  of  the  "  solidarity  of  society,"  the 
theory,  viz.,  that  the  individual  is  nothing  apart  from 


ON  UTlLlTAiRiANiSM  331 

society,  and  is  indebted  to  society  for  all  that  he  is  and 
has  ;  seventhly,  argument  drawn  from  the  necessity  of 
Utilitarianism  to  account  for  many  of  our  moral  in- 
tuitions. 

(i)  Argument   drawn   from   Psychology   that   in   man 
there  are  natural  benevolent  impulses. 

This  argument  is  essentially  a  theory  that  there  are 
in  us  original  impulses  which  have  for  their  object  the 
good  of  others,  not  the  good  of  determined  persons 
merely,  but  of  all  men. ,  Being  original,  or  given  to  man 
by  nature,  the  claims  which  these  benevolent  impulses 
make  upon  us,  it  is  asserted,  should  be  observed  in  all 
our  acts,  and,  therefore,  they  make  it  our  duty  in  every 
act  to  seek  the  general  good.  It  is  not,  indeed,  asserted 
that  these  impulses  comprise  our  whole  appetitive  nature 
as  men,  for  it  is  agreed  that  we  have  in  us  selfish  im- 
pulses as  well.  Shaftesbury,  for  instance,  considered 
that  the  benevolent  impulses  should  even  be  tempered 
by  the  selfish,  and  an  equilibrium  of  impulse  be  secured 
thereby.  But  utilitarians  generally  infer  from  the 
presence  of  these  benevolent  impulses  a  duty  in  all  our 
actions  to  seek  the  good  of  all — the  individual  himself 
counting  as  only  one  amongst  the  total  number  of 
men. 

Reply — We  have  to  consider  two  points — {a)  Granted 
these  impulses,  what  is  the  ethical  conclusion  they 
necessitate  ?  {h)  Are  our  benevolent  impulses  original, 
or  are  they  derivatives  from  the  impulse  for  our  own 
happiness  ? — for  if  they  are  offshoots  or  derivatives  from 
the  impulse  for  our  own  happiness,  then  the  impulse  to 
our  own  happiness  will  be  more  fundamental  than  the 
impulse  of  benevolence,  and  the  final  end  of  man  will 
be  not  the  good  of  society  but  a  man's  own  good.* 

*  We  must  keep  before  the  reader  that  we  still  admit  a  large  smd 
important  duty  of  benevolence. 


332  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(a)  We  maintain  that  even  if  we  have  in  us  original 
benevolent  impulses,  the  largest  duty  that  these  impulses 
could  give  rise  to  would  be  a  particular  duty  of  benevo- 
lence. They  could  not  determine  the  whole  moral  law 
for  us.  If  we  have  selfish  impulses  as  well,  then  these 
should  also  determine  part  of  our  duty.  Hence,  even  if 
we  have  benevolent  impulses,  our  sole  final  end  would 
not  be  necessarily  the  general  happiness  or  welfare. 
But,  it  will  be  said,  the  benevolent  impulses  relate  to 
the  good  of  all  and  the  selfish  to  the  good  of  one  man 
only,  and  two  such  impulses  would  not  be  properly 
balanced  unless  we  sought  our  own  good  as  a  part 
merely  of  the  general  happiness.  Our  reply  is  that  this 
contention  might  be  allowed  did  not  the  impulse  for 
our  own  good  outweigh  all  the  other  impulses.  And 
that  it  does  outweigh  all  others  is  evident  from  the 
fact  that  in  every  act  we  must  wish  our  own  good, 
whereas  it  is  rarely  that  the  benevolent  impulses  assert 
themselves  within  us.  Our  benevolent  impulses  have 
no  part,  for  instance,  in  inducing  us  to  eat  or  drink  or 
study  mathematics.  Hence,  the  impulse  for  our'  own 
good  is  of  more  importance  in  the  constitution  of  man 
than  that  of  benevolence,*  and,  therefore,  the  presence 
of  benevolent  impulses  in  us  does  not  prove  that  the 
general  happiness  is  our  final  end. 

[b)  But  now  we  shall  show  by  another  argument 
that  our  benevolent  impulses  are  naturally  far  out- 
weighed by  that  for  our  own  good.  Our  argument  is 
that  our  benevolent  impulses  are  not  original  and  un- 
derived,  but  are  merely  a  natural  offshoot  from  our  de- 
sire for  our  own  good.  There  is  in  the  will  but  one 
original  natural  impulse — viz.,  the  impulse  of  the  will 
to  the  attainment  of  its  natural  object — our  own  good. 

•  The  importance  of  this  desire  for  our  own  good  is  brought  out  by 
St.  Thomas  Aquinas  in  "  S.  Theol.,"  II.,  IT"".,  Q.  26,  A.  (>,  wlicre  he 
says,  sfxJHking  of  tlic  love  of  other  men,  that  we  should  love  more 
^tensely  those  who  are  near  to  us  than  those  who  are  near  to  God — a 
remarkable  admission  from  St.  Thomas  Aquinas. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  333 

On  this  love  of  our  own  good  is  based  every  other  im- 
pulse of  our  will.  We  may,  if  we  like,  call  this  desire 
selfish  in  the  sense  that  it  is  always  a  desire  for  our 
own  good.  But  whether  we  regard  it  as  selfish  or  not, 
on  it  is  based  every  other  desire  of  the  will.  Now,  this 
law  that  we  must  desire  our  own  good  is  by  no  means 
to  be  interpreted  as  meaning  that  we  cannot  desire  the 
good  of  others.  On  the  contrary,  "  our  own  good  " 
may  be  sought  in  another  person.  Our  own  good  may 
consist  in  seeking  the  good  of  another,  not  in  the  sense 
that  we  may  make  another's  happiness  a  means  to  our 
own,  but  in  the  sense  that  we  can  come  to  regard 
another's  happiness  as  our  own,  and  this  power  of 
regarding  the  happiness  of  another  person  as  our  own 
is  the  root  and  principle  of  benevolence.  How  the  love 
of  one's  own  good  comes  to  take  the  form  of  benevolence 
is  one  of  the  most  interesting  problems  in  philosophy. 
It  has  been  fully  treated  by  St.  Thomas  Aquinas,  follow* 
ing  Aristotle. 

A  man,  according  to  St.  Thomas,  may  love  others 
with  either  of  two  kinds  of  love — either  the  amor  con- 
cupiscentiae  *  or  the  amor  amicitiae.  In  amor  concupi- 
scentiae  we  love  a  thing  or  a  person  on  account  of  some 
advantage  accruing  to  ourselves  ;  for  instance,  we  may 
love  a  ruler  because  he  is  kind  to  us.  In  amor  amicitiae 
we  love  a  person  for  his  own  sake  alone.  Plainly, 
benevolence  is  the  love  of  the  second  kind,  and  it  is 
with  this  amor  amicitiae  and  benevolence  that  we  are 
now  concerned  in  this  present  section.  On  what  is 
this  love  of  benevolence  based  ?  "A  man,"  writes 
St.  Thomas,  "  is  never  said  to  be  friendly  towards  him- 
self. He  is  related  to  himself  by  something  deeper  than 
friendship.  By  friendship  we  effect  a  union  with  other 
people.  But  a  man's  relation  to  himself  is  something 
deeper  than  union — it  is  a  relation  of  unity  itself,  and 
unity  is  deeper  than  union — it  is  even  the  principle  of 

*  The  expression  is  technical.  It  must  not  be  supposed  to  imply 
necessarily  a  sensual  element  in  desire. 


? 


334  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

union.  And  as  unity  is  the  principle  of  union,*  so  is 
the  love  of  one's  self  the  principle  and  root  of  friendship. 
A  man  is  said  to  be  friendly  to  others,  just  in  so  far 
forth  as  his  attitude  towards  them  is  the  same  as  his  attitude 
to  himself.  As  Aristotle  says  in  9^  Ethic,  '  things 
appertaining  to  others — that  is,  to  friendship — are 
grounded  on  that  which  appertains  to  the  love  of  one's 
self"  ("S.  TheoL,"  IP.,  IP.,  XXV.).  The  love, 
therefore,  of  one's  own  good  is,  according  to  St.  Thomas 
and  Aristotle,  the  root  of  benevolence,  as  it  is  of  every 
other  human  impulse. 

But  we  certainly  cannot  stop  at  this.  We  must  go 
farther  and  explain  how  benevolence  can  be  grounded 
in  the  love  of  one's  own  good,  how  from  self-love  as  root 
we  may  obtain  the  flower — benevolence.  The  question 
can  be  put  in  the  form  of  a  difficulty  thus  :  In  every  act 
we  must  seek  our  own  good  ;  how,  then,  can  we  seek 
the  good  of  others  for  their  own  sakes  alone,  and  in 
particular  how  can  this  second  desire  be  grounded  on 
the  first  ?  Now,  there  would  be  no  difficulty  in  ex- 
plaining this  if,  instead  of  benevolence,  we  had  to  deal 
with  the  amor  concupiscentiae  merely — that  is,  loving 
a  man  because  he  is  good  to  us,  for  in  the  love  of  self 
is  contained  the  love  of  others  as  they  minister  to  one's 
self.  But  it  seems  hard  to  get  from  the  love  of  one's 
own  good  to  benevolence,  which  is  the  love  of  some 
one  for  his  own  sake  (or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  the 
wishing  of  good  to  another  for  his  own  sake)  alone. 
Still,  the  transition  is  possible,  and  as  effected  by  St. 
Thomas,  following  Aristotle,  it  is  highly  interesting  and 


•  Sidgwick  writes  :  "  Love  is  not  merely  a  desire  to  do  good  to  the 
object  beloved,  although  it  always  involves  such  a  desire.  It  is 
primarily  a  pleasurable  emotion,  which  seems  to  depend  on  a  certain 
sense  of  union  with  another  person  "  ("  Methods,"  244).  Sidgwick 
finds  great  difficulty  in  saying  whether  intense  love  for  an  individual 
is  a  moral  excellence  in  sense  of  a  benevolent  motive,  but  he  inclines 
to  the  negative  view.  Whether  he  is  rij^lit  in  this  \\v  sluiU  not  now 
inquire,  but  the  fact  is,  these  very  intense  loves  are  very  often  not 
examples  of  amor  amicitiae  but  of  amor  concupiscentiae,  and  that  is 
why  they  arc  often  not  benevolent. 


J 

ON  UTILITARIANISM  335 

worthy  of  St.  Thomas.*  It  is  made  to  depend  upon 
the  fundamental  natural  principle  of  union  between 
one  man  and  another — viz.,  our  common  human  nature. 
We  are  all,  according  to  St.  Thomas,  like  one  another  in 
our  human  nature — we  are  one  in  human  nature,  and 
we  differ  only  in  individual  characteristics.  On  that 
account  we  are  able  mentally  to  put  another  man  in  our  _ 
I  own  -place  and  wish  him  good  as  we  would  wish  it  to  our- 
selves. This  is  the  root  of  benevolence.  In  benevolence 
I  do  not  love  another  as  another,  because  for  that  it 
would  be  necessary  to  keep  my  neighbour  apart  mentally 
from  me,  to  regard  his  good  as  quite  a  distinct  thing 
from  mine.  Rather  I  put  him  in  my  own  place  on 
account  of  his  likeness  to  me,  make  of  him  an  alter  ego, 
regard  him  as  one  with  myself,  and  wish  him  well  ac- 
cordingly. Again,  we  quote  from  St.  Thomas  (P.,  11"., 
XXVII.,  3) — "  All  benevolence  is  grounded  in  likeness.f 
Two  men  that  have  the  same  form  are  one  in  that  form, 
and  all  men  are  one  in  their  humanity.  A  man's  love, 
therefore,  goes  out  to  another,  in  so  far  as  that  other 
is  one  with  himself,  and  he  will  consequently  wish  good 
to  that  other,  in  the  same  way  as  he  wishes  it  to  himself." 
Likeness  to  ourselves,  therefore,  is  the  root  of  friend- 
ship ("  omne  amans  amat  sibi  simile  ") — of  friendship  in 
its  best  sense — that  is,  as  benevolence.  Benevolence  is 
the  wishing  of  good  to  another  for  his  own  sake,  not  for 
mine,  and  this  wish  I  can  entertain  in  spite  of  the  fact 
that  benevolence  begins  in  the  love  of  my  own  good. 
For,  as  we  have  said,  in  benevolence  I  put  another  in 
my  place  for  the  moment,  who  then  becomes  my  alter 
ego ;  and  consequently  I  can  wish  him  good  in  the 
same  way  as  I  wish  it  to  myself.  In  benevolence, 
therefore,   the   love   of   self   is   not   extinguished — it   is 

*  It  is  not  a  doctrine  for  shallow  minds.  They  will  be  sure  to 
misunderstand  it. 

f  It  should  be  remembered  that  that  which  benevolence  loves  in 
another  must  be  something  which  a  man  esteems.  Else  the  benevolent 
lazy  man  could  love  only  lazy  men,  and  benevolent  bad  men  only  bad 
people  (see  Aristotle,  "  Nich.  Eth.,"  IX.,  5  (4)). 


336  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

rather  made  to  expand,  so  as  to  embrace  all  persons, 
whom,  therefore,  we  treat  as  we  would  treat  ourselves. 
This  is  the  highest  love  possible — to  treat  another  aS' 
we  would  treat  ourselves.  It  is  not  egoistic,  for  through 
I  it  we  desire  another's  pleasure,  not  our  own  personal 
pleasure.  It  is  not  the  amor  concupiscentiae,  for  by  it 
we  wish  another  well,  not  for  our  own  sake,  but  for 
his.  It  is  pure  benevolence.  In  amor  concupiscentiae 
I  wish  another  good  as  means  to  myself,  and,  therefore, 
as  distinct  from  myself.  In  benevolence  I  put  another 
man  in  my  own  place  and  make  his  "  good  "  mine.  In 
the  first  the  "  thine  "  is  distinct  from  the  "  mine:  "  in 
the  second  the  "  thine  "  is  the  "  mine."  * 

*  Of  modern  Ethicians  none  comes  closer  to  St,  Thomas  Aquinas 
in  his  analysis  of  benevolence  than  Leslie  Stephen.  He  gives  us  as 
the  rule  of  benevolence  to  another — "  Put  yourself  in  his  place  " 
("  Science  of  Ethics,"  page  230).  Again  he  writes,  "  So  far  as  I  sym- 
pathise with  you  I  annex  your  consciousness.  I  act  as  though  my 
nerves  could  somehow  be  made  continuous  with  yours  "  (page  236). 
And  lest  this  statement  should  be  taken  to  mean  that  I  sympathise 
with  your  pain  because  your  pain  brings  as  a  consequence  pain  to 
me  (as  distinct  from  you),  he  expressly  repudiates  this  interpretation 
(page  240).  The  theory  which  identifies  benevolence  with  regarding 
another  as  an  alter  ego  is  also  making  headway  amongst  French 
Ethicians.  Thus  Fouill6e,  in  his  account  of  the  Evolutionist  Ethics 
(in  "  La  Morale  Contemporaine  "),  regards  sympathy  as  arising  out 
of  the  common  consciousness  of  different  individuals  who  are  "  frferes 
siamois  par  la  tete  et  par  le  coeur,"  and  he  mentions  the  Darwinian 
interpretation  of  self-sacrifice  as  resulting  from  the  fact  that  "  les 
deux  poles,  moi  et  toi,  sont  intervertis." 

The  reader  in  considering  special  cases  of  love  or  kindness  should  be 
careful  to  distinguish  where  the  love  is  amor  concupiscentiae  and  where 
it  is  amor  amicitiae  or  benevolence,  for  it  is  not  always  easy  to  dis- 
tinguish between  them.  They  often  exist  in  the  same  mind  and 
towards  the  same  person.  Thus,  to  take  some  special  cases,  a  person 
with  qualities  that  arc  attractive  to  a  man  may  be  loved  by  that  man. 
Such  love  as  based  on  such  qualities  is  generally  the  amor  concupiscen- 
tiae. Now,  amor  concupiscentiae  is  a  good  and  a  useful  thing  ;  but  it 
is  not  benevolence,  A  man  loves  such  a  person  as  he  loves  a  beautiful 
scene  or  food — they  bring  him  pleasure.  But  the  same  person  may 
be  loved  amore  amicitiae,  i.e.,  a  man  may  desire  good  to  him  for  his 
own  sake.  Such  amor  amicitiae  or  benevolence  is  based,  not  on  some 
,  special  attractive  qualities  in  the  person,  but  upon  a  likeness  to  him 
who  loves.  Thus  a  father  who  loves  his  two  children  benevolently, 
loves  them  equally,  though  one  be  handsomer  and  more  attractive 
than  the  other,  liut  if  he  prefers  the  more  attractive  child  tins  pre- 
ference is  based,  not  on  benevolence,  but  on  the  amor  concupiscentiae ; 
for  it  is  a  preference  based  on  the  pleasure  given  to  himself,  and  it  is 
the  same  kind  of  preference  that  is  given  by  men  to  certain  kinds  of 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  337 

From  all  this  we  draw  an  important  conclusion — the 
only  one,  indeed,  that  has  any  bearing  on  our  present 
enquiry — viz.,  that  benevolence  is  not  an  original 
impulse  in  man.  On  the  contrary,  benevolence  is  a 
i  derivative  from  self-love  in  the  sense  of  the  love  of 
one's  own  good.  It  is,  indeed,  different  from  self-love, 
but  it  could  no  more  exist  without  self-love  than  the 
fruit  could  grow  without  the  tree.  Consequently,  the 
impulse  to  our  own  good  is,  in  the  order  of  nature, 
more  fundamental  than  that  to  the  good  of  the  race, 
and,  therefore,  the  good  of  the  race  cannot  be  our  final 
natural  end. 

And  what  we  say  of  benevolence  we  say  also  of  pity 
— pity  is  also  based  on  self-love.  Pity  is  benevolence 
towards  those  in  sorrow,  and,  again,  its  root  is  likeness 
to  ourselves.  "  Pity,"  writes  St.  Thomas,  "  is  compas- 
sion for  the  misery  of  another,  and  arises  from  the 
fact  that  we  are  pained  or  sorrowful  at  another's  pain. 
But  inasmuch  as  sorrow  relates  (properly)  only  to  (the 
loss  of)  our  own  good,  so  a  man  can  be  sorrowful  at 
another's  misery  only  in  so  far  as  he  regards  that  other's 
misery  as  his  own  "  (IP.,  IP.,  XXX.,  2). 

A  superficial  view  of  these  doctrines  of  St.  Thomas 
about  benevolence  and  pity  might  induce  one  to  think 
that  in  grounding  them  on  self-love  he  had  lowered 
the  standard  both  of  friendship  and  of  pity.  Maturer 
thought,  however,  will  reveal  the  opposite.  There  is  no 
higher  friendship  than  that  which  makes  me  regard  my 

food  or  wine,  m  which  cases  there  is  always  some  reference  to  the 
pleasure  which  the  presence  or  possession  of  the  object  gives  to  the 
individual  who  loves.  Granted  then  an  equal  degree  of  likeness 
between  the  objects  loved  and  him  who  loves,  pure  benevolence 
begets  equal  love.  Where  a  father's  love  is  one  of  pure  benevolence 
he  loves  all  his  children  equally,  because  their  likeness  to  him — that 
is,  their  family  connection  with  him — is  equal.  Where  patriotism  is 
purely  benevolent  one  loves  all  his  countrymen  with  an  equal  love, 
for  the  bond  is  the  same  with  all.  Where  the  love  of  humanity  is 
benevolent  all  men  are  loved  to  the  same  extent,  for  the  only  bond  is 
that  of  human  nature. 

The  clearest  example  of  benevolence  is  that  which  makes  us  love 
a  poor  man  who  has  no  attractions  for  us — a  kind  of  love  which  is  very 
different  from  our  love  for  attractive  people  or  for  beautiful  objects. 
Vol.  I — 22 


338 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


friend  as  an  alter  ego  ;   there  is  no.  deeper  pity  than  that 
which  makes  me  regard  another's  sorrow  as  my  own.* 

Pity,  then,  like  benevolence,  is  not  original ;  it  is  a 
derivative  (but  a  natural  derivative)  from  the  love  of 
one's  own  good.  Hence,  we  see — if  we  may  be  allowed 
to  carry  this  question  a  little  outside  the  region  of 
Ethics — how  wrong  Martineau  is  when  he  tells  us  that 

*  Schopenhauer  ("  The  Basis  of  Morals,"  III.,  i6)  gives  an  analysis 
of  pity  which  reads  like  a  page  from  St  Thomas  Aquinas.  "  In  these 
moments  (of  pity),"  he  writes,  "  the  line  of  demarcation  which 
separates  one  being  from  another  seems  to  disappear — the  non-ego 
to  a  certain  extent  becomes  the  ego."  In  order,  however,  to  avoid 
the  semblance  of  egoism,  he  then,  it  seems  to  us,  goes  too  far  on  the 
other  side,  saying  that  in  pity  I  do  not  imagine  the  grief  of  the  afflicted 
person  to  be  my  own,  rather  I  imagine  myself  as  happy,  and  contrast 
my  happiness  with  his  grief.  In  pity  my  neighbour's  sorrow  is  imagined 
as  his,  and  my  pity  is  all  the  greater — the  greater,  by  way  of  contrast, 
my  personal  joy.  Wundt  also  holds  the  same  extreme  altruistic 
view.  In  pity  "  we  do  not  take  on  the  sorrow  of  another,"  he  says, 
"  and  make  it  our  own,  because  there  could  be  no  greater  difference 
between  any  two  states  than  that  which  we  know  to  subsist  between 
the  hunger  of  the  hungry  man  and  the  pity  of  one  who  wishes  to  relieve 
him  "  (Ethik). 

In  contrast  with  this  view  of  Schopenhauer  and  Wundt,  there  are 
some  modem  theories  which  are  wholly  Egoistic — which,  therefore, 
though  thej'  are  in  some  respects  akin  to  the  theory  of  Aristotle  and 
St.  Thomas,  yet  must  be  carefully  distinguished  from  this  latter 
theory  because  according  to  these  latter  pity  is  wholly  benevolent ;  it 
rests  on  the  amor  amicitiae.  .it  is  wholly  a  movement  towards  another's 
good  (and  for  that  other's  sake)  whose  interest  I  yet  regard  as  my  own 
(as  said  above  I  make  of  that  other  an  alter  ego).  On  the  other  hand, 
the  Egoistic  theories,  to  which  we  refer  now,  make  pity  end  in  one's 
self  alone.  According  to  them,  pity  springs  from  the  amor  concupiscen' 
tiae,  or  the  love  of  another  as  means  merely  to  our  own  happiness. 
On  this  theory,  could  we  ourselves  get  the  same  happiness  that  we 
now  get,  without  the  happiness  of  the  other,  both  that  other  and  his 
interest  would  be  disregarded  by  us.  He  is  loved,  therefore,  not  for 
bis  own  sake,  but  for  ours  as  distinct  from  him. 

Bain  enumerates  four  such  egoistic  theories  :  (i)  The  theory  that 
we  love  or  pity  because  we  expect  to  obtain  an  immediate  reward 
fully  equivalent  to  the  sacrifice  made.  This  reward  may  be  in  kind 
or  not  (vide  Mandeville,  who  regards  flattery  as  the  principal  reward 
looked  to),  {2)  In  pity  we  are  pained  at  the  sight  of  an  object  in 
distress,  and  give  assistance  in  order  to  relieve  ourselves  of  the  pain 
(Hobbcs).  (3)  We  are  moved  to  benevolence  by  an  intrinsic  pleasure 
— i.e.,  by  the  pleasure  it  causes  in  us — and  we  are  moved  in  order  to 
cx{x;rience  that  pleasure  (Bcntham).  (4)  Benevolent  impulses  are  at 
first  purely  selfish  (we  love  and  pity  at  first  in  order  to  get  pleasure 
for  ourselves),  but  tliey  lx.'Come  purely  benevolent  later  on  "  by 
associations  and  habits  "  (James  Mill  and  Mackintosh).  These 
theories  are  evidently  distinct  from  the  view  expressed  by  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas.    They  are  in  no  sense  theories  of  pure  benevolence. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  339 

sympathy  with  suffering  is  so  grounded  in  our  nature — 
i.e.,  is  so  original  and  underived  in  our  constitution — 
that  "in  it  we  find  an  impressive  proof  that  pain  and 
sorrow  are  not  mere  uncontemplated  anomalies,  arising 
by  way  of  disorder  outside  the  idea  and  scheme  of  things, 
but  are  embraced  within  a  plan  of  human  life  and 
distinctly  provided  for  in  human  nature."  "  That  our 
constitution,"  he  adds,  "  is  furnished  with  this  medicine 
of  ill  indicates  a  system  constructed,  so  to  speak,  on  a 
theory  of  sorrow,  and  assigning  to  it  a  deliberate  place 
as  a  perpetual  element  of  discipline,  as  natural  and  not 
unnatural "  ("  Types,"  Vol.  XL).  In  this  passage 
Martineau  takes  it  for  granted  that  nature  furnishes 
every  man  originally  with  a  special  impulse  of  pity  or 
sympathy,  from  which  he  draws  the  conclusion  that 
sorrow,  and  therefore  evil,  are  a  necessary  part  of  the 
original  scheme  of  nature.  But  we  have  shown  that 
there  is  in  us  originally  and  fundamentally  no  such 
medicine  of  ill.  Pity,  like  benevolence,  is  a  derived 
I  impulse,  naturally  derived,  but  yet  derived.  In  the 
will  there  is  but  one  original  underived  impulse — namely, 
our  love  for  our  own  good. 

(2)  Argument  drawn  from  Hedonism. 

Utilitarians  argue  from  Ethical  Hedonism — that  is, 
from  happiness — as  the  supposed  end  of  man.  They 
extend  this  theory  from  the  happiness  of  the  individual 
to  the  happiness  of  all  men,  which  latter  happiness  then 
becomes  the  natural  end  of  the  individual.  They  offer 
two  proofs  drawn  from  Hedonism  for  their  theory  of 
the  happiness  of  all  men  as  the  Ethical  end  of  the 
individual.  The  first  proof  is  Mill's  rather  obsolete 
argument,  that  if  each  man's  happiness  is  the  end  of 
each,  then  all  men's  happiness  is  the  end  of  all,  and,i 
therefore,  all  men's  happiness  is  the  end  of  each.  His 
words  are — "  each  person's  happiness  is  a  good  to  that 
person ;  and  the  general  happiness,  therefore  (is),  a 
good  to  the  aggregate  of  all  persons,"  which  latter  pro- 


340  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

position  Mill  henceforth  treats  as  equal  to — the  general 
\  happiness  is  a  good  to  each  person.  The  second  is  the 
argument  used  by  Sidgwick,  Rashdall,  and  others,  that 
if  "  his  own  "  pleasure  be  not  only  an  end  to  every  man 
but  the  right  end  for  every  man,  an  end  that  he  ought 
to  pursue,  then  pleasure  gets  a  value  on  its  own  account 
objectively,  and  would  be  approved  of  by  an  Impartial 
Reason — that,  therefore,  the  words  "  his  own  "  could 
no  longer  be  considered  necessary  in  the  statement  that 
pleasure  is  the  end',  that  we  are  thus  led  to  the  con- 
clusion that  "  pleasure  (not  '  his  own  '  pleasure)  is  the 
end " — and  that  having  in  this  way  got  rid  of  the 
limitation  implied  in  the  words  "  his  own,"  the  law 
of  morals  naturally  announces  itself  thus — seek  pleasure, 
and  as  much  of  it  as  can  be  had,  or,  seek  all  men's 
pleasure. 

We  shall  now  examine  these  two  arguments. 

Mill's  Argument. — ^The  argument  used  by  Mill  is  a 
plain  sophism  which  it  will  not  be  necessary  to  consider 
at  any  length  here.  It  simply  uses  the  collective  sense 
of  the  word  "  every "  (that  is,  "  all  together ")  as 
equivalent  to,  and,  therefore,  interchangeable  with,  the 
distributive  sense  [i.e.,  each  one  separately).  Mill's 
first  proposition  is  that  each  man's  happiness  is  the 
end  of  each,  which  means  that  "  his  own  "  happiness  is 
the  end  of  each.  His  second  proposition  (which  he 
regards  as  a  consequence  *  of  the  first)  is  that  "  all 
men's  happiness  is  the  end  of  all."  This  means  that 
the  whole  body  of  men  in  their  collective  capacity 
{i.e.,  society)  should  seek  the  general  happiness.  The 
third  proposition,  which  is  supposed  to  result  from  the 
second,  or  to  be  the  equivalent  of  the  second,  is  that 
each  member  of  society  ought  to  seek  tke  general  good 
or  the  good  of  all  collectively.  Now,  to  infer  this  third 
proposition  from  the  second,  or  to  regard  them  as 
identical,  is  plainly  an  example  of  the  fallacy  of  Com- 

•  This  first  inference  might  very  well  be  questioned,  but  for  our 
pment  purpose  it  is  not  necessary  to  do  so. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  341 

position,  of  which  we  could  give  many  instances  exactly 
similar  in  form  to  Mill's  argument.  Such  a  similar 
instance  is  the  argument  that  if  a  hundred  men  have  a 
hundred  heads,  therefore  each  man  of  the  hundred  has 
a  hundred  heads,  an  inference  the  validity  of  which  it 
will  not  be  necessary  to  disprove. 

The  second  (Sidgwick's)  argument  requires  a  some- 
what closer  examination,  not  because  it  is  less  sophistic 
than  Mill's,  but  because  it  has  been  so  strangely  stated 
that  it  is  hard  to  find  the  sequence  of  it  and  to  show 
wherein  its  fallaciousness  consists.  We  shall  first  quote 
the  argument  as  given  by  Sidgwick  and  Professor 
Rashdall,  and  then  attempt  to  set  it  forth  clearly  in 
our  own  words. 

Sidgwick  writes  *  : — 

"  When,  however,  the  Egoist  puts  for\vard  implicitly  or 
explicitly  the  proposition  that  his  happiness  or  pleasure  is 
good  not  only  for  him,  but  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  Universe 
— as,  e.g.,  by  saying  that  nature  designed  him  to  seek  his  own 
happiness — it  then  becomes  relevant  to  point  out  to  him  that 
his  happiness  cannot  be  a  more  important  part  of  Good  taken 
universally  than  the  equal  happiness  of  any  other  person.  And 
thus  starting  with  his  own  principle  he  may  be  brought  to 
accept  Universal  happiness  or  pleasure  as  that  which  is 
absolutely  and  without  qualification  Good  or  Desirable  :  as 
an  end  therefore  to  which  the  action  of  a  reasonable  agent 
as  such  ought  to  be  directed." 

And  Professor  Rashdall  writes  j  : — 

"  He  (the  Egoist)  declares  not  merely  that  pleasure  is  his  J 
object,  but  that  pleasure  is  the  only  reasonable  object  of 


*  "  Methods,"  page  420.  In  the  last  chapter  of  his  "  Methods  " 
Sidgwick  himself  seems  to  us  to  express  a  want  of  confidence  in  th^ 
above  line  of  argument,  for  he  insinuates  that  it  does  not  amount  to 
what  is  properly  a  "  proof  "  of  Utilitarianism.  Yet,  in  an  earlier 
chapter,  he  seems  confident  enough  about  its  validity. 

t  "  Theory  of  Good  and  Evil,"  Vol.  I.,  page  44. 

{  All  the  italics  in  the  above  quotation  are  ours,  except  the  first, 
which  is  Prof.  Rashdall's  own.  We  have  italicised  those  phrases 
which  seem  to  us  to  be  the  turning  points  in  the  argument — i.e.,  the 
points  of  transition  from  Egoism  to  Universalism. 


342  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

desire,  that  every  reasonable  man  must  agree  with  him  in 
thinking  that  his  own  pleasure  is  to  each  the  only  proper 
object  of  pursuit,  that  anyone  who  pursues  any  other  aim 
is  unreasonable  and  makes  a  mistake.  And  when  that 
attitude  is  adopted  it  becomes  possible  to  urge  that  he  is 
implicitly  appeahng  to  a  universal  standard  which  must  be 
the  same  for  all  men*  The  pursuit  of  pleasure  f  is  approved, 
not  merely  because  it  chances  to  be  the  end  that  he  prefers, 
but  because  it  is  in  some  sense  the  true  end,  the  end  that 
ought  to  be  pursued.  The  champion  of  pleasure  may  indeed 
contend  that  the  Universal  Rule  which  Reason  approves  is 
not  that  pleasure  in  general  ought  to  be  pursued,  but  that 
each  man  should  pursue  his  own  pleasure. J  But  an  Egoistic 
Hedonist  of  this  type  is  liable  to  be  asked  on  what  ground  an 
impartial  or  impersonal  Reason  should  take  up  this  position.^ 
He  may  be  asked  whether  when  he  condemns  the  pursuit  of 
ends  other  than  pleasure  ij  he  does  not  imply  that  the  claims 
of  this  end  ^\  are  dependent  not  upon  the  individual's  chance 
likings   but   upon  something  in  pleasure  itself**  something 

*  This  sentence  has  no  connection  with  what  goes  before  (it  is 
meant  to  be  a  conclusion  from  what  goes  before),  unless  it  means — 
all  men  agree  that  "  his  own  "  pleasure  is  the  proper  end  for  each  man, 
and  to  that  universal  opinion  we  appeal  for  our  theory  that  each  man 
must  seek  his  own  happiness  only — and  to  pursue  any  other  aim,  as 
is  said  above,  is  unreasonable. 

t  Here  Prof.  Rashdall  has  let  drop  the  words  "  his  own  "  before 
"  pleasure."  He  should  not  have  done  so  if  the  sequence  of  the  argu- 
ment is  to  be  maintained.  Of  course  Prof.  Rashdall  must  mean  "  his 
own  pleasure  "  at  this  point,  but  it  would  be  better  to  say  so  on  account 
of  the  nature  of  the  matter  in  dispute. 

J  The  logician,  whether  a  champion  of  pleasure  or  not,  does  not 
say  so  ;  he  merely  says  that  if  there  is  to  be  sequence  in  the  argument 
then  "  pleasure  "  cannot  be  used  as  equivalent  exactly  to  "  his  own 
pleasure,"  and  that  we  should  not  let  drop  "  his  own  "  without  saying 
why.  Up  to  this  the  only  "  pleasure  "  that  preserves  the  logical 
.sequence  is  "  his  own  pleasure."  If  Prof.  Rashdall  lets  drop  the 
words  "  his  own  "  without  giving  reasons,  he  has  abandoned  his  line 
of  argument,  and  has  begun  merely  to  make  disconnected  assertions. 

§  Because  this  was  the  point  reached  in  the  argument  above,  and 
beyond  this  we  did  not  get — "  every  rea.sonable  man  must  agree  with 
him  in  thinking  that  his  own  pleasure  is  to  each,"  &c. 

II  The  Egoistic  Hedonist  admits  only  one  pleasure,  i.e.,  "  his  own  " 
pleasure.  This  must  be  understood  in  the  text  above  if  the  sequence 
of  the  argument  is  to  be  maintained. 

^  i.e.,  "  his  own  pleasure." 

•♦  The  Egoist  did  not  assert  that  "  pleasure  "  was  the  end,  but  that 
"  his  own  "  pleasure  was  the  end  ;  and  on  Prof.  Raslulall's  own  con- 
fession, all  men  are  agreed,  or  the  Universal  Kea.son  is  juTsuadcd,  that 
that  is  the  only  and  proper  end.  The  Hedonist,  therefore,  is  only 
logically  bound  to  admit  that  it  is  "  something  in  one's  own  pleasure  " 
itself,  &c. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  343 

which  Reason  discerns  in  it,  and  which  every  Reason  that 
really  is  Reason  must  likewise  discern  in  it.  And  if  that  is 
so,  he  may  further  be  asked  why  Reason  should  attach  more 
importance  to  one  man's  pleasure  than  to  another's*  If  it  is 
pleasure  that  is  the  end  it  cannot  matter,  it  may  be  urged, 
whose  pleasure  it  is  that  is  promoted. f  The  greatest  pleasure  J 
mtist  always  be  preferable  to  the  less  pleasure,  even  though 
the  promotion  of  the  greatest  pleasure  on  the  whole  should 
demand  that  this  or  that  individual  should  sacrifice  some  of 
his  private  pleasure.  From  this  point  of  view  it  will  seem 
impossible  that  Reason  should  approve  the  universal  rule 
that  each  should  pursue  his  private  pleasure  with  the  result 
of  losing  pleasure  on  the  whole.  The  rational  rule  of  con- 
duct will  appear  to  be  that  each  individual  should  aim  at 
the  greatest  pleasure  on  the  whole, §  and  that  when  a  greater 
pleasure  for  the  whole  can  be  procured  by  the  sacrifice  of  an 
individual's  private  pleasure,  the  sacrifice  should  be  made. 
The  Egoists'  appeal  to  Reason  |! — the  setting  up  of  Egoism  1j 
as  an  objectively  rational  rule  of  conduct,  the  condemnation 
as  irrational  of  those  who  pursue  any  other  end  ** — seems 
therefoie  to  react  against  his  own  position. ff     The  logic  of 


•  For  the  purposes  of  valid  reasoning,  that  is  all.  Prof.  Rashdall 
has  undertaken  to  prove  Utilitarianism.  It  is  of  importance,  therefore, 
that  he  should  give  the  full  term  each  time  a  term  occurs.  The  question 
is  not  whether  one  man's  happiness  is  more  important  than  another's, 
but  whether,  in  the  course  of  the  argument,  we  have  as  yet  got  away 
logically  from  that  annoying  particle  "  his  own."  If  the  present  argu- 
ment is  not  to  be  regarded  as  a  logical  proof  of  Utilitarianism,  if  the 
Hedonist  is  simply  being  asked  to  prove  something  himself — namely, 
to  prove  his  theory,  or  to  give  reasons  why  one  man's  happiness  is 
more  important  than  another's,  it  would  be  better  to  say  so  ;  but  Prof. 
Rashdall  has  evidently  undertaken  to  prove  the  Universalistic  theory, 
granted  the  Egoistic,  and  we  expect  him  to  keep  up  the  logical  sequence 
of  his  argument. 

I  This  may  be  quite  true,  but,  if  the  above  argument  has  any 
weight,  it  matters  much  that  when  "  his  own  pleasure  "  is  stated  to  be 
the  only  reasonable  end  for  the  individual,  "  his  own  "  should  not  be 
let  fall  out  without  our  being  told  why. 

J  i.e.,  the  greatest  amount  of  "  his  own  "  pleasure,  if  "  his  own  " 
pleasure  be  the  only  reasonable  end. 

S  i.e.,  "  his  own  "  greatest  pleasure  on  the  whole,  if,  we  repeat, 
"  his  own  "  pleasure  be  the  only  reasonable  end. 

I!  As  above,  an  appeal  to  Reason  to  declare  "  one's  own  pleasure  " 
the  only  reasonable  end,  a  declaration  which,  as  Prof.  Rashdall  him- 
self admits.  Reason  makes. 

^  Egoism  in  sense  of  "  one's  own  pleasure." 

♦*  "  Than  their  own  pleasure  " — i.e.,  to  each  "  his  own  "  pleasure. 

tt  How  ? 


344  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  egoistic  Hedonist's  position  carries  him  away  from 
egoistic  Hedonism  and  forces  him  into  the  adoption  of  a 
Universahstic  Hedonism."  * 

Now,  both  these  writers  are  here  attempting  to  build 
a  bridge  between  egoistic  and  universahstic  Hedonism. 
The  points  of  transition  from  the  Individual  happiness 
to  the  happiness  of  all  aie  clearly  shown  in  the  words 
of  Professor  Sidgwick,  italicised  by  us  ("  but  from  the 
point  of  view  of  the  Universe  "),  and  also  in  the  italicised 
passages  in  Professor  Rashdall's  statement.  The  aim 
of  the  transition  in  both  cases  is  to  get  rid  of  the  element 
"  his  own  "  in  that  principle  of  the  Egoist — "  to  each 
his  own  happiness  is  an  end,"  and,  as  a  means  to  this 
elimination  of  "  his  own,"  each  writer  appeals  to  the 
fact  that  "  his  own  pleasure  "  being  a  good  and  right 
end  to  the  individual,  an  end  that  he  ought  to  pursue, 
it  is  as  a  consequence  an  end  which  would  be  approved 
by  "  the  whole  world  "  or  the  "  Universal  Reason  "  or 
an  "  impartial  Reason,"  and  in  that  way,  since  an 
impartial  Reason  cannot  be  more  interested  in  me  than 
in  others,  pleasure  becomes  an  end  with  a  purely  ob- 
jective value — i.e.,  it  gains  a  value  apart  from  its  rela- 
tion to  the  individual  altogether  ;  and,  therefore,  having 
a  value  distinct  from  the  individual,  it  ought  to  be 
pursued  irrespectively  of  its  being  owned  by  any  person 
in  particular.  On  this  theory,  as  long  as  an  end  is 
approved  of  by  the  individual  alone  (for  example,  sweets 
or  fruits  or  other  such  ends),  as  long  as  the  goodness  of 
these  things  consists  in  the  fact  that  it  is  only  I  who 
wish  them,  so  long  the  Universal  or  Impartial  Reason 
has  nothing  to  say  to  these  ends,  and  so  long  they  have 
merely  a  subjective  value  (a  value  for  mc)  not  an  ob- 

•  Not  as  long  as  the  Hedonist  emphasises  that  annoying  particle 
"  his  own."  Tlic  reader  must  not  consider  that  in  following  the 
argument  almost  word  by  word  we  have  taken  a  narrow  view  of  it, 
or  have  sacrificed  the  spirit  of  the  argument  to  the  letter  We  have 
called  attention  to  the  details  of  the  argument  because  it  was  necessary 
to  do  so  in  order  to  guard  against  a  subtle  fallacy  which  could  only 
creep  in  under  cover  ot  words 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  345 

jective  value.  But  when  the  Impartial  Reason  approves 
of  an  end  (and  the  Impartial  Reason  will  approve  of 
an  end  whenever  the  value  of  that  end  consists  in  some- 
thing other  than  the  mere  fact  of  its  being  desired  by 
me — for  instance,  when  it  consists  in  the  fact  that  a 
certain  end  is  necessary  to  me,  or  that  nature  has  given 
me  an  impulse  to  it)  then,  since,  as  we  have  said,  an 
impartial  Reason  has  no  special  interest  in  any  indi- 
vidual, that  end  comes  to  be  of  value  on  its  own  ac- 
count, as  disassociated  from  "  me "  and  then  the 
element  "  his  own  "  can  be  allowed  to  drop  out.  For 
utilitarians  of  this  school,  therefore,  "  pleasure "  and 
not  "  one's  own  pleasure  "  becomes  the  end,  and  our 
highest  end  must,  accordingly,  be  the  greatest  quantity 
of  pleasure,  or  the  pleasure  of  all  men. 

We  think  this  as  fair  a  statement  of  the  argument  as 
can  be  given.  But  with  a  plain  statement  of  it  the 
sophism  it  contains  stands  out  as  plainly  as  in  Mill's 
argument.  In  the  present  argument  the  transition  from 
the  happiness  of  the  individual  to  the  happiness  of  all 
is  effected  either  {a)  through  the  assertion  that  the 
universal  or  Impartial  Reason  approves  of  the  end,  or 
(6)  through  the  proposition  that  the  end  has  a  value 
in  and  for  itself,  {a)  The  consequence  in  the  first  of 
these  assertions  may  be  illustrated  by  an  analogy — the 
analogy  of  a  sick  man  and  his  medicine.  The  doctor 
orders  medicine  for  the  sick  man  ("  his  own  "  medicine 
— i.e.,  a  medicine  specially  compounded  for  this  patient). 
This  medicine  is  prescribed  not  because  the  patient  has 
taken  a  liking  to  it — our  point  is  that  it  is  prescribed 
because  it  is  necessary  for  him,  and  that,  therefore,  it  is 
an  end  which  an  Impartial  or  Universal  Reason  would 
quite  approve  of.  Yet,  this  medicine  does  not  thereby 
acquire  a  value  which  is  purely  objective,  a  value  in 
and  for  itself  without  reference  to  the  individual.  The 
element  "  his  own  "  does  not  cease  to  have  its  proper 
value  in  consequence  of  this  Universal  approval,  nor 
does  the  law  henceforth  become  for  the  patient — seek. 


346  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

not  "  your  own  "  medicine,  but  all  men's  medicines  and 
your  own  as  just  one  amongst  the  number.  The  ex- 
pression "  his  own  "  can  never  become  detached  from 
that  prescription.  It  is  as  his  own  that  the  medicine 
is  prescribed  for  him,  and  it  is  as  "  his  own  "  that  the 
Impartial  Reason  approves  of  it,  and  only  as  "  his  own  " 
is  it  desirable  and  to  be  given  to  him.  This  analogy 
may  not  be  perfect — omnis  comparatio  claudicat — but 
it  will  help  to  bring  out  our  meaning.  If  the  law  of 
Egoistic  Hedonism  be — "  seek  your  own  pleasure  "  ; 
or — "  your  own  pleasure  is  a  good,"  and  if  Reason 
approves  of  what  is  an  end  to  me  by  a  law  of  nature — 
viz.,  "  my  own  pleasure  " — then  nothing  can  remove 
these  qualifications  indicated  in  the  expression  "  my 
own,"  whether  the  approving  Reason  be  partial  or 
impartial,  particular  or  universal.  The  Utilitarian 
might,  indeed,  find  other  arguments  to  show  that  the 
impartial  Reason  approves  of  the  general  happiness. 
But  he  cannot  establish  it  from  Egoism.  Beginning 
with  Egoism,  then,  there  is  simply  no  way  open  to  "  the 
general  happiness  as  end  of  the  individual,"  for,  from 
the  very  start,  the  qualification  "  his  own  "  attaches  to 
the  pleasure,  and  makes  impossible  the  transition  to 
Universalism.  (6)  Again,  if  we  take  as  the  point  of 
transition  the  words  "  of  value  in  and  for  itself,"  we 
have  once  more  the  same  evident  fallacy.  If  "  my  own 
pleasure  "  is  a  natural  end  of  action,  if  it  is  the  end 
which  we  ought  to  pursue  (as  Rashdall  himself  confesses), 
then  it  is  "  my  own  pleasure,"  and  not  "  pleasure  in  the 
abstract,"  that  gets  a  "  value  in  and  for  itself,"  and  no 
amount  of  shuffling  of  the  cards  can  get  rid  of  this  con- 
dition which  Egoistic  Hedonism  affixes  from  the  very 
start,  and  which  reappears  at  every  turn — the  condition 
of  "  personal  reference  "  expressed  in  the  words  "  one's 
own  "  pleasure.  If  we  do  not  begin  with  that  we  are 
not  beginning  with  Egoistic  Hedonism,  and  then  Pro- 
fessor Rashdall 's  words  are  meaningless.  If  we  do 
begin  with  that,  tjie  condition  "  my  own  "  remains  to 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  547 

the  end,  and  then  Universalistic  Hedonism  is  in  very 
terms  excluded.* 

Having  thus  shown  the  weakness  of  the  Utilitarian 
inference  from  Egoism  to  Universalism,  it  remains  to 
point  out  that  our  criticism  of  this  argument  does  not 
affect  Aristotle's  reasoning,  which  builds  not  Utili- 
tarianism, indeed,  but,  at  least,  benevolence  on  the 
fact  that  every  man  desires  his  own  good.  For  Aris- 
totle's argument  differs  toto  coelo  from  that  of  Sidgwick 
and  Professor  Rashdall,  and  the  difference  lies  not  in 
the  result  of  the  arguments  merely,  the  one  leading  to 
a  duty  of  benevolence,  the  other  to  Utilitarianism,  but 
in  the  logical  value  of  the  respective  arguments.  For, 
whereas  Aristotle  and  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  recognise 
that  any  end  that  I  may  wish  is  "my"  good  both  before 
and  after  the  transition  to  benevolence  (the  "  my " 
never  disappearing,  but  simply  expanding  so  as  to  em- 
brace all  men  through  their  union  with  me),  the  other 
two  writers  seek  to  get  away  from  this  reference  to  the 
individual's  pleasure  altogether,  or  to  represent  it  as 
only  one  amongst  a  million  pleasures,  other  people's 
pleasures  being  distinct  from  mine,  and  equal  to  mine. 
That,  we  have  shown  to  be  impossible.  From  Egoism 
to  benevolence  there  is,  we  believe,  but  one  way  open 
— that  indicated  in  St.  Thomas'  argument,  which  bases 
benevolence  on  the  likeness  men  bear  to  one  another  in 
their  nature,  and  their  being  one  in  that  nature. 

Before  concluding  this  section  it  may  be  well  to  point 
out  that  the  same  fallacy  that  we  have  just  exposed  in 

•  Prof  Rashdall  p¥ts  the  argument  from  Egoistic  Hedonism  in 
many  other  ways  without,  to  our  mind,  increasing  its  force.  He  writes, 
for  instance  (page  46) — "  The  very  principle  upon  which  (men's)  own 
preference  of  pleasure  to  all  other  objects  of  desire  rests  seems  to  put 
them  under  the  necessity  of  approving  a  similar  end  for  other  people. 
How,  then,  can  they  condemn  in  themselves  an  impulse  which  tends 
towards  the  realisation  of  that  end  for  others  ?  "  We  answer,  we 
don't  condemn  such  an  impulse,  but  we  deny  that  the  natural  desire 
which  each  man  has  for  his  own  pleasure  leads  of  necessity  to  his 
making  other  people's  pleasure  an  end  to  be  striven  for  by  himself. 
It  does  lead  to  our  recognising  that  other  people's  pleasure  is  an  end 
to  them  and  to  be  striven  for  by  them,  as  mine  is  an  end  to  me,  and  to 
be  striven  for  by  me. 


348  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Sidgwick's  argument  is  found  also  in  other  forms  of 
the  Utilitarian  argument — for  instance,  in  the  argument 
that  as  pleasure  is  our  natural  end,  our  highest  end  must 
be  the  sum  of  all  pleasures — i.e.,  the  maximum  pleasure 
of  all.  Our  reply  is — If  "  his  own  "  pleasure  be  the 
natural  and  constant  end  of  the  individual  (and  there  is 
no  other  constant  pleasure-end)  his  highest  end  will  be 
the  maximum  of  "  his  own  "  pleasure,  not  that  of  other 
men — just  as,  if  my  aim  be  my  own  bodily  exercise,  my 
highest  aim  will  be  the  best  bodily  exercise  that  I  can 
get,  not  the  best  or  greatest  exercise  of  other  people. 

We  have  drawn  this  argument  out  at  length  because 
of  the  importance  it  has  assumed  in  recent  utilitarian 
literature. 

(3)  Argument  drawn  from  the  moral  good  as  categorical 
and  objective. 

Many  modern  writers  (particularly  the  German 
ethicians)  seek  to  prove  that  the  good  of  humanity 
is  the  only  moral  end,  and  is,  therefore,  the  final  end 
of  the  individual,  by  reasoning  from  [a)  the  categorical 
and  absolute  nature  of  the  moral  law,  the  only  absolute 
value  in  nature  being,  according  to  these  writers,  the 
good  of  humanity  as  a  whole,  the  good  of  the  individual 
being  conditional  only — that  is,  referrable  to  the  good  of 
the  whole ;  or,  on  the  other  hand,  by  reasoning  from 
{h)  the  "  objective  "  value  of  the  moral  good — the  mere 
individual  good  is,  in  this  theory,  of  value  only  for  the 
individual  man,  and  therefore  (as  we  shall  presently 
explain)  it  is  not  objective  because  not  universal. 

Reply — {a)  This  theory  is  met  by  principles  estab- 
lished by  us  in  our  second  chapter — the  principles, 
namely,  that  the  Infinite  Good  is  the  natural  final  end 
of  the  individual  man,  and  that  this  end  is  of  value 
on  its  own  account  (absolutely),  and  not  merely  as  a 
means  to  something  else  (conditionally).  The  end  of 
the  individual   man   is,   therefore,   a   categorical  good. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  349 

Consequently,  it  is  not  true  that  the  only  absolute  and 
categorical  good  is  the  good  of  humanity  as  a  whole. 

Again,  this  theory  is  built  on  the  supposition  that  the 
individual  is  a  mere  part  of  society.  Now,  we  admit 
that  if  the  individual  man  were  nothing  more  than  a 
portion  of  society,  and  if  he  had  no  end  apart  from 
society,  then  society  would  be  the  only  thing  of  absolute 
value  to  him.  We  might,  then,  like  these  Ethicians 
whom  we  are  now  considering,  compare  the  individual 
to  the  human  arm,  the  value  of  which  is  conditional — 
that  is,  its  value  depends  upon  its  being  part  of  the 
whole  body.  But  the  individual  man  is  not  a  mere  part 
of  society,  and  independently  of  society  he  has  his  own 
ends,  and  particularly  his  own  final  end.*  Society  is 
not  his  final  end.  And,  therefore,  the  final  good  of  the 
individual,  though  an  individual  good,  can  be  yet  a 
good  of  absolute  value. 

[b)  Our  principles  regarding  the  ends  of  our  natural 
faculties  dispose  of  the  second  argument  above — that 
the  objectivity  of  the  moral  good  lies  in  its  being  the 
good  of  all  men.  For  we  have  shown  that  the  natural 
ends  of  all  natural  faculties  are  real  and  objective. 
We  showed  especially  that  the  end  of  our  wills — the 
perfect  or  infinite  Good — is  real ;  and  on  this  infinite 
Good  as  our  final  end,  and  on  the  other  natural  objects 
of  our  faculties,  is  based  the  reality  or  objectivity  of 
the  moral  law.  It  is  not  true,  then,  that  the  only 
objective  good  is  the  good  of  all  men. 

Moreover,  there  is  nothing  (either  moral  good  or 
anything  else)  whose  "  reality  "  or  "  objectivity  "  con- 
sists in  being  "  valued  "  by  all  men.  The  theory  that 
places  the  reality  or  objectivity  of  moral  good,  in  its 
being  valued  by  all  men,  is  based  on  the  Kantian 
doctrine  that   "  Objectivity  "   and   "  Universality  "    (or 

*  As  St.  Thomas  writes  :  "If  the  whole  of  which  anything  is  a 
part,  is  not  (its  own)  final  end,  but  is  referred  to  some  still  further  end, 
then  the  ultimate  end  of  the  part  will  be  that  other  thing  (to  which 
the  whole  system  is  referred),  and  not  the  whole  of  which  it  is  a  part  " 
("  S.  Theol.,"  I.,  II.,  Q.  II.,  Art.  8). 


350  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  fact  that  a  thing  is  an  object  for  all  men)  are  one. 
This  doctrine  we  cannot  accept.  A  thing  might  be 
objectively  real  even  though  I  alone  perceived  it,  and  a 
thing  might  be  of  objective  value  even  though  I  alone 
desired  it.  Universality,  then,  and  objectivity  are  not 
one  either  in  the  theoretical  or  in  the  practical  sphere. 
An  object  might,  we  say,  exist,  though  I  alone  perceived 
it.  An  end  may  be  objective  even  though  I  alone  desire 
it ;  and,  therefore,  the  individual  good  may  be  objective 
and  a  moral  good.  The  good  of  the  individual,  there- 
fore, may  be  as  categorically  necessary  and  as  objective 
as  the  good  of  the  race,  and  hence  the  moral  law  is  not 
grounded  necessarily  upon  the  idea  of  the  racial  good. 

(4)  Argument  drawn  from  the  common  conception  of 
morals. 

This  argument  is  two-fold  in  form. 

(a)  Bain  writes  :  "By  far  the  greater  part  of  the 
morality  "  (he  means  moral  laws  and  institutions  and 
opinions)  "  of  every  age  and  country  has  reference  to 
the  welfare  of  society.  Even  in  the  most  superstitious, 
sentimental,  and  capricious  despotisms  a  very  large 
share  of  the  enactments,  political  and  moral,  consist  in 
.  .  .  securing  justice  between  man  and  man.  ...  Of 
the  ten  commandments  four  pertain  to  Religious 
worship,  six  are  Utilitarian — that  is,  have  no  end 
^except  to  ward  off  evils  and  to  further  the  good  of 
mankind."  ♦  The  drift  of  this  argument  is  that  since 
most  of  men's  thought  about  morals  is  taken  up  with 
'  the  good  of  society,  the  good  of  society  must  be  the 
essential  element  in  morals. 

(6)  Gizycki  f  adopts  the  same  argument,  but  he 
modifies  it  by  adding  to  it  the  idea  of  evolution  in 
moral  ideas.     The  following  is  a  short  statement  of  his 

•  "  Moral  Science,"  page  442. 

t  "  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  Ethics,"  page  5.  We  have  already 
•aid  tliat  the  "  end,"  according  to  Gizycki,  consists  in  holiness  of  will  or 
peace  of  conscience,  but  this  end,  he  declares,  is  promoted  by  action 
tor  the  good  of  others 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  351 

theory  on  this  point  :  Moral  ideas  have  developed,  and 
development  brings  with  it  greater  truth.  But  develop- 
ment in  human  action  has  been  wholly  in  the  direction 
of  a  greater  and  greater  sympathy  with  the  woild  at 
large.  Hence  the  truth  lies  in  the  direction  of  tJni- 
versalism.  In  the  beginning  an  act  was  considered 
morally  valuable  which  promoted  the  happiness  of  the 
family  or  the  tribe.  To-day  we  tend  to  include  all 
men  in  our  sympathies,  and  regard  that  alone  as  good 
which  promotes  the  sum  of  human  happiness  in  general. 
Reply — We  shall  deal  with  the  second  (Gizycki's) 
form  of  the  argument  only,  as  it  is  the  more  modern 
form,  and  includes  Bain's.  First,  we  deny  that  men 
now  tend  to  identify  the  moral  good  with  that  which 
brings  happiness  to  the  race.  The  only  people  who  do 
so  are  the  utilitarian  ethicians,  and  they  do  so  only  in 
their  books.  In  common  life,  every  man,  even  the 
ethician,  will  assert  his  rights  as  against  society,  and 
he  will  assert  certain  of  these  rights,  and  regard  himself 
as  justified  in  so  doing,  no  matter  what  be  the  amount 
of  general  pleasure  that  he  feels  he  spoils  by  clinging  to 
his  rights.  Secondly,  even  granted  that  we  are  becoming 
(as  perhaps  we  are)  more  benevolent,  this  does  not  mean 
that  the  content  of  our  moral  ideas  is  changing,  that  we 
tend  to  identify  all  goodness  with  benevolence,  but  only 
that,  on  the  one  hand,  we  now  exercise  greater  careful- 
ness in  discharging  this  very  important  duty  of  benevo- 
lence than  hitherto,  and,  on  the  other,  that  whereas  we 
were  formerly  brought  into  contact  with  but  a  few  men 
whom  it  was  possible  for  us  to  benefit,  our  modern 
system  has  brought  all  the  nations  under  each  other's 
influence,  and  made  it  possible  for  and  incumbent  upon 
us  to  widen  our  sympathies  more.  We  are,  in  other 
words,  now  more  one  family  than  we  were.  But  that 
does  not  mean  that  the  good  of  others  has  become  our 
sole  end.  A  father  knows  that  he  has  a  duty  of  benevo- 
lence towards  his  own  family,  and  as  the  family  grows 
the  demands  upon  his  benevolence  may  become  corre- 


352  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

spondirgly  greater.  These  increasing  demands  thus 
made  :>n  his  Hberahty,  and  his  correspondence  with 
these  mcreasing  demands,  do  not  imply  that  he  has 
altered  his  ideas  of  benevolence  or  that  he  has  tended 
moie  to  identify  all  morality  with  benevolence.  It  is  so 
with  the  race  at  large.  Our  sympathies  may  widen — 
/  still  our  idea  of  the  final  end  remains  the  same.  Thirdly, 
w^hen  we  admit  that  men's  sympathies  may  have 
widened  with  time,  we  mean,  not  so  much  that  the 
individual  mind  has  grown  more  benevolent  (though 
it  has,  perhaps,  grown  to  some  extent),  as  that  the 
public  mind  or  interest  in  the  general  affairs  of  State 
has  grown — has  developed — and  that  it  expresses  itself 
more  than  was  formerly  the  case.  The  political  educa- 
tion of  the  masses  as  a  result  of  modern  political  con- 
ditions is  a  subject  of  which  we  have  heard  much,  and 
it  needs  no  discussion  here  beyond  indicating  that  it 
has  had  some  influence  in  helping  the  ordinary  citizen 
to  understand  the  nature  of  the  public  interests — such 
as  interests  of  the  State.  But  we  must  not  forget  that 
however  appreciation  of  public  interests  is  developed, 
private  interest  will  not,  therefore,  urge  its  claims  on 
the  individual  with  diminished  force,  although  the  pur- 
suit of  it  must  naturally  be  always  less  prominent  and 
receive  less  notice  than  matters  of  State  in  public 
records.  It  is  not  easy,  therefore,  to  see  how  any 
growth  of  interest  in  the  public  good  strengthens  the 
case  for  that  development  in  moral  ideas  spoken  of  by 
utilitarians.  Growth  of  interest  in  the  public  good  is 
explained  not  by  development  of  our  ideas  as  to  the 
natural  end  of  man  but  by  the  "  political  education  of 
the  masses,"  who  now  share  in  framing  the  laws  of 
the  State  and  in  the  procuring  of  the  public  good. 
Fourthly,  Gizycki  has  argued  as  if  men  were  becoming 
more  social — i.e.,  as  if  from  the  beginning  the  social 
interest  were  developing  and  the  individual  interest 
gradually  disappearing.  But  we  would  ask  the  reader 
to  compare  with  Gizycki's  account  the  following  quota- 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  353 

tion  from  M.  Levy-Bruhl's  work  on  "  Moral  Science  " 
(M.  Levy-Bruhl  is  no  opponent  of  Utilitarianism) — a 
work  in  which  this  distinguished  writer  teaches  exactly 
the  opposite  of  Gizycki's  view,  and  regards  the  history 
of  the  human  race  as  a  history  of  the  gradual  emanci- 
pation of  the  individual  from  the  social  body  of  which, 
according  to  Levy-Bruhl's  theory,  he  was  at  first  a 
mere  part  without  any  end  of  his  own  :  "  Nous  pouvons 
admettre  avec  une  vraisemblance  proche  de  la  certitude 
que  dans  les  groupes  humaines  {i.e.,  pre- Australian 
groups)  qui  differaient  autant  des  Soci6t6s  Australiennes 
que  nous  differons  d'elles,  I'individu  n'existait  guere 
mentalement  pour  lui-meme,  n'avait  guere  conscience, 
si  Ton  ose  dire,  de  sa  conscience  individuelle,  et  que  sa 
vie  psychique  ^tait  de  nature  presque  purement  col- 
lective." Here,  then,  it  is  the  individual  that  is  repre- 
sented as  coming  forward — society  as  falling  back.  In 
such  a  variety  of  conflicting  views  among  the  Utili- 
tarians it  is  hard  to  regard  the  argument  drawn  from 
history  as  a  decisive  proof  either  of  Utilitarianism  or 
of  any  other  ethical  theory. 

In  summing  up  our  criticism  of  the  arguments  in 
favour  of  Utilitarianism  drawn  from  the  "  common 
conception  of  Morals "  we  say,  first,  that  men  have 
indicated  no  tendency  so  to  change  their  moral  ideas 
as  to  identify  the  moral  good  with  the  general  happi- 
ness. Secondly,  if  we  assume,  what  is  really  very 
doubtful,  that  there  has  been  a  considerable  growth 
in  charity  in  modern  times,  we  cannot  thence  infer 
that  men  are  developing  a  belief  in  the  "  general  happi- 
ness "  as  the  natural  ethical  end  of  the  individual.  It 
proves  at  most  that  men  do  now  more  frequently  and 
extensively  what  they  always  knew  to  be  one  of  their 
principal  duties. 

(5)  The  Argument  from  Pragmatism. 
Pragmatisi^n   is   the   theory   that   that   is   true   which 
works.     Applied    to   the   question    of   Moral    theory    it 
Vol.  I — 23 


354  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

means  that  a  theory  of  conduct  is  true  which  yields  the 
most  acceptable  and  workable  code  of  human  morals. 
Utilitarianism,  we  are  told  by  its  advocates,  is  found  to 
work.  It  does  not,  according  to  the  Utilitarians,  like 
Hedonism,  debase  mankind.  Its  moral  code  is  a  high 
one.  The  world  has  been  working  on  it  for  centuries 
("  by  far  the  greater  part  of  the  morality  of  every  age 
and  country  has  reference  to  the  welfare  of  Society," 
writes  Bain  *).  Utilitarianism,  it  is  asserted,  is  the 
expression  of  a  law  the  observance  of  which  holds 
society  together,  of  a  law  which  would,  if  adopted 
generally  by  mankind,  prevent  war  and  injustice  and 
cruelty  and  the  antagonisms  of  classes,  and  everything 
else  which  brings  misery  to  men.  Utilitarianism,  then, 
works  in  the  best  sense  of  the  word.  Consequently  it 
must  be  true. 

Reply — On  the  general  principle  of  Pragmatism,  or 
the  principle  that  what  works  is  true,  we  cannot  speak 
now,  for  in  this  book  we  are  concerned  with  Ethical 
theory  only.  We  shall,  therefore,  confine  our  attention 
to  the  Pragmatist  argument  as  applied  to  Morals. 

Both  the  major  and  the  minor  premiss  of  this  argu- 
ment need  to  be  examined — viz.,  that  "  a  theory  of  con- 
duct which  works  is  true,"  and  that  "  Utilitarianism  is 
a  workable  theory  of  conduct." 

The  major  proposition  could  not  be  accepted  without 
very  great  restrictions.  Before  workability  could  be 
regarded  as  a  test  of  the  truth  of  a  moral  theory,  the 
theory  should  be  workable  in  the  sense  and  under  the 
conditions  that  follow — (a)  it  should  possess  a  workable 
criterion — that  is,  a  criterion  which  is  certain  and  can  be 
applied  with  certainty  to  conduct ;  (6)  it  should  lead 
to  a  workable  moral  code,  a  code  which  it  is  possible 
to  accept ;  (c)  it  should  be  the  only  workable  moral 
theory,  for  a  moral  theory  is  supposed  to  assign  the 
ultimate  ground  of  morals,  and  there  can  be  only  one 

*  "  Moral  Science,"  page  442. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  355 

ultimate  ground  of  morals.  Hence,  there  can  be  only 
one  true  complete  moral  theory.  With  these  restric- 
tions we  shall  for  the  sake  of  argument  *  accept  the 
major  proposition  of  our  opponents  without  further 
question,  and  in  the  light  of  these  restrictions  we  go 
on  to  the  principal  portion  of  our  argument,  which  is 
the  examination  of  the  minor  proposition — that  Utili- 
tarianism works.  We  find  that  this  minor  premiss 
fails  to  fulfil  any  of  the  three  conditions  under  which 
alone  we  accepted  the  major  proposition,  {a)  Utili- 
tarianism has  no  workable  criterion  ;  (6)  it  does  not 
yield  a  workable  code  ;  [c]  it  excludes  other  theories 
which  are  workable. 

{a)  We  have  already  seen  that  the  Utilitarian  criterion 
is  quite  unworkable  in  practice.  Its  application  to 
conduct  is  most  difficult  and  uncertain,  if  not  absolutely 
impossible. 

(6)  We  also  saw  that  the  code  of  morals  to  which  this 
Utilitarian  criterion  leads  when  rigidly  and  consistently 
applied  is  not  such  as  mankind  could  possibly  accept  or 
has  ever  accepted.  For  the  essential  feature  of  Utili- 
tarianism is  that  it  subordinates  the  individual  wholly 
to  society,  a  condition  of  things  which  the  individual 
will  never  allow  and  could  not  allow.  Every  man 
claims  the  right  to  pursue  his  own  end,  due  regard, 
of  course,  being  had  to  the  claims  of  society.  There  is 
no  man  who  will  not  consider  that  he  has  rights  inde- 
pendently of  society,  and  that  he  can  exercise  these 
rights  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  society  may  be  deprived 
of  much  pleasure  thereby — of  more  pleasure  than  he 
gains  in  using  his  right.  Thus,  society  has  no  right  to 
make  a  man  profess  a  faith  in  which  he  does  not  believe, 
even  though  the  profession  of  such  faith  promoted  the 
material    interests    of    society.     We    claim,    then,    that 

*  We  should  explain  to  the  reader  that  even  with  these  conditions 
realised  we  would  not  feel  compelled  to  accept  this  theory  that  "  a 
moral  theory  that  is  workable  is  true."  The  above  conditions  are  the 
least  that  we  should  require  before  even  considering  the  question 
whether  "  a  moral  theory  that  works  is  necessarily  true." 


356  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  individual  will  always  regard  himself  as  independent, 
to  a  large  extent,  of  society,  and  that  if  society  should 
at  any  time  treat  the  individual  merely  as  a  thing 
without  rights  on  his  own  account,  the  individual  will 
resolutely  resent  any  such  action  on  the  part  of  society. 
But  society  will  not  and  cannot  do  this.  It  cannot 
afford  to  ignore  the  individual  right  and  individual 
independence.  Therefore,  the  principle  of  Utilitarian- 
ism is  unworkable.* 

(c)  Utilitarianism,  even  if  it  were  a  workable  theory, 
is  not  the  only  workable  theory.  Everything  that  is 
true  in  this  theory  is  contained  in  the  Aristotelian  and 
Scholastic  moral  system,  and  they  are  not  Utilitarian. 
All  the  virtues — temperance,  justice,  fortitude,  benevo- 
lence,  prudence,  truth — were  formulated  before  the 
introduction  of  the  Utilitarian  theory,  and  without  the 
';x:aid  of  the  Utilitarian  principle. 

/        Utilitarianism,    therefore,    as    a    system    is    neither 

1     necessary  nor  workable,  nor  the  only  workable  theory  ; 

and,  therefore,  we  cannot,  on  the  ground  of  its  supposed 

workability,   postulate  its  truth.     There  are,   however, 

in    the   Utilitarian    theory    some    principles   which    are 

1      both  workable  and  true,  as  we  pointed  out  in  the  be- 

'      ginning  of  this  chapter ;    but   these  principles  do  not 

'      justify    us   in    accepting    the   Utilitarian    system    as   a 

whole. 

(6)  Argument  from  the  theory  of  the  "  Solidarity  "  of 
Society. 

It  is  not  easy  to  give  a  definition  that  will  adequately 
describe  all  the  forms  of  this  theory.j  Most  of  them, 
however,  are,  we  think,  contained  in  the  following 
rather  lengthy  definition,  which  may  be  described  as, 
a  mean  reading  of  the  "  Solidarity "  theories.  The 
theory    of    "  Solidarity "    implies    that    society    is    an 

•  See  also  pp.  328-g. 

t  A  good  account  of  the  various  forms  of  this  theory  is  given  in  M. 
Fouill6e  8  "  Elements  Sociologiqucs  de  la  Morale,"  rmj^  also  some 
account  of  tho  name  "  Solidaritd,"  a^  applied  to  Morals. ,  ' 


ON  Utilitarianism  357 

organic  unity  made  up  of  individual  men  and  related 
to  those  individuals  much  as  the  body  is  related  to  its 
members — that  just  as  the  body  and  the  members  act 
on  one  another  reciprocally,  so  society  and  individuals 
have  a  reciprocal  influence  on  one  another  ;  that  as 
the  members  derive  their  existence,  their  functions,  and 
their  meaning  from  the  whole  body  of  which  they  are 
the  parts,  so  the  individual  man  is  indebted  to  society 
for  his  existence,  his  faculties,*  the  development  of  his 
faculties,  his  character  and  (in  a  very  special  way)  for 
his  moral  nature  ;  that  apart  from  society  the  individual 
is  unintelligible  (some  of  the  expressions  of  this  are 
curious — "  Unus  homo,  nullus  homo  "  f — "  we  are  what 
we  are  through  the  rest  "  J — "  a  man  not  dependent 
on  a  race  is  as  meaningless  a  phrase  as  an  apple  that 
does  not  grow  upon  a  tree "  §)  ;  that  (this  is  their 
principal  ethical  conclusion)  as  the  body  is  the  end  of 
the  members,  so  society  is  the  end  of  the  individual, 
and  that  on  this  account,  as  also  on  account  of  the 
indebtedness  of  the  individual  to  society  for  all  that  he 
is  and  has,  he  should  direct  his  actions  to  the  good  of 
society. 

Criticism — In  this  theory  we  fmd  two  points  for. 
criticism — (I.)  The  proposition  that  society  is  the  end 
of  the  individual  as  the  body  is  the  end  of  the  members. 
(II.)  That  the  individual  is  formed  by  his  social  environ- 
ment, and  consequently  is  indebted  to  society  for  all 
that  he  is  and  has,  and  that  he  should  in  all  his  actions 
seek  the  good  of  society. 

*  This  theory  that  the  individual  is  formed  by  the  organism  of 
society  is  part  of  the  theory  of  Social  Evolution — that  is,  the  theory 
that  the  feelings  of  the  individual  (the  mind  or  ego  being  only,  accord- 
ing to  these  writers,  a  bundle  of  feelings)  are  inherited  from  the  race 
at  large,  and  that  they  have  been  evolved  by  the  pressure  of  all  parts 
of  society  upon  each  part,  so  that  the  individual  may  be  regarded  as 
a  microcosm  of  all  society,  past  and  present.  "  We  are  not,"  writes 
Carneri  ("  Grundlegung,"  page  331),  "  as  individuals,  any  longer  a 
part — we  are  the  whole  of  society,  and  carry  it  in  our  breast." 

t  Trendelenburg 

X  Guyau. 

§  Leslie  Stephen 


358  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(I.)  On  the  first  proposition  it  is  not  necessary  to  say 
much  at  this  point.  We  have  aheady  seen  that  society 
is  not  the  end  of  the  individual  man,  that  the  individual 
man  and  society  have  the  same  end,  which  is  beyond 
them  both — namely,  the  Infinite  Good — and  that,  conse- 
quently, the  individual  man  is  not  a  mere  part  of  society. 

The  analogy  of  the  members  and  the  body,  and  its 
applicability  to  society,  will  be  further  considered  when 
we  come  to  treat  of  society.  But  it  will  have  already 
suggested  itself  to  the  reader  that  the  analogy  is  of  its 
nature  misleading,  since  the  cells  and  members  of  a  body 
are  not  free  beings,  whereas  the  individual  man  is  a  free 
being.  Also,  the  cells  and  members  have  no  end  of  their 
own  beyond  the  body,  because  their  capacities  do  not 
exceed  that  of  promoting  the  good  of  the  body,  whereas 
the  individual  has  capacities  that  exceed  the  promotion 
of  social  happiness,  and,  therefore,  his  final  end  cannot 
be  the  promotion  of  this  happiness.  The  relation  of  the 
cells  and  members  to  the  body  we  describe  as  organic, 
that  of  individuals  to  society  as  "  hyperorganic."  * 

(II.)  The  question  of  the  indebtedness  of  the  indi- 
vidual to  society,  of  which  so  much  is  made  in  the 
theory  of  "  Solidarity,"  must  be  considered  here  more 
closely.  This  indebtedness  is  described  at  great  length 
and  in  an  interesting  way  by  Leslie  Stephen.  The 
following  passage,  though  not  quite  so  thoroughgoing 
in  matter  and  aim  as  other  expositions  with  which  we 
are  acquainted,  will,  nevertheless,  give  the  reader  a 
good  idea  of  the  style  of  argument  generally  adopted 
in  the  exposition  of  this  theory  : — 

"  Almost  every  action  of  my  life,"  he  writes,  "  is  dependent 
more  or  less  directly  upon  the  co-operation  of  others,  and  the 
more  so  as  I  become  more  civilised.  I  cannot  think  without 
assuming  the  knowledge  attained  by  others.     I  see  that  my 


•  Wc  must  repeat  here  that  we  liavc  no  wish  to  limit  the  extent  of 
the  fluty  of  Ixrnc'volence.  VVu  think,  in  fact,  that  there  is  no  duty 
which  utilitarians  would  i«  prailire  demand  from  us  that  we  could 
not  as  scholastics  accept  and  recognise. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  350 

fire  is  low,  I  feel  that  I  am  too  cold.  I  infer  that  I  should 
put  on  coals.  Even  in  so  simple  a  case  I  use  inherited  results 
of  the  experience  of  others,  and  especially  of  the  great  dis- 
covery of  fire  and  its  properties.  But  I  am  also  dependent 
on  the  continued  co-operation  of  others.  ...  If  I  can  devote 
myself  to  write  an  Ethical  treatise,  it  is  because  thousands  of 
people  all  over  the  world  are  working  to  provide  me  with 
food  and  clothes  and  a  variety  of  intellectual  and  material 
products.  ...  It  is  again  obvious  that  as  every  man  is 
born  and  brought  up  a  member  of  this  vast  organisation  (of 
Society)  his  character  is  throughout  moulded  and  determined 
by  its  pecuharities.  It  is  the  medium  in  which  he  lives  as 
much  as  the  air  which  he  breathes  or  the  water  which  he 
drinks.  And  this  implies  not  merely  .  .  .  that  his  intel- 
lectual furniture,  his  whole  system  of  beliefs,  prejudices, 
and  so  forth,  are  in  a  great  degree  acquired  by  direct  trans- 
ference, and  that  consciously  or  unconsciously  he  imbibes 
the  current  beliefs  and  logical  methods  of  his  fellows,  but 
also  that  he  is  educated  from  infancy  by  the  necessity  of 
conforming  his  activities  to  those  of  the  surrounding  mass. 
If  his  feelings  or  beliefs  bring  him  into  conflict  with  his 
neighbours  he  is  constantly  battered  and  hammered  into 
comparative  uniformity,"  &c. 

Other  advocates  of  this  theory  claim,  as  we  have  said, 
a  much  greater  degree  of  indebtedness  and  dependence 
than  Leslie  Stephen. 

Now,  in  order  to  answer  this  theory,  it  is  important 
that  we  should  set  forth  briefly  and  in  outline  our  own 
view  on  the  indebtedness  of  individuals  to  society, 
saying  how  much  comes  to  us  generally  from  our  social 
environment,  and  how  much  we  have,  not  from  society, 
but  from  nature  directly,  or  from  the  Author  of  nature  ; 
for  we  claim  that,  besides  the  benefits  which  we  derive 
from  society,  there  are  others  that  we  derive  not  from 
society  but  from  nature. 

(i)  In  the  first  place,  there  are  those  things  which 
are  common  to  all  men — that  is  to  say,  our  human 
nature  itself  and  its  essential  properties.  These  come  to 
us  directly  from  God.  Our  parents  are  only  the  in- 
strumental causes  of  our  existence  and  of  our  human 
nature — they    are   the   transmitters   of   human   nature. 


36o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

not  its  causes.  And  this  common  human  nature  in- 
cludes a  body  and  a  soul,  the  parts  of  the  body  and  the 
functions  of  the  soul.  Society  has  not  given  us  heart, 
stomach,  or  eyes ;  neither  has  it  given  us  our  powers 
of  growing,  feeling,  and  thinking.  These  things  are 
given  directly  by  the  Author  of  nature,  and  merely 
transmitted  to  us  by  our  parents.  Society,  and  more 
particularly  our  non-living  environment,  may  make 
some  accidental  changes  in  some  of  these  things.  A 
limb  may  develop  or  become  atrophied  in  response  to 
environment,  but  our  body  and  soul  and  our  faculties 
are  all  from  nature.  So  far  society  can  make  no  claim 
upon  us. 

(2)  In  the  second  place,  there  are  those  things  in  which 
men  differ  from  one  another,  and  here  society  has  some 
claim  upon  us.  Of  those  things  in  which  men  differ 
some  are  innate  and  some  are  acquired.  The  innate 
element  includes,  broadly  speaking,  three  things — ■ 
[a)  bodily  properties  like  health,  (6)  mental  ability, 
(c)  our  innate  will-tendency  or  character.  Now,  (a) 
individual  bodily  properties  like  health  depend  very 
much  on  social  environment,  but  not  so  much  on  society 
in  general  as  on  the  special  influence  of  parents  and 
immediate  ancestors.  (6)  Innate  mental  abilities  de- 
pend but  little  (much  less  than  bodily  health)  on  society. 
From  decrepit  ancestors  it  is  scacrely  possible  to  inherit 
a  strong  and  active  body — but  out  of  a  stupid  race  we 
may  get  a  sharp  intelligence.  Therefore,  mental  ability 
is  more  independent  of  environment  than  bodily  health. 
Still,  here  again,  there  must  be  some  degree  of  depen- 
dence— not,  indeed,  on  any  efforts,  conscious  or  uncon- 
scious, of  society  at  large,  but  on  influences  from  par- 
ticular individuals  in  our  line  of  ancestors,  (c)  The 
character  with  which  we  are  born  exhibits  much  depen- 
dence not  only  on  particular  individuals  in  society,  but 
on  society  at  large.  As  the  father  is,  so,  to  a  large 
extent,  is  the  son.  As  the  race  is,  so,  to  a  large  extent, 
is  the  individual.     Every  man  is  affected  by  the  family 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  361 

disposition  and  by  the  racial  disposition  (the  disposition, 
for  instance,  of  the  Frenchman,  the  Enghshman,  and  the 
German),  and  in  both  of  these  respects  we  are  dependent 
on  our  social  environment.  So  far,  we  have  spoken  of 
innate  individual  possessions  only. 

Another  class  of  human  attributes  in  which  men  differ 
(a  class  which  is  of  the  greatest  importance  to  the  theory 
of  Solidarity)  is  that  portion  of  our  being  which  consists 
of  acquired  habits.  Acquirements  are  in  the  main  ac- 
quirements of  {a)  growth  (body),  {h)  of  knowledge 
(intellect),  (c)  of  character  (will). 

{a)  The  first  of  these  classes  of  acquirements  it  is  not 
necessary  to  dwell  on,  since  it  cannot  be  of  much  conse- 
quence to  the  theory  we  are  criticising.  For  their  food 
and  other  things  necessary  to  growth  children  are 
indebted  to  their  parents  only,  not  to  society  at  large. 
No  doubt,  many  articles  of  food  would  be  impossible 
without  society,  but  food  in  general  could  be  obtained 
even  though  men  never  entered  society.  If  animals 
can  obtain  their  food  without  society  there  is  no  reason 
why  men  could  not  do  the  same.  For  bodily  growth, 
therefore,  we  are  not  essentially  dependent  on  society. 

But  it  is  in  relation  to  the  other  two  classes  of  acquire- 
ments :  {h)  our  information  and  (c)  our  character — that 
we  are  most  indebted  to  our  social  environment,  and  it 
is  on  these  two  factors  that  the  advocates  of  the 
"  Solidarity  "  theory  lay  most  stress.  Now,  as  we  shall 
show  in  a  moment,  our  debt  to  society  in  respect  of  in- 
formation and  character  is  a  very  large  one.  Yet  it  is 
not  so  large  as  to  lend  countenance  to  the  theory  that 
we  owe  all  to  society.  For,  not  to  sepak  of  such  know- 
ledge as  could  be  gained  by  us  even  though  society 
did  not  exist,  and  confining  our  attention  to  that  portion 
which  depends  to  some  extent  on  social  aids,  we  still 
claim  that  much  of  our  knowledge  and  our  character 
depends  upon  the  individual  himself  and  not  on  social 
environment.  For  (i)  there  is  no  such  thing  as  a  pure 
or  unmixed  mental  acquirement.     As  the  scholastics  say 


362  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

— Id  quod  recipitur  recipitur  secundum  modum  recipientis. 
The  information  we  are  capable  of  acquiring  depends 
not  merely  upon  our  teachers,  but  also  upon  our  natural 
abilities  and  industry,*  and  for  these  we  are  not  in  the 
main  indebted  to  society.  So  also  the  character,  views, 
opinions,  tendencies,  which  our  surroundings  beget  in 
us,  depend  largely  on  what  we  are  by  nature,  upon  our 
general  complexion  of  soul  and  body,  and  not  on  en- 
vironment. Mere  environment  could  never  make  a 
great  man.  We  are,  it  is  said,  what  our  age  makes 
us  ;  but,  then,  the  age  must  find  us  in  order  to  make 
us.  To  some  extent  Shakespeare  was  the  product  of 
his  age,  but  it  needed  a  Shakespeare  to  take  hold  of  and 
utilise,  and  by  his  own  personal  industry  to  perfect, 
what  the  age  had  to  give  him — else  we  should  not  have 
had  the  author  of  "  Hamlet  "  and  "  Macbeth."  What 
we  are  and  do,  then,  depends  largely  on  ourselves,  our 
ability,  and  our  industry  ;  and  even  what  we  do  receive 
from  outside  is  so  largely  modified  within  us  that  our 
information  and  character  cannot  be  said  to  be  due 
wholly  or  even  chiefly  to  external  sources.  (2)  For  our 
acquirements,  intellectual  and  moral,  we  are  largely 
indebted  to  the  mere  material  world  and  not  exclusively 
to  social  environment.  Much  of  our  information  comes 
to  us  direct  from  the  physical  world.  Also,  our  faculty 
of  knowledge  is  to  some  extent  sharper  or  duller  accord- 
ing to  our  surroundings.  The  brighter  fancy,  for 
instance,  depends  upon  the  more  sunny  climate.  Moral 
character,  too,  is  largely  formed  in  response  to  the 
visible  world  around  us.  The  vicinity  of  lofty  moun- 
tains influences  us  to  generous  feeling  and  to  detach- 
ment from  trifles — a  gloomy  and  forbidding  environ- 
ment inclines  us  to  the  opposite  of  this.  Our  debt, 
therefore,  cannot  be  wholly  to  human  society.     (3)  Both 

•If  wc  iniKht  borrow  an  .analogy  from  Economics:  "Without 
industry  capital  would  be  of  very  little  value  to  commerce,  and  without 
induKtry  the  acquirements  of  the  race,  which  arc  our  mental  capital, 
would  do  little  for  the  individual."  Wc  are  not,  therefore,  what  our 
age  makes  us. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  363 

in  the  matter  of  information  and  in  the  matter  of 
character  we  depend  not  as  a  rule  upon  society  at  large 
but  upon  definite  individuals,  proximately  upon  our 
parents  and  teachers,  and  remotely  upon  other  indi- 
viduals. For  actual  teaching  we  are  indebted  to  our 
parents :  for  the  principles  on  which  their  instruction 
proceeds  we  are  indebted  to  the  individuals  who  dis- 
covered or  proved  these  principles.  It  is  absurd,  there- 
fore, to  speak  of  the  individual  mind  being  formed  in 
response  to  "  social  pressure "  from  all  parts  of  the 
social  organism,  when  we  can  actually  point  out  the 
individuals  to  whom  we  are  indebted  for  what  we  have. 
Our  debt,  then,  is  not  wholly  to  society  but  is  due 
mostly  to  individuals.  (4)  That  which  we  have  re- 
ceived we  have  received  mainly  from  the  generations 
that  are  dead,  and  only  to  some  extent  from  our  con- 
temporaries to  whom  we  owe  comparatively  little ; 
and  it  would  be  absurd  to  base  on  the  individual's  debt 
to  the  past  a  theory  that  he  is  bound  to  regard  the 
happiness  of  the  present  and  future  generations  as  his  sole 
natural  end.  Now  to  this  argument  that  it  would  be 
absurd  to  base  on  our  debt  to  the  past  a  theory  that  our 
sole  natural  end  is  the  good  of  present  and  future  genera- 
tions, some  might  be  inclined  to  return  the  follow- 
ing answer  :  Present  and  future  generations  are  the 
heirs  of  the  past,  and  it  is  therefore  right  that  they 
should  benefit  by  the  individual's  indebtedness  to  the 
past.  This  answer,  however,  we  cannot  regard  as 
satisfactory.  When  a  father  leaves  property  to  his 
children,  no  one  argues  that,  because  each  child  is 
indebted  to  his  father,  he  is  therefore  indebted  to  his 
brothers  and  sisters  also,  who  are,  like  himself,  his 
father's  heirs.  That  which  each  receives  is  his  own. 
So  also,  whatever  we  have  received  of  being,  of  cha- 
racter, of  information  from  our  ancestry  should  be 
regarded  as  our  own  property  ;  and,  therefore,  if  the 
analogy  based  on  inheritance  is  to  hold  good,  our  debt 
to  the  past   involves  no  duty  of  seeking   the  welfare 


364  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

or  the  happiness  of  our  fellowmen.  Our  duty  to  ouf 
fellowinen  is,  as  we  have  seen,  based  upon  very  different 
grounds  from  that  of  mere  "  inheritance."  For  our 
information,  therefore,  and  for  what  is  acquired  in  our 
character,  we  are  to  a  very  large  extent  independent 
of  social  environment. 

And  yet  we  must  admit  that  to  society  we  are  in- 
debted for  something  that  we  are  and  something  that 
we  possess.  And  our  debt  is  not  a  small  one.  It  is 
through  society  that  we  become  "  the  heir  of  all  the 
ages."  It  is  society  that  receives  and  transmits  to  the 
human  race  the  knowledge  attained  by  each  succeeding 
generation.  Without  society  there  could  be  no  human 
development,  no  language,  for  instance,  and,  therefore, 
no  efficient  thought.  In  a  word,  without  society  the 
possibilities  of  human  nature  would  to  a  large  extent 
remain  possibilities,  and  man's  development  and  higher 
perfection  would  remain  unaccomplished.  This  means 
that  our  debt  to  society  is  very  large,  but  it  means  no 
more  ;  and  we  cannot  legitimately  infer  from  it  that 
our  debt  to  society  makes  the  happiness  of  society 
man's  sole  natural  end.* 

*  The  theory  that  we  owe  all,  even  the  existence  of  our  minds,  to 
society,  has  been  maintained  and  defended  by  the  most  varied  argu- 
ments. Besides  the  reasons  given  in  the  text,  some  adduce  an  argu- 
ment from  the  supposed  discovery  of  Prof.  Baldwin  that  the  child's 
mind  or  Ego  is  formed  by  imitation  of  the  actions  of  those  around  it. 
Others,  like  Prof.  Royce,  find  a  proof  for  this  theory  that  the  Ego  or 
mind  is  formed  by  society,  in  the  fact  that  our  thoughts  and  disposi- 
tions are  a  reflex  of  the  attitude  of  other  men  towards  us.  If  the 
world  opposes  us.  Prof.  Royce  says,  the  Ego  of  which  we  are  self- 
conscious  (our  own  Ego)  is  felt  as  a  fighting  Ego.  If  the  world  admires 
us,  our  Ego  is  felt  as  a  heroic  Ego,  and  so  on.  (These  arguments  are 
given  in  Baldwin's  "  Mental  Development  in  the  Child  and  the  Race," 
and  in  Royce's  works,  "  Studies  in  Good  and  Evil  "  and  "  The  World 
and  the  Individual.")  Others  argue  from  the  supposed  absence  of 
Reason  in  the  wild  solitaries  who  have  never  been  under  the  influence 
of  society. 

Fully  to  consider  these  and  the  other  arguments  used  in  support 
of  the  theory  of  "  Solidarity  "  would  require  more  space  than  it  is 
{X)s.siblc  to  give  them  here.  Prof.  Baldwin's  and  Royce's  theories 
the  reader  will  have  no  difficulty  in  answering  for  himself.  Before 
the  child  could  imitate  the  world  around  him,  he  must  be  pt)ssesscd  of 
a  mind — lie  must  Ik;  an  Ego  ;  and  before  a  man  could  reflect  his  sur- 
roundings in  the  way  described  by  Prof.  Royce,  he  must  have  a  mind 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  365 

We  conclude  our  account  of  the  Solidarist's  view  of 
the  action  of  society  on  the  individual  and  the  depen- 
dence of  the  individual  on  society  with  a  quotation  from 
M.  Fouillee  :  "  Les  solidaristes,"  he  writes,*  "  en  defini- 
tive, n'ont  point  pousse  jusqu'au  bout  I'analyse  de 
I'idee  de  dependance.  L'homme  ne  depend  pas  seule- 
ment  des  autres  hommes,  de  la  nature,  de  la  famille,  de 
la  nature  exterieure  ;  il  depend  aussi  de  sa  propre  con- 
stitution individuelle ;  il  depend  de  lui-meme  et  de 
toutes  les  relations  internes  qui  le  constituent  tel  ou 
tel.  L'interdependance  suppose  I'intradependance.  .  .  . 
On  pent  done  dire  que  les  solidaristes  voient  seulement 
la  moitie  de  la  verite  ;  ils  constatent  la  loi  de  solidarite 
relative  qui  nous  emporte  hors  de  nous,  ils  oublient  la 
loi  de  non-solidarite  relative  qui  nous  concentre  en 
nous."  t 

(7)  Argument  from  the  necessity  of  Utilitarianism  to 
account  for  our  moral  intuitions. 

A  seventh  argument  in  favour  of  Utilitarianism,  an 
argument  which  we  do  not  think  it  necessary  to  con- 
sider at  any  length  here,  is  derived  from  the  fact  that 

by  which  to  reflect  them.  Hence  the  individual  Ego  could  not  be 
formed  by  imitation  or  by  reflection  of  society.  Besides,  both  of 
these  theories  are  built  on  the  false  supposition  that  the  soul  is  only 
a  bundle  of  qualities  or  dispositions  or  thoughts,  and  not  a  substance — 
a  theory  the  refutation  of  which  belongs  to  Psychology.  As  regards 
the  argument  derived  from  the  supposed  lack  of  Reason  in  the  wild 
solitaries,  our  reply  is  that  so  far  as  we  are  acquainted  with  the  history 
of  these  wild  solitaries  (our  knowledge  of  their  history  is  mainly  con- 
fined to  that  given  in  a  remarkable  work  entitled  "  Homo  Sapiens 
Ferus,"  by  a  certain  Prof.  Rauber),  we  are  persuaded  that  the  actions 
and  habits  of  these  solitaries  give  no  ground  for  thinking  that  they 
were  not  possessed  of  Reason.  On  the  contrary,  the  ease  with  which 
they  were  in  practically  all  cases  taught  to  speak  and  read  (the  few 
exceptions  being  mainly  cases  in  which  these  wild  men  were  taken 
when  old,  and  in  whom,  therefore,  the  organs  of  speech  had  practically 
become  atrophied  for  want  of  use)  shows  conclusively  that  they  had 
Reason,  and  could  think  just  like  other  men. 

•  "  Les  Elements  Sociologiques  de  la  Morale,"  page  395. 

t  We  think  it  fair  to  mention,  before  quitting  the  consideration  of 
this  theory,  that  much  of  the  civilisation  and  refinement  of  the  world 
to-day  depends  upon  religion  and  the  church,  and  not  on  civil  society. 
We  mention  this,  however,  not  as  an  argument  but  as  a  fact. 


366  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Utilitarianism  {a)  explains  many  of  our  supposed  moral 
intuitions,  which  (b)  on  any  other  theory  of  morals 
would  not  be  explainable.  Thus,  it  is  claimed  that 
our  intuition  of  the  goodness  of  justice,  truth,  and 
other  such  virtues  is  explainable  only  on  the  supposi- 
tion that  the  "  good "  is  that  which  promotes  the 
welfare  and  happiness  of  the  race. 

Reply — ^This  argument  we  regard  as  false  in  its  pre- 
misses and  in  its  supposition.  In  its  premisses  it  is 
false  because  it  does  not  explain  our  moral  intuitions. 
It  does  not,  as  we  have  already  shown,*  explain  the 
law  of  justice,  and  it  opposes  our  view  of  the  unlawful- 
ness of  homicide  and  of  lying.  Again,  it  is  false  in  its 
supposition  that  the  truth  of  a  moral  theory  is  to  be 
judged  by  its  conformity  with  a  particular  moral  code. 
It  is  not  allowable  to  accept  a  moral  theory  for  the 
simple  reason  that  it  explains  or  harmonises  with  our 
moral  beliefs,  since  if  Ethics  is  a  science,  our  beliefs 
must  be  themselves  grounded  upon  and  reasoned  out 
on  the  basis  of  our  theory  of  the  end  of  man  and  the 
nature  of  the  good.  Hence,  our  beliefs  depend  upon 
our  theory  of  Ethics,  not  vice  versa.  Nor  does  it  make 
a  difference  that  these  moral  beliefs  referred  to  are 
intuitions.  The  truth  of  our  intuitions  as  well  as  of 
all  other  beliefs  must  be  tested  by  that  which  we  regard 
as  the  true  theory  of  moral  goodness  and  of  man's 
final  end — that  is,  our  beliefs  must  all  be  tested  by  our 
Ethical  theory.  Hence  our  Moral  intuitions  afford  no 
sufficient  reason  for  our  accepting  the  theory  of  Utili- 
tarianism. 

These,  we  believe,  are  the  main  arguments  adduced 
by  the  Utilitarian  Ethicians,  and  from  the  consideration 
of  them  we  are  persuaded  that  they  do  not,  to  use 
Mill's  words,  "  determine  the  mind  to  accept "  the 
Utilitarian  theory. 

•  See  pp.  328-9  }y 


(^ 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  367 

APPENDIX  I 

The  Theory  of  Moral  Values 

The  theory  of  "  moral  values  "  (Werttheorie)  has  come  to 
occupy  such  a  prominent  place  in  recent  Ethical  literature 
that  we  cannot  pass  from  the  present  chapter  without  saying 
a  few  words  about  it.  It  will  not  be  necessary  to  consider 
this  theory  at  any  length  because  we  have  already  said  a 
great  deal  in  the  present  chapter  about  its  principles,  though, 
indeed,  we  have  not  spoken  of  them  under  the  name  of  the 
"  moral  value  "  theory.  Only  the  general  principles  of  the 
theory  will  be  here  described — the  details  and  the  various 
forms  of  the  theory  are  to  be  found  principally  in  Ehrenfels' 
"  System  der  Werttheorie,"  Meinong's  "  Psychological  Ethical 
Enquiries  on  Theories  of  Values,"  and  other  such  works. 

A  thing  in  this  theory  is  said  to  have  "  value  "  when  it 
answers  to — that  is,  is  the  object  of — desire  or  appetite.  It 
is  said  to  have  a  moral  value  when  the  race  desires  it,  or 
when  it  leads  to  something  which  the  race  desires.  The 
value  of  a  thing  then  depends  upon  our  desires.  "  We  do 
not,"  says  Ehrenfels,  "  desire  things  because  they  have  a 
value — they  have  a  value  because  we  desire  tbem."  Desire 
is  the  criterion  of  value.  But  though  this  principle  is  common 
to  all  "  value  philosophies,"  it  is  not  always  understood  in 
the  same  way  by  the  valuists.  For  some  accept  the  principle 
in  the  sense  that  an  object  has  value  when  it  is  indispensable 
for  our  needs,  whilst  others  claim  that  only  such  objects 
have  value  as  are  worthy  of  being  desired. 

Valuists  also  differ  as  to  {a)  the  cause,  {h)  the  conditions  of 
intensity  and  (c)  the  object  of  desire.  The  most  prominent 
view  on  the  first  two  of  these  is  that  of  Ehrenfels  who  teaches 
{a)  that  desire  arises  when  the  state  of  happiness  which  is 
conditioned  by  our  desires  lies  higher  in  the  scale  of  feeling 
than  the  state  of  happiness  which  is  possible  without  the 
gratification  of  those  desires,  and  (6)  that  the  intensity  of 
desire  depends  upon  the  difference  in  these  two  levels  of 
feeling,  (c)  On  the  object  of  desire,  some  of  this  school 
teach  that  what  is  desired  is  not  an  object  or  a  feeling  but 
existence — the  existence  of  some  object  or  action  or  feeling. 
A  curious  development  of  this  theory  is  that  of  Meinong, 
who  teaches  that  all  feelings  of  worth  or  value  are  feelings 
that  arise  from  affirmative  or  negative  existential  judgments. 
Thus  according  to  this  author  the  "  value  "  of  any  end  x 
is  proportioned  to  the  sum  of  the  pleasures  and  pains  got 


368  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

from  inagining  the  two  existential  judgments  together  "  x 
exists"  and  "  x  does  not  exist,"  exist,  viz.,  as  an  attained  or 
realised  end. 

In  all  these  theories  the  value  of  an  object  necessarily 
depends  upon  a  calculus  of  pleasures  and  pains  ;  and  in 
order  to  facilitate  this  calculus  they  distinguish  values  into 
positive  and  negative — positive  when  an  increase  in  the 
object  makes  for  the  fulfilment  of  desire  ;  negative  when  a 
decrease  in  it  makes  for  the  fulfilment  of  desire. 

Ethical  values  have  in  this  theory  two  prominent  character- 
s  tics — they  promote  the  general  good  and  they  are  absolute, 
i.e.  they  are  independent  of  change  in  desire.  Now  on  the 
nature  of  this  latter  characteristic  valuists  are  very  much 
divided.  Some  maintain  that  this  absolute  value  is  real, 
some  that  it  is  only  apparent.  Brentano,  for  instance,  com- 
pares Ethical  values  to  true  (we  take  it  that  he  means  "  neces- 
sary ")  judgments,  and  claims  that  Ethical  values  are  always 
true  values,  just  as  true  necessary  judgments  are  always  true. 
Ehrenfels,  on  the  other  hand,  defends  the  imaginative  cha- 
racter of  absolute  values.  He  contends  that  no  values  are 
absolute,  but  that,  in  the  popular  judgment.  Ethical  values 
assume  an  absolute  form,  or  appear  absolute,  and  for  two 
reasons — first,  because  of  the  constant  tendency  of  the  human 
mind  to  turn  the  relative  into  the  absolute  ;  secondly,  because 
de  facto  there  does  actually  obtain  in  action  an  absolutely 
necessary  relation — a  relation  of  necessary  truth — which  we 
illegitimately  regard  as  attaching  to  the  moral  character  of 
acts.  This  absolutely  necessary  relation  obtains  between 
means  and  ends,  for  in  every  moral  value  a  certain  means  is 
absolutely  and  truly  necessary  to  some  end.  This  absolute 
necessity,  he  says,  the  popular  mind  easily  but  illogically 
transfers  from  the  means  to  the  end  itself,  and  in  this  way 
we  come  to  regard  our  moral  judgments,  which  concern  ends 
only,  as  absolute  or  categorical  judgments — that  is,  as  judg- 
ments that  certain  things  are  categorically  necessary.  The 
popular  judgment  being  then  once  formed,  it  is  easy  to  see, 
Ehrenfels  contends,  how  even  the  philosopher,  misled  by  the 
popular  fallacy,  may  proceed  to  build  upon  these  spurious 
judgments  a  system  of  absolute  or  categorical  morals. 
Ethics,  concludes  Ehrenfels,  is  therefore  a  .spurious  science, 
as  long  as  it  claims  absoluteness  for  moral  law.  A  genuine 
Ethics,  he  tells  us,  is  not  an  absolute  but  a  relative  science, 
and  it  differs  from  the  other  parts  of  the  "  theory  of  values  " 
only  in  the  width  of  the  desires  to  which  it  assigns  values, 
for  the  characteristic  of  the  Ethical  desire  is  that  it  is  a 
desire  for  the  good  of  all  men. 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  369 

The  question  "  in  what  the  general  good  consists  "  again 
gives  rise  to  differences  of  opinion  among  the  valuists  ;  some 
say  it  consists  in  the  greatest  pleasure  of  the  greatest  number, 
others  in  the  satisfaction  of  the  general  common  desire, 
others  in  the  health  bodily  and  mental  of  society,  others  in 
the  combination  of  all  these  under  the  common  title — "  the 
satisfaction  of  our  common  needs." 

There  being,  according  to  Ehrenfels,  no  true  absolute 
value  in  objects,  the  value  of  objects  may  change.  The 
principal  factors  in  these  value-changes  will  be  those  that 
follow  on  (a)  changes  of  atrributes  in  man  himself,  (b)  pro- 
gress in  human  knowledge,  (c)  change  of  social  relations,  e.g., 
change  from  an  aristocratic  to  a  democratic  form  of  society, 
{d)  changes  in  inter-social  or  inter-national  relations. 

One  important  part  of  the  theory  of  Ehrenfels'  is  the  claim 
that  man  is  given  by  nature  only  a  certain  amount  of  energy, 
that  this  energy  must  feed  the  moral  as  well  as  the  non-moral 
dispositions,  that  these  non-moral  dispositions  are  powers 
which  need  to  be  developed  as  well  as  the  morad,  and  that 
consequently  we  should  not  develop  the  moral  dispositions  too 
highly,  lest  we  fail  in  other  respects.  A  perfectly  good  humanity 
would  necessarily,  say  some  valuists,  mean  a  weak  and  a  poor 
humanity. 

This  rough  outline  of  the  theory  of  Values  will  make  it 
clear  to  the  reader  that  ethically  there  is  very  little  that  is 
new  in  the  theory  of  Values  over  and  above  what  belongs  to 
Utilitarianism. 

APPENDIX  II 

Hedonism  and  Utilitarianism — their  Reconciliation 

To  hedonists  and  utilitarians  the  question — whether  and 
in  what  manner  Hedonism  and  Utilitarianism  may  be  recon- 
ciled with  one  another — is  not  only  an  interesting,  it  is  a 
vital  problem.  For  it  seems  to  us  from  our  reading  of  the 
works  of  utilitarian  philosophers,  to  take  their  case  first, 
that  when  utilitarians  sit  down  in  a  cool  moment  to  consider 
the  question  which  of  the  two  ends — his  own  good  or  the 
good  of  society — is  of  more  importance  to  the  individual, 
which  of  the  two  (if  there  be  such  a  thing  as  a  final  end)  is  the 
final  end  of  the  individual,  it  must  seem  plain  that  the  end  of 
paramount  importance  to  the  individual  man  is  his  own  good. 
Of  course  a  man  may  be  so  interested  in  a  certain  part  of 
society  that  the  happiness  of  that  part  is  of  more  importance 
to  him  than  his  own.     For  instance,  a  father  may  think  more 

,       Vol.  I — 24 


370  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of  the  happiness  of  his  children  than  of  his  own  happiness. 
But  we  are  not  speaking  of  such  special  cases  here.  We  are 
speaking  here  of  a  general  comparison  of  the  good  of  the  in- 
dividual man  with  that  of  society  at  large  as  the  end,  and  we 
say  that  a  utilitarian  ought  to  recognise  that  the  end  of  most 
importance  to  the  individual  is  his  own  good,  or  (which  is  the 
same  thing  for  utilitarians)  his  own  happiness.  To  the  utili- 
tarian therefore  it  becomes  a  vital  problem  whether  or  not  it 
can  be  shown  that  the  individual  in  seeking  the  good  of  other 
men  is  also  promoting  his  own. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  Hedonist  would  seem  to  feel  that 
unless  his  system  can  be  extricated  from  the  narrow  rut  of 
selfishness — unless  it  can  be  shown  that  the  theory  that  our 
own  happiness  is  the  final  end  leads  on  in  some  way  to  the 
obviously  more  refined  theory  that  in  all  our  acts  we  should 
seek  the  good  of  the  race — his  system  of  Hedonism  will/t)e 
considered,  and  is,  an  ignoble  philosophy,  narrow,  demeaning, 
and  brutalising.  Hence  the  endeavours  of  both  hedonists 
and  utilitarians  to  bridge  over  the  gap  separating  the  two 
systems. 

Of  the  various  methods  proposed  for  reconciling  the  two 
systems  of  Hedonism  and  Utilitarianism,  we  can  mention 
only  a  few — 

(i)  Some,  like  Mill,  attempt  to  reconcile  them  on  grounds 
of  pure  Logic  by  deducing  the  second  theory  from  the  first. 
Mill's  attempted  deduction  of  the  duty  of  seeking  all  men's 
happiness  from  our  duty  to  seek  '  each  his  own  '  we  have 
already  noticed  in  this  chapter.  A  similar  attempted  deduc- 
tion is  the  argument  that  since  each  man's  happiness  i§  to 
count  for  one  and  nobody's  for  more  than  one,  therefore  no 
man's  happiness  is  of  more  account  to  himself  than  the  happi- 
ness of  any  other  man.  In  other  words,  that  because  A.'s 
happiness  is  no  more  to  A.  than  B.'s  is  to  B.,  therefore  A.'s 
happiness  is  no  more  to  A.  than  B.'s  is  to  A.  This  argument 
it  is  not  necessary  to  refute. 

(2)  Others  attempt  to  reconcile  them  on  grounds  of  Ethics. 
Thus  {a)  we  have  Rashdall's  and  Sidgwick's  argument  that 
since  each  man  maintains  not  only  that  his  own  happiness  is 
an  end,  but  is  the  right  end  or  the  end  which  he  ought  to  pur- 
sue, his  duty  is  to  seek  the  general  happiness.  This  argument 
we  have  examined.  (6)  Some  contend  that  by  seeking  the 
happiness  of  others  we  secure  for  ourselves  the  greatest  of  all 
pleasures — namely,  the  peace  and  happiness  of  a  good  con- 
science, and  consequently  that  the  law  to  seek  the  general 
happiness  is  the  same  in  effect  as  the  law  to  seek  our 
own.    This  is  the  idea  of  Gizycki's  principle — "  Strive  after 


ON  UTILITARIANISM  371 

peace  of  Conscience,  by  seeking  in  all  things  the  good  ol 
Humanity."  * 

(3)  Others  attempt  a  psychological  reconciliation  either 
{a)  through  the  passion  of  sympathy  which,  they  say,  at  once 
induces  us  to  do  good  to  others  and  at  the  same  time  brings 
us  pleasure  when  we  do  such  good  ;  or  (6)  through  the  sup- 
posed law  of  feeling  that  in  order  to  get  the  maximum  of 
personal  pleasure  we  must  indulge  alternately  the  selfish  and 
benevolent  feelings,  else  the  power  of  feeling  would  become 
fatigued.  "  Egoism,"  writes  Spencer,  "  must  be  checked  by 
intervals  of  altruism  if  our  faculties  are  to  recover  the  energy 
lost  by  pleasure." 

(4)  In  some  systems  they  are  reconciled  through  a  meta- 
physical theory  of  {a)  the  relation  of  the  individual  to  the 
race  or  {h)  of  the  reciprocal  effect  on  one  another  of  the 
individual  and  the  social  happiness.  Thus  (a)  many  recent 
Ethicians  argue  that  in  seeking  the  happiness  of  the  race  we 
are  seeking  the  happiness  of  the  true  "  ego  "  since  the  race  is 
the  true  substance  of  the  individual,  {h)  Others  claim  that  to 
seek  for  the  general  good  to  the  neglect  of  the  individual  good 
would  be  to  render  one's  self  unfit  for  benevolence  ;  whilst  un- 
less we  seek  the  general  good  we  are  sure  to  bring  upon  our- 
selves ultimate  misery.  The  first  theory  is  to  be  found  in 
Seth.  The  latter  principle  is  defended  by  Spencer,  the  second 
portion  of  it  being  adopted  by  Shaftesbury  also.  "  It  is  cer- 
tain," writes  Shaftesbury,  "  that  if  a  man  were  destitute  of 
all  wish  for  the  social  good — that  is,  opposed  it  on  all  occa- 
sions— he  would  be  thoroughly  miserable.  So  if  a  man  does 
anything  against  the  social  good  he  is  doing  a  part  of  that 
which  will  ultimately  cause  him  great  misery."' 

(5)  Butler,  Locke,  and  Paley  maintain  that  the  reconcilia- 
tion of  Hedonism  and  Utilitarianism  lies  in  Theology — that  a 
benign  Legislator,  God,  must  ultimately  secure  the  harmony 
of  the  two  interests,  the  individual  and  the  social. 

As  we  said,  this  question  is  of  a  good  deal  of  importance 
to  Hedonists  and  Utilitarians.  But  to  the  Scholastic  philo- 
sopher it  is  not  of  very  great  importance ;  and  hence, 
though  in  itself  it  gives  rise  to  much  interesting  speculation, 
we  shall  not  quote  our  own  view  here  beyond  saying,  first, 
that  we  do  not  think  that  Utilitarianism  is  a  necessary  growth 
out  of  Hedonism  ;  and,  secondly,  we  believe  that  in  the  face 
of  the  facts  of  ordinary  experience  it  would  be  impossible  to 
show  anything  approaching  a  perfect  identification  of  the 
private  and  the  public  good. 

♦  "  Moralphilosophit,"  page  121. 


CHAPTER  XII 

"EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS— A  DISCUSSION 
OF  THE  ETHICAL  THEORIES  OF  THE 
EVOLUTION    PHILOSOPHERS  " 

Evolution  means  growth — by  the  Evolutionist  Ethics 
is  meant  the  theory  that  morals  are  a  growth,  a  growth 
from  non-ethical  elements. 

There  are  three  principal  theories  of  Evolutionist 
Morals — the  Biological,  the  Psychological,  and  the 
Transcendental  theory. 

The  theory  of  biological  evolution  is  a  theory  of 
the  evolution  of  the  objective  laws  of  morals,  such  as 
the  laws  of  temperance  and  justice.  It  is  the  theory 
that  right  and  wrong  and  their  laws,  objectively  taken, 
are  only  stages  or  conditions  in  the  evolution  of  life, 
the  right  being  that  which  promotes  life,  and  the  wrong 
that  which  impairs  it. 

The  theory  of  psychological  evolution  concerns  not 
the  objective  laws  of  morals,  but  our  subjective  moral 
opinions  and  sentiments,  and  it  explains  these  opinions 
and  sentiments  as  evolved  from  certain  mere  non-moral 
feelings  like  those  of  pleasure  and  pain.  This  theory  of 
Psychological  Evolution  reduces  all  moral  principles  to 
mere  subjective  conditions  of  mind,  and  so  its  chief  aim 
is  to  explain  the  origin  of  our  moral  beliefs. 

The  theory  of  transcendental  evolution  explains 
the  objective  moral  law,  and  our  subjective  moral 
opinions  as  two  sides  of  one  fundamental  evolutionary 
process — the  evolution,  namely,  of  the  Absolute.  Of 
this  Absolute  we  shall  give  an  explanation  in  the  next 
chapter  before  cUscussing  its  relations  to  Ethics. 

It  will  be  seen  that  though  those  three  theories  are 
distinct    they    are    not    wholly    contradictory,    for    the 

372 


EVOLUTIOlS  AND  ETHICS  373 

subject-matter  of  each  is  distinct.  One  treats  only  of 
objective  moral  laws,  another  of  subjective  moral  con- 
victions, the  third  of  both  objective  and  subjective, 
but  under  an  aspect  quite  different  from  that  con- 
sidered in  the  other  two  systems.  There  is,  then, 
nothing  to  prevent  the  same  ethician  from  advocating 
all  three  theories  or  any  two  of  them.  Indeed,  most 
professed  adherents  of  the  Biological  school  belong  to 
the  school  of  Psychological  Evolution  as  well,  and  some 
of  those  who  profess  the  first  two  theories  are  followers 
of  the  Transcendentalist  theory  also. 

Now,  these  three  Evolutionary  systems  require 
separate  treatment,  and  we  will  take  them  in  the  order 
in  which  we  have  given  them  above. 


ETHICS    OF    BIOLOGICAL   EVOLUTION 

(a)    ACCOUNT   OF   spencer's  THEORY 

The  most  representative  exponent  of  the  theory  of 
Biological  Evolution  is  Herbert  Spencer.  To  the  dis- 
cussion of  his  work,  therefore,  we  shall  devote  ourselves 
in  the  present  section. 

The  task  which  Spencer  sets  himself  in  his  "  Data  of 
Ethics  "  *  is  that  of  explaining  morality  through  the 
ordinary  laws  of  evolution.  That  the  world  in  general 
is  subject  to  evolution  he  takes  for  granted,  and  he 
finds  himself  forced  to  bring  morals  under  this  general 
law  of  evolution  by  "  finding  that  they  "  (the  moral 
laws)  "  form  part  of  the  aggregate  of  phenomena  which 
evolution  has  wrought  out.  If  the  entire  visible  Uni- 
verse has  been  evolved,  if  the  solar  system  as  a  whole, 
the  earth  as  part  of  it,  the  life  in  general  which  the 
earth  bears,  as  well  as  that  of  the  individual  organism 
— if  the  mental  phenomena  displayed  by  all  creatures, 
up    to    the    highest    in    common    with    the    phenomena 

♦  Spencer's  Ethical  opinions  are  also  expressed  in  hjs  work  on 
"  Sociology." 


374  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

presented  by  aggregates  of  these  highest — if  one  and 
all  conform  to  the  laws  of  evolution,  then  the  necessary 
implication  is  that  those  phenomena  of  conduct  in  these 
highest  creatures  with  which  Morality  is  concerned  also 
conform."*     In    the    light,    therefore,    of    the    law    of 
evolution,  Spencer  goes  on  to  show  that  morally  good 
conduct  and  highly  evolved  conduct  are  one.     In  the 
establishment  of  this  proposition  there  are  two  steps. 
First,  he  shows  that  the  conduct  of  man  is  not  different 
in  kind  from  that  of  the  higher  animals,  and  that  the 
conduct  of  the  higher  animals  is  not  different  in  kind 
from  that   of  the  lower.     By  "  higher  "   in  conduct  is 
only  meant  the  inclusion  in  conduct  of  more  and  more 
numerous  ends.     And  this  inclusion  of  more  and  more 
numerous  ends  is  found,  he  assures  us,  always  to  accom- 
pany development  in  structure  and  function,  the  animal 
of  more  complex  structure  and  function  being  capable 
of  taking  in  more  ends — that  of  less  complex  structure 
and  function,  fewer  ends.     Secondly,  he  compares  highly 
evolved  conduct  as  just  explained  with  what  he  con- 
ceives to  be  the  general  content  of  our  moral  beliefs, 
and  he   finds  that   that   which   men   call   morally  good 
conduct  is  exactly  the  same  thing  as  what,  on  his  first 
enquiry,  he  found  to  be  highly  evolved  conduct.     His 
conclusion,  therefore,  is  that  the  laws  of  morality  are 
only  the  laws  of  highly  evolved  conduct,  and  that  these 
laws  are  not  proper  to  man,  but  are  the  laws  by  which 
nature    rules    the    conduct    of    animals    as    well,    the 
difference   of   higher   and   lower   being,    as   already   ex- 
plained, one  of  degree  merely,  not  of  kind.     Let  us  now 
fill  in  some  of  the  details  of  this  remarkable  system,  f 

(i)  spencer's  definition  of  Ethics. 
Ethics,   Spencer  tells  us,   is  the  science  of  conduct- 

•  "  Data  of  Ethics,"  page  63. 

I  We  are  conscious  of  a  certain  want  of  proportion  between  the 
space  here  given  to  the  consideration  of  Spencer's  tlioory  and  tlie  rest 
of  our  work.  The  nature  and  imp>ortancc  of  the  fhcory  under  review 
is  our  only  justification  for  this  defect,  if  it  be  a  defect. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  375 

By  conduct  he  means  purposeful  external  action.  As 
external,  conduct  differs  from  '  function — function  being 
purely  internal.  "  We  are  concerned  with  functions  in 
the  true  sense  when  we  think  of  them  as  processes 
carried  on  within  the  body."  But  "  we  enter  on  the 
study  of  conduct  when  we  begin  to  study  such  com- 
binations amongst  the  actions  of  sensory  and  motor 
organs  as  are  externally  manifested."  Not  all  external 
action,  however,  is  conduct,  but  only  purposeful  external 
action.  Purposeful  action  means  co-ordinated  action, 
action  that  is  adjusted  in  some  degree  to  an  end  outside 
the  individual.  The  subject-matter,  therefore,  of  Ethics 
is  "  the  aggregate  of  all  external  co-ordinations  (or  pur- 
poseful actions)  ;  and  this  aggregate  includes  not  only 
the  simplest  as  well  as  the  most  complex  performed  by 
human  beings,  but  also  thosa  performed  by  all  inferior 
beings  considered  as  more  or  less  evolved."  Thus,  on 
Spencer's  theory,  man's  action  is  not  specifically  distinct 
from  that  of  the  animals  below  him.  Man  is  only  the 
more  highly  evolved  animal.  And  Ethics,  though  it 
has  to  deal  more  emphatically  with  the  more  highly 
evolved  animals  (including  men)  and  their  acts,  has 
not  to  do  exclusively  with  human  acts — its  subject- 
matter  is  conduct  or  purposeful  activity,  whether  of 
man  or  of  animal. 


(2)  Aim  of  the  evolutionary  process. 

Spencer  now  proceeds  to  show  that  conduct,  just  like 
everything  else,  is  subject  to  the  laws  of  evolution. 
Throughout  the  world  there  obtains  a  law  of  evolution. 
One  grade  of  being  is  obviously  more  evolved  and,  in 
that  sense,  stands  higher  than  another,  that  again  than 
another — the  stages  extending  from  the  protozoa  at  the 
lowest  to  man  at  the  highest  point  of  the  evolutionary 
series.  This  law  of  evolution  extends,  first  of  all,  to 
structure — the  lower  stages  being  characterised  by  a 
comparatively  simple,   the  higher  by  a  more .  differen- 


376  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

tiated,  structure  ;  and,  secondly,  to  function,  the  lower 
beings  possessing  but  few,  the  higher  very  many  and 
intricate,  functions.  But  evolution  of  structure  and 
function  is,  he  tells  us,  always  accompanied  by  a  third 
kind  of  evolution — viz.,  greater  purposefulness  of  action, 
greater  adjustments  of  act  to  ends  or  to  environment  ;  in 
other  words,  more  developed  conduct. 

This  is  very  evident  in  the  case  of  the  lower  animals. 
Bees,  ants,  horses,  or  elephants  are  evidently  more 
evolved,  in  the  sense  of  showing  a  greater  capacity  for 
securing  far-away  ends,  than  the  snail  and  the  fish. 
But  the  very  same  difference  in  purposefulness  will  be 
found  to  characterise  the  higher  or  more  civilised  man 
in  comparison  with  the  lower  or  less  civilised.  Thus 
he  writes  : — 

"Between  the  shelter  of  boughs  and  grass  which  the 
lowest  savage  builds  and  the  mansion  of  the  civilised  man 
the  contrast  in  aspect  is  not  more  extreme  than  is  the  con- 
trast in  number  and  efficiency  of  adjustment  of  acts  to  ends 
betrayed  in  their  respective  constructions." 

This  difference  in  human  purposefulness  must,  as  in 
the  case  of  the  animals,  be  an  accompaniment  of 
difference  in  structure  and  function.  But  the  same 
three-fold  variation  of  structure,  function,  and  adapta- 
tion is  more  evident  in  the  case  of  the  lower  animals 
than  in  the  case  of  men.  The  more  evolved  the  animal 
in  structure  and  function  the  better  adjusted  are  its 
acts  in  relation  to  its  environment.  It  is,  in  fact,  as  a 
means  to  this  finer  adjustment  of  acts  to  ends  and  to 
environment  that  the  animal  is  possessed  of  finer  and 
more  complicated  structure  and  functions. 

Now,  what  is  the  final  aim  of  these  powers  of  liner 
adjustment,  or  (the  question  is  the  same)  what  is  the 
natural  end  and  aim  of  this,  whole  evolutionary  process  ? 
The  end  is  Life — ^greater  duration  and  greater  quantity 
of  Life. 

"  The  fish  roaming  about  at  hazard  in  search  of  something 
to  cat,  able  to  detect  it  by  smell  or  sight  only  within  short 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  377 

oistances,  and  now  and  again  rushing  away  in  alarm  on  the 
approach  of  a  bigger  fish,  makes  adjustments  of  acts  to  ends 
that  are  relatively  few  and  simple  in  their  kinds  ;  and  shows 
us,  as  a  consequence,  how  small  is  the  average  duration  of  life. 
So  few  survive  to  maturity  that,  to  make  up  for  the  destruc- 
tion of  unhatched  young  and  small  fry  and  half-grown  indi- 
viduals, a  million  ova  have  to  be  spawned  by  a  codfish  that 
two  may  reach  the  spawning  age.  Conversely,  by  a  highly 
evolved  mammal,  such  as  an  elephant,  those  general  actions 
performed  in  common  with  the  fish  are  far  better  adjusted  to 
their  ends.  By  sight,  as  well  probably  as  by  odour,  it  detects 
food  at  relatively  great  distances.  .  .  ,  But  the  chief  difference 
arises  from  the  addition  of  new  sets  of  adjustments.  We 
have  combined  actions  which  facilitate  nutrition,  the  breaking 
off  of  succulent  and  fruit-bearing  branches,  the  selecting  of 
edible  growths  throughout  a  comparatively  wide  reach  ;  and, 
in  case  of  danger,  safety  can  be  achieved  not  by  flight  only 
but,  if  necessary,  by  defence  or  attack,  bringing  into  combined 
use  tusks,  trunks,  and  ponderous  feet.  .  .  .  Evidently  the 
effect  of  this  more  highly  evolved  conduct  is  to  secure  the 
balance  of  the  organic  actions  throughout  far  longer  periods  " 
("  Data  of  Ethics,"  page  13). 

The  end,  then,  of  this  whole  evolutionary  process  is 
the  attainment  of  complete  life.* 

(3)  Furtherance  of  complete  life — its  meaning. 

Furtherance  of  life,  Spencer  continues,  does  not  mean 
its  prolongation  merely.  It  means  increase  of  life,  both 
in  point  of  duration  and  of  quantity.  "  Duration " 
needs  no  explanation.  "  Quantity  "  of  life  means  the 
"  sum  of  the  vital  activities  during  any  given  interval." 
Many  of  the  lower  animals  live  longer  than  man,  but 
they  have  not  the  same  quantity  of  life — that  is,  they  do 
not  exercise  the  same  amount  of  activity  in  a  given 
time.  The  highest  end  of  conduct,  then,  is  fulness  of 
life  in  duration  and  in  quantity,  or,  as  Spencer  puts  it, 
"  in  length  and  in  breadth."    * 

It   must    not   be   thought,    however,    that   by   life   as 

*  Spencer  tells  us  that  the  promotion  of  life  itself  would  not  be 
good  unless  life  generally  brought  us  a  preponderance  of  pleasure  oyer 
pain,  ^ 


378  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

natural  end  of  conduct  is  meant  the  life  of  the  indi- 
vidual merely.  The  evolutionary  process  tends  to  the 
furtherance  of  all  life,  and,  therefore,  of  the  social  life 
as  well  as  of  the  individual.  The  lower  animals  are  of 
comparatively  simple  structure  and  function,  and  are 
capable  of  comparatively  little  adjustment  of  acts  to 
the  preservation  of  the  life  of  the  species.  Sometimes 
the  3'oung  are  left  to  the  care  of  nature  altogether,  as 
in  the  case  of  the  Protozoa  which  preserve  the  species 
by  breaking  up  into  a  number  of  individuals.  Higher 
up  in  the  line  of  evolution  germ  and  sperm  cells  are 
just  ripened  and  sent  out  into  water,  and  left  to  their 
fate.  But  the  higher  animals  go  through  a  most  com- 
plicated process  of  adjustment  in  order  to  preserve 
their  young — man's  efforts  naturally  being  finest  and 
most  complicated  of  all.  With  evolution  of  structure, 
then,  and  function  there  goes  ever  a  finer  and  finer 
adjustment  of  acts  to  the  preservation  and  furtherance 
of  the  life  of  the  individual  and  of  offspring.  These 
two  form  the  two  first  and  principal  kinds  of  conduct — 
conduct,  viz.,  directed  to  the  preservation  of  the  life 
of  the  individual  and  of  the  race. 

But  with  these  two  the  evolution  of  conduct  is  not 
complete.  It  is  not  enough  for  the  complete  furtherance 
of  life  that  the  individual  be  preserved  and  the  race  be 
propagated.  We  must  (thirdly)  not  inter/ere  with  the 
lives  of  others.  And  (fourthly)  we  must  positively  help 
others  even  with  some  cost  to  ourselves.  These  last 
two  kinds  of  conduct  are  not  only  the  highest — they 
are  also  the  only  decidedly  moral  kind,  or,  as  Spencer 
calls  them,  the  "  emphatically  moral  "  kind,  because, 
as  Spencer  explains,  they  are  the  only  kind  to  the  exer- 
cise of  which  we  need  compulsion.  When  these  four 
are  realised — the  individual  perfectly  maintaining  his 
own  life,  offspring  perfectly  looked  after  and  trained  as 
a  means  to  a  prolonged  and  full  adult  life,  absolute 
non-interference  with  our  neighbour's  life  (implying, 
therefore,  a  perfectly  peaceful  society),  and  the  positive 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  379 

extension  of  aid  to  others  as  a  means  to  their  better 
living — then  is  conduct  completely  evolved. 

Of  these  four  kinds  of  conduct,  however,  the  latter 
two  stand  in  a  very  different  relation  to  the  law  of 
evolution  from  the  first  two.  For  the  relation  of  the 
frst  two  to  the  process  of  evolution  is,  according  to  Spencer, 
most  evident,  whereas  that  of  the  latter  two  is  not  evident. 
It  is  not  difficult  to  see  that  the  first  two  kinds  of  con- 
duct evolve  pari  passu  with  evolution  of  structure  and 
function.  The  higher  animals  attain  individually  to 
greater  quantity  of  life  and  maintain  their  offspring 
more  efficiently  than  the  lower.  But  that  cannot  be 
said  for  the  third  and  fourth  kinds  of  conduct.  Amongst 
the  higher  animals — that  is,  those  of  more  developed 
structure  and  function — there  is  no  apparent  desire  for 
the  peace  of  society  any  more  than  amongst  the  lower. 
Their  mutual  antagonisms  are  just  as  many  as  amongst 
the  lower,  if  they  are  not  more  numerous.  Yet  these 
are  the  very  kinds  of  conduct  that  are,  according  to 
Spencer,  most  "  emphatically  moral."  How,  then,  are 
they  to  be  got  into  the  evolutionary  series  ?  By  a 
method  which  most  readers  will  find  not  a  little  sur- 
prising. We  are,  he  tells  us,  when  we  think  of  the 
higher  animals  and  their  antagonisms,  led  "  by  associa- 
tion "  to  think  of  the  opposite  of  these  antagonisms — 
viz.,  the  friendly  support  of  one  race  of  animals  by  the 
other — and  hence  we  are  led  to  think  that  mutual 
support,  and  not  antagonisms,  must  be  the  characteristic 
of  the  highest  animals.  Experience,  he  admits,  does 
not  tell  us  that  that  is  the  characteristic  of  the  higher 
animals,  still  in  the  higher  animals  "  there  remains  room 
for  modifications  which  will  bring  conduct  "  up  to  this 
level,  and  hence  these  modifications  must  be  regarded 
as  present  when  we  reach  the  highest  stage. 

(4)  "  Evolution  "  and  "  moral  beliefs." 

Having,  as  he  claims,  succeeded  in  showing  that  it  is 
the    end    of    the    evolutionary    process    to    procure    a 


38o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

maximum  of  life,  and  that  this  maximum  is  to  be 
attained  by  the  four  kinds  of  conduct  mentioned — self- 
preservation,  preservation  of  offspring,  non-interference 
with  the  lives  of  others,  and  positive  care  for  the  lives 
of  others — Spencer  goes  on  to  show  that  the  current 
notions  of  "  morally  better  and  worse,"  as  conceived, 
first,  by  ethicians,  and,  second,  by  men  in  general, 
correspond  exactly  with  the  notion  we  have  just  gained 
of  "  the  more  and  the  less  highly  evolved  "  in  human 
conduct. 

In  the  first  place,  he  claims  that  practically  all  exist- 
ing theories  of  morality  accept  the  principle  that  the 
"  good  "  and  the  "  pleasant  "  are  one  ;  similarly,  the 
bad  and  the  painful  are  one.  But,  on  the  other  hand, 
the  pleasant  is  also  the  life-maintaining,  and  the  painful 
is  the  life-destroying.  "  Actions  that  are  injurious  to 
life  are  accompanied  by  disagreeable  feelings  and  the 
beneficial  ones  by  agreeable."  Hence,  the  morally  good 
and  the  life-maintaining  are  one,  and  the  bad  and  the 
life-destroying  are  one.  In  his  own  words,  "  that  which 
in  the  last  chapter  we  found  to  be  highly  evolved  con- 
duct "  (viz.,  the  four  kinds  of  conduct  already  men- 
tioned, all  tending  to  maintain  life  or  health)  "  is  that 
which  in  this  chapter "  (on  "  Theories  of  Good  and 
Evil  ")  "  we  find  to  be  what  is  called  good  conduct, 
.  .  .  and  the  ideal  goal  of  the  natural  evolution  of 
conduct  there  recognised,  we  here  recognise  as  the  ideal 
standard  of  conduct  ethically  considered." 

In  the  second  place,  he  maintains  that  not  only 
ethicians  but  even  ordinary  men  take  the  same  view  of 
morality  that  the  evolutionist  takes  of  the  gradation  of 
conduct.  But  in  order  to  establish  this  second  pro- 
position Spencer,  instead  of  speaking  of  conduct  in  the 
abstract,  proceeds  to  consider  the  various  sides  or  aspects 
of  conduct,  and  analyses  our  moral  ideas  in  regard  to 
each  aspect. 

Conduct,  he  says,  has  four  aspects — first,  a  ph3'sical 
aspect ;    second,  a  biolo^y'ical  aspect ;    third,  a  psycho- 


I 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  381 

logical  aspect ;  fourth,  a  sociological  aspect.  Conduct 
on  its  physical  or  outward  side  is  external  movement. 
Now,  the  movements  of  the  more  highly  developed 
animals  are  characterised  by  two  things — complexity 
and  co-ordination.  The  movements  of  the  fish  are  few 
and  comparatively  aimless.  Those  of  the  bird  (in 
building-time,  for  instance)  are  many  but  unified.* 
So  also  (here  we  meet  the  first  point  of  comparison  with 
our  moral  ideas)  in  the  common  conception  of  morals 
the  good  life  is  always  regarded  as  a  coherent  life,  a 
life  of  moving  equilibrium — a  life  perfectly  adjusted 
to  the  whole  world.  There  is  in  it  neither  excess 
nor  defect.  It  forms  one  consistent  whole.  In  this, 
therefore,  according  to  Spencer,  we  have  an  un- 
doubted parallelism  between  evolution  and  ethical 
convictions. 

Secondly,  there  is  the  biological  aspect.  All  move- 
ments proceed  from  inner  functions,!  and  the  conduct 
of  the  higher  animals  is  characterised  by  "  balance  of 
function  " — that  is,  one  function  is  not  exercised  at 
the  expense  of  any  other.  So,  too  (comparing  again), 
for  the  common  mind  the  good  life  is  that  in  which 
every  function  is  duly  exercised. J  Again,  in  Biology, 
the  mark  of  the  inner  balance  of  functions  is  pleasure, 
that  of  their  discordant  exercise  pain.  And  in  the 
same  way,  turning  to  ethical  opinion,  we  find  that  to 
the  common  mind  the  good  is  that  which  brings  a  sur- 
plusage of  pleasure,  the  bad  that  which  brings  pain. 
The  parallelism,  therefore,  of  evolved  conduct  and 
morals  is  borne  out  by  Biology. 

Thirdly,  conduct  has  its  psychological  side — i.e.,  it 
proceeds    from    the    feelings    as    deliberate    motives    of 

*  Spencer  is  wrong  here — the  movements  on  their  mere  physical 
or  external  side  may  be  many,  but  of  themselves,  that  is,  as  physical, 
they  are  not  co-ordinated.  It  is  the  inner  impulse  or  end  that  co- 
ordinates them. 

t  Why  does  Spencer  here  introduce  the  inner  function  ?  Did  he 
not  define  conduct  as  external  co-ordinated  action  ? 

X  The  value  of  this  statement  of  Spencer's  must  depend  on  the 
interpretation  of  the  word  "  duly,"  which  is  highly  ambiguous. 


3  82  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

action.*  The  higher  the  animal  the  more  complex  the 
feeling,  and,  therefore,  the  further  away  are  the  ends 
aimed  at,  and,  consequently,  the  greater  is  the  adjust- 
ment attained  in  reference  to  the  whole  environing 
world.  Comparing  this  with  our  ethical  views,  the 
good  for  the  common  mind  is  always  regarded  as  a 
last  end.  Present  pleasures  are  not  usually  accounted 
good.  (Departing  somewhat  here  from  the  purpose  of 
the  argument  in  order  to  explain  the  conception  of 
obligation,  he  adds  that  the  faculty  of  "  will,"  in  so 
far  as  it  is  the  faculty  by  which  we  pursue  far-off  ends 
and  restrain  the  desire  for  present  ones,  comes  easily 
to  be  personified  into  the  conception  of  an  authoritative 
society  or  even  of  God.  Will,  as  a  restraining  faculty, 
gives  us  also  the  idea  of  control,  which  in  its  most 
abstract  form  becomes  the  idea  of  moral  obligation.) 
On  the  psychological  side  of  conduct,  therefore,  the 
parallelism  is  still  further  illustrated. 

Fourthly,  conduct  has  its  sociological  aspect,  and 
in  this  the  parallelism  is  most  pronounced  of  all.  For 
Sociological  Evolution  explains  not  only  the  basis  of 
the  laws  of  conduct,  but  also  variations  in  our  moral 
beliefs.  Highly  developed  conduct  is  at  once  a  striving 
after  our  own  pleasure  and  that  of  society.  "  At  the 
outset  these  ends  are  not  harmonious."  f  Their  perfect 
harmony  will  be  the  last  step  in  the  evolutionary  pro- 
cess. The  degree  of  adjustment  to  environment  already 
attained  determines  at  each  stage  the  laws  by  which 
further  harmony  is  to  be  secured,  for,  at  different  places 
and  at  different  times  the  individual  stands  variously 

*  In  describing  the  second  aspect  Spencer  also  spoke  of  feeling, 
but  in  a  different  connection.  He  there  spoke  of  it — first,  not  as  a 
motive  of  conduct,  but  as  springing  from  inner  function  ;  and  second, 
as  indeliberate.  Under  the  psychological  aspect  he  speaks  of  feeling, 
not  as  related  to  function,  but  as  related  to  outer  action,  and  as  de- 
liberate. 

t  Again  we  notice  the  weakness  referred  to  before.  Spencer  cannot 
show  that  the  more  highly  evolved  animals  have  more  care  than  the 
lower  evolved  for  the  life  or  happiness  of  the  whole  race  of  living  things, 
or  even  of  their  own  tribe.  He  simply  takes  the  altruism  ol  llu-  higher 
animals  lor  granted. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  383 

related  to  society.  Comparing  this  with  our  ordinary 
views  of  morahty  we  find  that  men's  ideas  of  right  and 
wrong  vary  very  much  with  times  and  places.  For 
one  set  of  people  the  law  is,  "  Love  even  your  enemies  "  ; 
for  another,  "  Kill  every  one  that  is  not  of  your  tribe." 
Between  these  are  innumerable  compromises.  Present- 
day  Ethics  (which  Spencer  speaks  of  as  actual  or  em- 
pirical Ethics)  can  do  no  more  than  study  these  varying 
beliefs  and  compromises.  But  one  day  there  will  be  a 
valid  absolute  Ethics  available — an  Ethics  that  can 
afford  us  absolutely  valid  and  unchanging  laws,  viz., 
when  the  individual  shall  have  become  perfectly  ad- 
justed to  society.  Such  adjustment  is  to  be  attained 
by  the  development  of  the  passion  of  sympathy,  for 
development  of  sympathy  must  tend  to  make  conduct 
altruistic.  But  sympathy  is  two-fold — sympathy  with 
joy  and  sympathy  with  sorrow.  Sympathy  with  sorrow 
pains,  and  therefore  impairs  life.  Sympathy  with  joy 
pleases,  and  therefore  increases  life.  Hence,  it  is  only 
when  all  sorrow  shall  have  ceased  that  sympathy  will 
have  reached  its  full  efficiency  as  a  world-force.  Then 
we  shall  have  no  difficulty  in  doing  good  to  others. 
At  present  the  difficulties  of  the  moral  life  are  many. 
The  good  to-day  is  always  mixed  with  evil.  It  is  never 
perfect  good.  At  its  best  the  good  can  at  present  be 
only  "  the  least  wrong." 

Thus  Spencer  claims  to  have  shown  that  morality  as 
expressed  in  our  moral  opinions  depends  on  evolution, 
that  it  is  only  part  of  the  universal  process  of  evolution, 
and  develops  concomitantly  with  the  rest  of  the  living 
world.  ' 


Note  on   Leslie   Stephen's  Biologico-Sociological 
Theory 

Before  proceeding  to  the  criticism  of  Biological  Evolution 
we  have  something  to  say  on  the  subject  of  Leslie  Stephen's 
theories,  for  any  account  of  Biological  Evolution  which  did 
not  contain  a  reference  to  him  would  be  incomplete.    He 


384  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

has  developed  the  theory  of  Spencer  on  its  sociological  side. 
Like  Spencer,  he  starts  out  from  the  evolutionary  standpoint, 
and  his  task  is  to  explain  from  that  standpoint  not  the  laws 
that  ought  to  exist,  but  the  moral  laws  that  do  exist,  or, 
which  is  the  same  thing,  the  laws  that  are  actually  enforced 
amongst  us.     He  begins  by  taking  it  for  granted  that  the 
law  of  evolution  prevails  universally,  and  that  therefore  it 
governs  morality  as  well  as  everything  else.     "  The  exposition 
and  establishment  of  the  theory  of  evolution  lies  beyond 
the  Ethical  problem,  and  is  one  of  the  data  which  we  must 
be  content  either  to  repudiate,  or  (as  I  do)  take  for  granted  " 
("  Science  of  Ethics,"  page  80).     The  task  which  he  sets 
before  himself  is  that  of  explaining  morality,  or,  which  is 
the  same  thing  for  Leslie  Stephen,   our  moral  sentiments 
and  beliefs,  from  the  evolutionary  point  of  view.     Besides 
taking  the  law  of  evolution  for  granted  he  also  takes  for 
granted  two  other  things — first,  the  proposition  that  to  the 
common  mind  the  moral  good  and  that  which  brings  happi- 
ness to  society  are  one.     "  Goodness  "  is,  he  admits,  a  very 
crude  conception  ;   but  in  showing  how  the  law  of  evolution 
affects  conduct  he  will  also  fill  in  this  crude  conception,  and 
thereby  give   us   what   he   calls   the   "  scientific  form "   of 
Morality,     Secondly,  he  takes  it  for  granted  that  all  moral 
beliefs  reduce  to  sentiments  or  feelings,  that  reason  is  "  a 
vast  complexity  of  feelings,"  and  that  reasonable  conduct  is 
a   "  process  of  forming  a  certain  hierarchy  in  which  the 
separate  special  instincts  "  (or  feelings)  "  are  subordinated 
to  the  more  central  and  massive."     By  this  last  assumption 
he  hopes  the  more  easily  to  bring  moral  beliefs  under  the 
law  of  evolution.     These  three  propositions  are  the  most 
essential  in  Leslie  Stephen's  ethical,  system.     But  we  caution 
the  student  that  he  will  not  find  them  thus  brought  together 
in  Leslie  Stephen's  book,  nor  laid  down  in  the  same  form, 
nor  always  in  the  same  words  as  those  in  which  we  have 
summarised  them  here  for  convenience. 

Leslie  Stephen  asks  the  question — is  such  a  thing  as  a 
scientific  idea  of  morality  possible  ?  In  support  of  the 
negative  view  there  is  the  argument  that  a  scientific  idea 
connotes  at  least  some  general  agreement  amongst  men, 
whereas  moral  opinions  vary  at  every  age  and  in  every  new 
set  of  circumstances.  But  Leslie  Stephen  adopts  the  affirma- 
tive view,  and  argues  that  though  beliefs  vary,  they  are  not 
opposed,  and  they  are  all  partial  views  of  the  whole  truth. 
Every  moral  belief,  he  asserts,  corresponds  to  and  is  true  for 
a  particular  stage  in  the  evolution  of  man,  and  it  is  the 
business  of  Ethics  to  pick  out  the  underlying  permanent 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  385 

element  in  all  these  beliefs.  This  underlying  element  will 
give  us  the  essential  notion  of  goodness  in  the  abstract.  It 
will  be  the  definition  of  the  "  good." 

Now  the  good,  according  to  Leslie  Stephen,  being  that 
which  promotes  the  welfare  of  society,  he  proceeds  to  enquire 
what  is  the  relation  of  the  individual  to  society.  In  the 
first  place,  he  holds  that  society  is  not  a  mere  aggregate  of 
individuals — it  is  an  organism.  It  is  not,  to  use  the  language 
of  Biology,  a  mere  collection  of  cells — it  is  tissue.  But, 
secondly,  society  exists  previously  to  individuals  fully  made. 
Individuals  are  formed  by  the  social  tissue  and  in  response  to 
the  mutual  pressure  of  part  on  part  of  the  whole  organism. 
How  can  this  be  ?  How  can  mere  pressure  from  environ- 
ment form  a  man  ?  It  can  form  him,  in  Leslie  Stephen's 
theory,  because  man  is  a  mere  bundle  of  feelings,  and 
feelings  are  aroused,  altered,  created,  and  extinguished  in 
an  individual  by  influences  from  without.  The  whole  pro- 
cess of  evolution,  then,  is,  on  this  theory,  a  process  of  shaping 
or  adjusting  the  individual  to  society.  Some  conduct  will 
help  to  that  adjustment,  other  conduct  will  impede  it. 

We  are  now,  according  to  Leslie  Stephen,  at  the  point 
where  conduct  divides  itself  off  into  good  and  bad,  or  rather 
where  our  feelings  divide  themselves  off  into  feelings  of 
approval  for  certain  kinds  of  conduct  as  morally  good,  or 
disapproval  for  others  as  morally  bad.  As  we  saw  before, 
goodness  and  badness  are  respectively  the  pleasure-producing 
and  the  pain-producing  in  reference  to  society.  How  then 
can  we  connect  these  two  with  the  law  of  evolution  or  of 
adjustment  to  social  environment  ?  Very  simply.  When 
the  parts  of  a  watch  are  adjusted  to  the  whole  watch,  then 
we  have  an  efficient  watch.  When  the  organs  of  the  body 
are  adjusted  in  relation  to  one  another  and  to  the  whole  body, 
then  we  have  an  efficient  body — a  healthy  body,  and  the 
result  is  pleasurable  activity.  Non-adjustment  brings  in- 
efficiency, want  of  health,  and  pain.  So  also  acts  that 
further  the  adjustment  of  the  individual  to  society  are 
health-producing  acts.  Those  that  prevent  adjustment 
bring  inefficiency.  Hence  those  acts  that  promote  the  health 
of  society  we  regard  as  good.  Those  that  have  the  opposite 
effect  we  regard  as  bad.  Evolution  is  the  process  of  greater 
and  greater  adjustment  of  the  individual  to  society. 

Now,  the  acts  that  promote  adjustment  at  one  period  and 
in  one  set  of  circumstances  will  not  promote  it  in  another,  just 
as  the  same  medicine  that  helps  digestion  at  one  period  will 
not  help  it  at  another  ;  and  just  as  the  effect  of  medicine  on 
the  body  depends  largely  on  the  previous  state  of  the  body. 

Vol.  I — 25 


386  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

so  also  the  effect  of  an  action  on  society  depends  upon  the 
degree  of  adjustment  of  individuals  to  social  environment 
already  attained.  Hence  our  moral  sentiments  change  with 
times  and  circumstances.  But  they  are  all  true  for  their  own 
period  and  their  own  circumstances.  The  moral  code  of  one 
age  and  country  is  not  that  of  another— but  all  codes  are 
right. 

The  whole  moral  law  then  arises  from  the  fact  that  indi- 
viduals are  a  part  of  the  social  organism,  that  we  are  born, 
not  into  a  merely  disorderly  aggregate  or  chaotic  crowd, 
where  any  place  and  any  act  or  movement  would  be  as  good 
as  any  other,  but  into  an  organised  army  where,  if  we  would 
not  suffer  pain  or  even  be  crushed  out  of  existence,  we  must 
"  learn  to  keep  step  and  rank  and  to  obey  orders." 

The  moral  law  is  therefore,  according  to  Leslie  Stephen, 
"  a  statement  of  the  conditions  or  part  of  the  conditions  that 
are  essential  to  the  vitalit}^  of  the  social  tissue,"  *  and  the 
criterion  by  which  we  shall  know  what  acts  make  for  vitality 
is  their  capability  for  advancing  health.  By  health  he  means 
health  bodily  and  mental. 

This,  Leslie  Stephen  asserts,  is  the  permanent  law  of 
morals  which  is  present  in  all  our  changing  moral  sentiments. 
But,  according  to  our  author,  there  is  another  point  of  im- 
portance. Oiir  sentiments  not  only  vary  naturally  from 
age  to  age,  but  even  from  one  period  in  the  life  of  the  indi- 
vidual to  another.  Even  the  introduction  of  a  new  circum- 
stance may  completely  alter  our  belief  about  the  moral  law. 
We  see  this  even  in  the  case  of  good  men,  who  to-day  assert 
that  lying  is  bad,  and  who  to-morrow  will  tell  a  lie,  let  us  say, 
to  save  their  country,  and  think  that  they  are  right  in  doing 
so.  This  would  seem  to  destroy  the  invariability  of  the 
moral  law  altogether,  whereas  surely  a  moral  law  must  have 
some  stability.  But,  according  to  Leslie  Stephen,  the  case 
just  mentioned  does  not  affect  the  stability  of  the  law. 
For  the  moral  law  refers  not  so  much  to  acts  as  to  character, 
and  character  does  not  change  even  where  action  changes. 
The  moral  law  is  not  "  Do  this,"  but  "  Be  this."  The  con- 
tent of  the  "  do  "  may  change,  while  that  of  the  "  be  "  remains 
the  same.  Thus  a  man  must  always  he  trustworthy,  but 
there  are  times  when  he  may  and  even  must  tell  lies.  Un- 
trustworthiness  can  never  help  society,  but  it  may  be  neces- 
sary for  the  good  of  the  State  that  a  man  should  tell  a  lie, 
and  in  that  case  "  he  will  lie  and  lie  like  a  man."  The  man, 
according  to  Leslie  Stephen,  who  tells  a  lie  to  save  his  country 

*  "  Science  oi  Ethics/  pagu  148. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  387 

is  still  trustworthy,  and  consequently  observes  the  law  of 
trustworthiness. 

Such  are  the  central  points  of  Leslie  Stephen's  theory. 
Our  statement  of  them  may  be  found  useful  by  a  student 
who  is  about  to  read  Leslie  Stephen's  book — a  book  which  he 
will  not  find  it  easy  to  comprehend,* 


CRITICISM    OF    THE    ETHICS    OF    BIOLOGICAL 
EVOLUTION 

(i)  Is  THE  Moral  Law  Subject  to  Evolution  ? 

We  must  now  answer  the  question  whether  the  moral 
law  evolves  or  is  subject  to  change  ?  And  first,  does  it 
evolve  subjectively — that  is,  do  our  conceptions  of  right 
and  wrong  evolve  ?  Secondly,  does  it  evolve  objectively 
— that  is,  can  what  is  right  at  one  age  be  wrong  at 
another,  and  vice  versa  ? 


SUBJECTIVE   VARIATION 

In  the  sphere  of  morals  we  have  to  distinguish  two 
kinds  of  knowledge — knowledge  of  the  basis  of  morals, 
which  we  speak  of  as  the  philosophy  of  morals,  and 
knowledge  of  the  moral  code  itself  or  of  the  things 
which  are  right  and  wrong.  Now  it  would  be  idle  to 
deny  that  our  knowledge  of  the  basis  of  morals  is  sub- 
ject to  variation  and  growth.  The  history  of  philo- 
sophical speculation  is  largely  a  history  of  the  growth 
of  men's  ideas  as  to  the  nature  and  ground  of  goodness, 
duty,  rights,  responsibility  and  the  other  chief  moral 

*  There  are  many  other  forms  of  Biological  Ethics  besides  those 
of  Spencer  and  Leslie  Stephen.  For  instance,  there  is  the  naturalistic 
theory  of  Littre,  which  grounds  all  morals  in  certain  purely  physio- 
logical tendencies.  The  moral*  sentiments,  according  to  this  author 
all  reduce  to  two  things — egoism  and  altruism  ;  and  those  sentiments 
are  respectively  based  on  the  two  physiological  needs  of  self-preserva- 
tion and  the  preservation  of  the  race.  To  these  sentiments  Littre 
adds  a  third,  that  of  justice,  which,  strange  to  say,  though  treated 
as  a  sentiment,  is  purely  intellectual  in  character.  Such  theories  as 
these  it  would,  we  believe,  be  waste  of  time  either  to  develop  or 
criticise 


388  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

categories.  But  here  we  are  concerned  not  with  the 
basis  of  moraUty,  but  with  the  moral  code  itself,  and 
our  question  is  whether  our  knowledge  of  what  is  right 
and  wrong  varies  and  is  subject  to  evolution. 

It  is  obvious  that  a  great  number  of  our  moral  judg- 
ments as  to  right  and  wrong  evolve,  since  it  is  possible 
for  man  to  advance  in  knowledge  ;  and  we  advance  in 
knowledge  within  the  moral  sphere  in  the  same  way  as 
we  advance  in  our  knowledge  of  the  other  sciences, 
viz.,  by  the  acquiring  of  new  truths.  In  some  of  the 
sciences,  like  Geometry,  advance  depends  on  pure 
reasoning  alone  ;  in  others  it  depends  upon  experience. 
Our  knowledge  of  morals  is  advanced  in  both  these 
ways  ;  for  some  of  our  judgments  are  derived  by  reason- 
ing from  the  first  principles  of  morals,  whilst  others 
pre-suppose  a  long  experience  of  the  effects  of  action. 
It  is  in  this  second  way,  for  instance,  that  the  evil  of 
marriage  within  the  forbidden  degrees  comes  to  be 
recognised  ;  without  experience  it  would  not  be  possible 
to  know  that  blood-relationship  is  detrimental  to  the 
end  of  marriage,  which  is  the  maintenance  of  the  race. 

But  the  question  arises  whether  our  knowledge  of 
the  first  -principles  of  morals  is  subject  to  alteration 
and  increase.  As  yet  we  have  not  explained  fully  what 
these  first  principles  are,  or  how  they  are  identified 
and  distinguished  from  other  principles.*  Let  it  suffice 
at  this  point  to  say  that  the  first  principles  of  morals 
concern  the  fundamental  necessities  or  needs  of  nature, 
and  the  question  whether  our  knowledge  of  the  first 
principles  is  subject  to  growth  is  thus  seen  to  be  identical 
with  the  problem  whether  our  knowledge  of  the  funda- 
mental needs  of  our  natural  constitution  is  subject  to 
growth  or  on  the  contrary  was  present  from  the  begin- 
ning. Now  whereas  it  is  possible  for  man  to  remain 
in  ignorance  for  a  very  long  time  in  regard  to  some 
elements  or  aspects  of  our  natural  constitution  it  is 
unthinkable  that  men  could  for  long  remain  unconscious 

•  This  is  done  later,  page  510, 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  389 

of  the  fundamental  natural  needs  such  as  that  for  food, 
for  sex,  for  existence,  for  the  racial  welfare.  Some  of 
our  needs  are  of  the  nature  of  felt  impulsions  like  that 
for  food  and  sex  which  therefore  at  once  awaken  in  us 
a  knowledge  of  their  presence  and  object,  others  are 
known  natural  directions  of  faculties  to  ends,  for  in- 
stance, food  is  naturally  meant  to  sustain  life,  sex  for 
the  maintenance  of  the  race.  But  what  ever  be  the 
nature  of  the  needs  they  all  express  fundamental  re- 
quirements of  which  the  race  would  not  long  remain 
in  ignorance.  And  therefore  the  first  principles  of 
morals,  founded  as  they  are  on  these  fundamental  needs 
and  appetites  must  have  been  known  from  the  be- 
ginning. Of  course  in  this  connection  more  account 
must  be  taken  of  the  means  of  knowledge  open  to 
society  than  to  the  individual.  It  is  impossible  to 
gauge  the  vagaries  and  the  capacity  for  ignorance  of 
the  individual  mind.  But  so  simple  and  obvious  are 
the  fundamental  requirements  of  nature,  and  so  readily 
and  forcibly  do  they  make  themselves  felt  to  any  one 
who  thinks  about  them  that  most  men  and  certainly 
society  at  large  must  always  have  possessed  some  know- 
ledge of  them,  however  incomplete  and  ill-defined  that 
knowledge  might  be.  Men  might  doubt,  for  instance, 
whether  a  particular  prohibition  would  hold  in  certain 
extreme  cases,  but  about  the  general  wrongfulness  and 
deordination  of  lying,  of  infanticide,  of  adultery,  there 
could  be  no  doubt.  As  we  shall  show  later  there  is  no 
race  so  weak  or  ignorant  as  not  to  recognise  evil  in  these 
things,  and  the  punishments  with  which  crimes  of  the 
kind  are  visited  by  the  lowest  savage  races  is  proof  of 
the  clearness  and  strength  of  their  convictions  in  regard 
to  at  least  the  fundamental  truths. 

In   general   then   the   fundamental   relations   and   re- 

//quirements  of  nature  are  easily  recognised,  and  conse- 

'quently  in  our  knowledge  of  the  first  principles  of  morals 

providing  for  these  requirements  there  is  no  room  for 

variation  or  growth,  except,  indeed,  in  the  very  limited 


390  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

sense  that  we  can  acquire  a  more  complete  recognition 
of  the  place  and  meaning  of  those  principles  in  our 
moral  S3stem,  and  can  attain  to  a  more  exact  formula- 
tion of  them  and  of  their  distinction  from  other  mental 
assets.* 


OBJECTIVE   VARIATION 

As  regards  objective  variation  we  must  distinguish 
between  the  applications  of  the  primary  principles  and 
the  primary  principles  themselves. 

The  applications  of  the  primary  moral  principles  to 
individual  acts  must  vary  since  the  circumstances  in 
which  these  principles  apply  are  subject  to  variation. 
There  are  indeed  some  principles  which  in  their  applica- 
tions are  not  dependent  on  circumstances.  These  are 
cases  involving  the  violation  of  some  natural  require- 
ment no  matter  what  the  circumstances.  Suicide,  for 
instance,  is  always  a  violation  of  nature's  purposes  f 
and  ends.  But  in  the  case  of  many  precepts  of  the 
natural  law  it  is  necessary  to  take  full  account  of  the 
circumstances,  and  variation  in  the  requirements  of 
the  moral  law  is  to  be  admitted.  The  law  of  temperance 
for  instance,  binds  all,  but  the  obligation  its  application 
imposes  differs  in  the  case  of  a  health}-  man  and  an 
invalid.  The  law  of  benevolence  has  a  different  signifi- 
cance for  rich  and  poor.  The  widest  divergence  and 
variation  are  naturally  to  be  expected  in  those  depart- 
ments of  morals  that  concern  our  social  obligations,  the 
social  relations  being  most  fluid  of  all,  and  most  liable 
to  continued  transformation.  The  operation  of  economic 
and  other  laws  will  always  necessitate  the  periodic  re- 
moulding of  the  form  of  society  and  therefore  the  social 
laws  are  subject  to  revision  in  their  application  at  every 
age. 

•  A  fuller  investigation  of  our  present  question  is  found  in   the 
chapters  on  Intuitionism  and  Syndcnsis  in  the  present  volume. 
I  For  other  cases  see  Y^Z'^  '34  °^  present  volutnc. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  391 

As  regards  the  fundamental  natural  finnciples  them- 
selves, it  will  be  evident  that  they  are  not  subject  to 
variation,  since  they  are  founded  on  the  nature  of  man 
— on  the  essential  properties  of  our  human  nature  ;  and 
the  essential  properties  of  human  nature  are  not  subject 
to  change  any  more  than  the  properties  of  the  triangle 
and  the  laws  of  mechanics  are  subject  to  change. 

And  it  is  important   to  remember  that   the  natural 
law  is  founded,  not  on  any  aspect  or  any  kind  of  pro- 
perty in  our  nature,  but,  as  we  have  already  pointed 
out,  on  properties  of  a  very  special  kind,  and  bearing 
a   special   relation   to   human   life   and   existence,   viz., 
our  natural  needs  and  the  natural  appetites  on  which 
these    needs    are    founded.     These    fundamental    needs 
and   appetites   are   always   present.     They   may   under 
certain  conditions  cease  to  make  themselves  felt  or  to 
urge  us  to  their  object,  like  the  appeti.e  for  food  in  the 
sick    or    the    satiated.     Some    appetites    depend    upon 
certain  physical  conditions  for  their  exercise.     But  the 
natural    appetites    though    not    always    operative    are 
always  present  and  given  the  right  conditions  will  not 
fail  to  urge  us  to  their  natural  objects.     The  appetites 
therefore  arising  from   our  nature  are  permanent.     The 
body  may  change  in  structure,*  in  shape,  in  colour,  in 
stature,    through   influences   of   environment   and   from 
other  causes.     But  the  natural  appetites  are  essential 
to  the  human  race.     No  man  is  without  them  or  has 
ever  been  without  them.     They  spring  out  of  his  inner- 
most   constitution    and   belong   to   him   in   his   various 
capacities  as  substance,   as  animal,   as  rational  being. 
The  appetite  for  self-preservation  and  welfare,  for  food, 
for  sex,  for  the  care  of  offspring  are  all  natural  needs, 
and   are  inseparable   from   our   humanity.     They   were 
present  in  the  beginning  as  they  are  present  now.     With- 
out them,  says  Leslie  Stephen,  the  race  could  not  have 

*  The  possibility  of  change  even  here  is  strictly  limited.  The 
mechanism  concerned  with  eating,  with  digestion,  with  circulation, 
and  the  central  nervous  system  must  remain  in  the  same  wav  as  the 
fundamental  appetites  remain. 


392  THE  SCIENCE   OF  ETHICS 

survived  a  generation.  And,  consequentl}^,  the  laws  that 
are  based  upon  these  needs  are  permanent  and  in- 
variable. 

The  general  argument  just  given  requires  to  be  supple- 
mented by  a  more  detailed  consideration  of  appetite  in 
relation  to  alteration  and  development. 

All  appetites  are  of  the  nature  of  faculties.  Now  there  are 
only  three  ways  in  which  it  is  possible  to  contemplate  altera- 
tion in  a  faculty — first  {a)  the  appearance  of  a  new  faculty  ; 
secondly  {b)  change  of  object  subtended  by  a  faculty  ; 
thirdly  (c)  disappearance  of  a  faculty.* 

{a)  As  regards  the  appearance  of  a  new  faculty  two  things 
are  clear — first,  that  if  a  radically  new  faculty  were  to  appear 
it  would  be  difficult  to  consider  it  as  natural,  which  is 
generally  regarded  as  identical  with  what  is  original  and  as 
excluding  what  is  adventitious  in  our  constitution  ;  secondly, 
development  proceeds  always  on  the  basis  of,  and  through 
the  operation  of  the  existing  faculties,  and  therefore  any 
faculty  that  might  appear  could  hardly  be  regarded  as 
radically  distinct  from  the  others — it  would  rather  be  of  the 
nature  of  some  extension  or  modification  of  them,  and  hence 
it  would  not  give  rise  to  a  radically  new  law.  It  is  of  course 
difficult  to  set  bounds  by  means  of  mere  a  priori  reasoning 
to  the  powers  of  nature.  But  from  what  we  know  of  nature 
the  emergence  of  a  completely  new  faculty  in  our  consti- 
tution would  seem  to  be  quite  impossible.  If,  however, 
such  a  thing  did  occur,  it  would  at  once  give  rise  to  a  new 
law  binding  to  the  proper  exercise  of  the  faculty  in  question, 
and  in  that  case  the  natural  law  (even  its  first  principles) 
would  be  said  to  vary  by  way  of  addition. 

{b)  The  second  kind  of  alteration  alluded  to  above  is  quite 
impossible  and  indeed  unmeaning.  A  faculty  cannot  change 
its  essential  object.  A  faculty  may  develop  in  such  a  way 
as  to  include  in  its  object  a  greater  range  of  detail.  The 
eye  might  become  capable  of  discerning  new  colours  as  yet 
unknown.  The  ear  might  develop  a  greater  range  of  hearing. 
But  the  eye  could  not  so  alter  its  object  as  to  perceive  sound 
or  weight,  and  it  is  unmeaning  to  claim  that  the  faculty  of 

•  Sometimes  a  faculty  ceases  to  be  cxcrci-scd  through  loss  of  the 
organ,  as  when  vision  is  lost  through  destruction  of  the  eye.  In  this 
case  the  faculty  is  not  really  lost  and  it  would  at  once  rc-assert  itself 
if  the  organ  were  repaired  or  restored.  In  the  text-note  above  we 
refer  to  the  complete  disappcarnnce  of  the  faculty  not  the  suppression 
of  its  activity, 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  393 

vision  could  alter  its  act  Irom  seeing  to  hearing.  It  is  so 
also  with  the  natural  appetites.  They  have  their  own 
natural  objects  which  cannot  be  changed, 

(c)  We  come  now  to  the  third  kind  of  change  indicated  in 
this  note.  The  question  of  the  complete  disappearance  of 
a  natural  appetite  gives  rise  to  the  two  following  considera- 
tions :  first,  there  are  appetites  of  fundamental  importance 
in  our  constitution  which  yet  are  of  such  a  nature  that  dis- 
appearance of  them  would  not  necessarily  involve  alteration 
in  the  moral  law.  For  instance,  even  if  the  natural  appetite 
for  food  were  to  disappear  we  should  still  be  obliged  to  eat, 
since  food  is  necessary  to  life,  and  every  living  substance 
has  a  natural  appetite  for  continuance  in  life.  As  long  as 
this  appetite  remains  we  shall  be  subject  to  the  law  to  take 
the  means  necessary  to  life.  Secondly,  and  to  this  we  invite 
the  reader's  special  attention,  a  change  of  constitution  in- 
volving the  disappearance  of  any  of  the  fundamental  appe- 
tites is  not  to  be  contemplated  as  possible,  since,  should  such 
disappearance  occur,  the  race  would  suffer  irreparable  harm 
and  probably  complete  extinction.  If  the  animal  had  no 
natural  appetite  for  food,  for  sex,  for  self-preservation — if  it 
was  all  the  same  to  the  animal  whether  it  lived  or  died,  the 
race  of  animals  could  not  survive.  It  is  the  same  in  the 
case  of  the  human  species.  It  is  through  the  working  of  the 
natural  appetites  deep  down  in  our  constitution  that  our 
human  interests  are  maintained,  that  action  is  secured,  that 
life  is  regarded  as  worth  preserving.  Without  powerful 
natural  appetites  urging  to  the  great  fundamental  objects 
and  to  the  things  necessary  for  these  objects  the  world  of 
life  and  even  of  human  life  would  become  a  world  of  complete 
inertia,  and  decay.  It  is  evident  therefore  that  the  funda- 
mental appetites  must  remain  as  long  as  the  species  survives, 
and  consequently  that  alteration  of  the  moral  law  by  way  of 
subtraction,  i.e.,  by  the  cessation  of  its  fundamental  precepts 
is  impossible. 


THE   EVOLUTIONIST   ARGUMENT   IN   REGARD  TO   MORALS 

Having  shown  from  the  nature  of  morals,  and  the 
manner  in  which  they  are  grounded  in  our  constitution, 
that  the  fundamental  principles  considered  objectively 
do  not  vary  in  themselves,  however  much  they  may 
vary  in  their  application,  we  now  go  on  to  consider  the 
chief   argument    of   the   evolutionists,    which   is   to   the 


394  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

effect,  first,  that  morals  are  a  part  of  the  visible  universe 
which  is  in  its  entirety  subject  to  evolution — "  if  the 
entire  visible  universe,"  writes  Spencer,  "  has  been 
evolved  .  .  .  the  necessary  implication  is  that  those 
phenomena  of  conduct,  with  which  morality  is  con- 
cerned, also  conform  "  (to  laws  of  evolution) — secondly, 
that  man  is  developed  from  the  brute  species,  and 
therefore  that  the  laws  of  human  conduct  develop  pari 
passu  with  our  human  constitution.* 

In  our  answer  to  this  argument  we  propose  to  develop 
three  points,  {a)  that  even  if  the  whole  universe  and  man 
in  particular  were  evolved  the  laws  of  morals  need  not 
necessarily  be  regarded  as  subject  to  variation  ;  [h]  that 
universal  evolution  is  an  unproved  assumption  ;  (c)  that 
the  evolution  of  man  from  the  brute  species  has  not 
been  proved. 

[a)  Even  if  the  hypothesis  of  universal  evolution  were 
fully  established  we  should  still  not  be  justified  in 
regarding  the  laws  of  human  conduct  as  variable,  for 
the  natural  law  is  founded  on  our  nature  as  men,  and 
therefore  we  should  still  be  subject  to  it  as  long  as  we 
arc  men  and  even  though  the  human  race  was  evolved 
from  a  species  lower  than  itself.  Thus  even  if  man  be 
evolved,  trutn  :ind  justice  and  temperance  would  still 

*  There  is  a  second  argument  which  it  will  not  be  necessary  to 
develop  at  great  length  here  since  it  has  already  been  considered  to 
some  extent  (page  3S7)  and  is  treated  in  its  various  parts  at  ililfcrcnt 
places  in  our  second  volume.  This  argument  is  based  on  experience 
and  appeals  to  the  various  changes  that  havjc  occurred  in  the  moral 
laws  recognised  by  society  at  diilerent  periods  in  the  world's  history. 
Now  it  is  evident  that  this  argument  is  largely  inapplicable  to  our 
present  enquiry.  For  these  changes  are  subjective,  i.e.,  they  represent 
periods  of  growth  in  our  opinions  about  morals,  whereas  our  present 
enquiry  relates  to  the  po.ssibility  of  objective  variation  ;  secondly, 
these  changes  largely  lx;long  to  the  applications  of  principles,  whereas 
our  present  discussion  relates  to  the  fundamental  moral  principles 
themselves.  Hut  as  regards  those  fundamental  principles,  we  can 
safely  say  that  no  enquiry  of  sociologist  or  of  historian  has  succeeded 
in  disclosing  divergence  and  variation  either  as  between  periods  or 
races  such  as  might  be  used  to  sui)port  the  argument  of  the  evolu- 
tionist. On  the  contrary,  as  will  be  fully  shown  in  o\ir  second  volume 
in  connection  with  the  chief  laws  of  morals,  the  moral  codes  accepted 
by  those  savage  races  that  come  nearest  to  the  primitive  stock  are  in 
closcttt  correspondence  with  the  laws  accepted  by  civilised  men  to-day. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  395 

be  human  goods  and  their  opposites  human  evils  ;  in 
other  words  the  law  of  good  and  evil  in  regard  to  these 
things  would  not  be  altered,  even  if  man  were  evolved ; 
the  law  of  marriage  would  still  be  obligatory,  for  no 
theory  of  the  origin  of  man  can  alter  the  fact  that  the 
child  cannot  develop  itself,  that  for  its  support  and 
rearing  it  needs  the  help  of  others  through  many  years, 
that  the  child  has  a  claim  on  those  who  brought  it  into 
life  to  support  and  maintain  it,  and  that  the  only  parties 
known  to  nature  as  bound  to  respond  to  that  claim  are 
the  parents.  And  marriage  is  nothing  more  than  this 
as  we  shall  show  fully  later — the  union  of  father  and 
mother  for  the  rearing  of  the  child.  Again,  whether 
man  is  developed  from  the  brute  or  not,  a  man  has  a 
right  to  the  products  of  his  own  energies,  and  being  the 
equal  of  other  men  in  his  natural  constitution  he  is  not 
to  be  treated  by  others  as  mere  means — in  which  rela- 
tion is  found  the  first  principle  of  commutative  justice. 
These  few  examples  will  suffice  to  bring  out  the  bearing 
of  our  present  argument.  A  man's  duty  is  determined 
by  his  human  nature,  by  his  natural  faculties  and  their 
objects,  just  as  what  is  good  for  an  animal  is  determined 
by  the  animal  nature.  But  man's  nature  is  what  it  is, 
and  his  appetites  are  what  they  are  whatever  be  man's 
histor}'.  That  is  why  in  determining  the  moral  codej 
the  philosopher  does  not  ask  about  man's  origin,  whether,/ 
for  instance,  he  came  from  the  brute,  whether  reason  isf 
developed  from  sense,  or  speech  from  mere  animal  ex- 
pression of  feeling.  These  enquiries  have  nothing  to  do 
with  the  determination  of  the  moral  code.  The  philo- 
sopher, in  setting  out  the  code  of  natural  morals,  merely 
considers  man  as  he  is,  asks  what  his  human  nature  is, 
and  what  are  his  natural  needs  ;  and  on  the  basis  of 
these  essential  needs  and  their  objects  he  proceeds  to 
build  up  the  S3-stem  of  natural  law.  The  fundamental 
code  therefore  of  human  morals  does  not  vary  or  evolve. 
To  this  line  of  argument  the  objection  may  be  raised 
that  it  assumes  the  essential  distinction  of  the  human 


39"^  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

from  the  brute  nature,  whereas  if  man  be  evolved  the 
human  and  brute  natures  are  not  essentially  distinct 
but  melt  into  one  another  gradually  and  imperceptibly  ; 
in  this  case  human  nature  would  only  be  a  better  brute, 
nature  and  the  laws  of  human  conduct  only  the  brute 
laws  but  elevated  and  refined  ;  hence  the  moral  law  is 
subject  to  evolutionary  changes. 

We  answer,  as  well  might  we  say  that  because  the 
colours  of  the  spectrum  melt  into  one  another  imper- 
ceptibly therefore  green  is  only  another  kind  of  3'ello\v, 
and  purple  another  kind  of  green,  as  to  say  that  human 
nature  cannot  be  essentially  distinct  from  other  natures 
on  the  hypothesis  that  it  evolves  out  of  them  and  is 
continuous  with  them.  The  fact  is  that  the  colours 
of  the  spectrum  are  absolutely  distinct  in  spite  of  the 
phenomenon  of  continuity  between  its  parts.  So  also 
man's  nature  is  distinct  from  that  of  the  brute,  no  matter 
how  he  may  be  related  to  the  brute  in  origin,  and  the 
only  difficulty  in  the  case  is  the  difficulty  of  explaining, 
not  how  our  human  nature  can  be  distinct  from  that 
of  the  brutes,  but  how  of  things  so  radically  and  so 
obviously  distinct,  as  we  shall  presently  show  them  to 
be,  one  could  have  sprung  out  of  the  other.  But  that 
is  a  difficulty  for  the  evolutionist  not  for  us.  Our  con- 
tention therefore  is  that  even  if  man  were  sprung  from] 
the  brutes  he  would  still  be  subject  to  human  laws,i 
not  laws  befitting  the  brute  nature,  and  that  the  moral 
law  for  human  beings  is  in  its  fundamental  principles; 
not  subject  to  change. 

We  now  go  on  to  the  second  part  of  our  discussion. 

{b)  Universal  evolution  an  unproved  assumption.  In 
Spencer's  theory  the  evolution  of  morality,  is  as  we  have 
said,  based  upon  the  assumption  that  the  whole  world 
is  subject  to  evolution.  Now,  this  assumption,  in  order 
to  be  made  the  basis  of  the  whole  theory  of  morals, 
should  itself  be  absolutely  certain,  and  if  it  is  not  cer- 
tain no  trustworthy  theory  could  be  built  upon  it.  We 
are,    therefore,    justified   in   askin^^   is    tjic   assumption 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  397 

certain — does  it  represent  an  incontrovertible  fact  ? 
We  claim  that  it  is  not  certain,  that  it  does  not  repre- 
sent an  incontrovertible  fact,  and  that  hence  the  system 
of  Ethics  that  is  built  upon  it  is  vitiated  and  unreliable 
from  the  very  start. 

No  scientific  assumption  could  be  regarded  as  certain 
on  which  scientists  are  not  universally,  or  almost  uni- 
versally, agreed.  But  the  theory  of  Universal  Evolu- 
tion is  not  universally  agreed  upon.  On  the  contrary, 
it  is  the  theory  of  extremists  merely,  and  recent  investi- 
gation is,  on  the  admission  of  the  most  trustworthy 
scientists,  dead  against  it.  And  even  the  extremists 
who  still  profess  it  do  so,  it  seems  to  us,  not  because 
investigation  leads  them  to  do  so,  but  in  spite  of  in- 
vestigation, and  merely  as  an  hypothesis  that  may  some 
day  be  brought  into  harmony  with  the  known  facts. 

In  support  of  this  contention  it  will  be  enough  to 
show,  on  the  testimony  of  evolutionists  themselves, 
that  there  are  gaps  in  nature  which  Evolutionary  science 
is  quite  unable  to  bridge  over — that  is,  that  there  are 
cases  of  species  which,  so  far  as  science  can  ascertain, 
are  not  evolved  from  any  other  species,  but  are  simply, 
so  far  as  can  be  seen,  original  parts  of  the  universe. 
This  having  been  established,  it  will  follow  that  the 
assumption  of  Universal  Evolution  is  an  unpr-oved 
hypothesis. 

Let  us  quote  the  testimonies  of  some  scientists  on  the 
question  before  us. 

Herr  Du  Bois-Reymond,  of  Berlin  University,  an 
avowed  evolutionist  and  materialist,  so  far  from  ad- 
mitting that  science  has  shown  that  the  law  of  con- 
tinuity or  of  evolution  is  universal,  declares  that  the 
universe  confronts  us  with  seven  problems  or  enigmas 
for  which  science  can  offer  no  solution.  These  are : 
(i)  the  nature  of  matter  and  of  force,  (2)  the  origin  of 
motion,  (3)  the  origin  of  Hfe,  (4)  the  apparently  designed 
order  of  the  universe,  (5)  the  origin  of  sensation  and  of 
consciousness,    (6)    the   origin   of   rational   thought   and 


398  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

speech,  (7)  free-will.  The  first,  second,  and  fifth  of 
these  enigmas  he  regards  as  transcendental  and  beyond 
the  possibility  of  solution.  The  others  in  his  judgment 
may  perhaps  be  solved  some  day.* 

Of  these  enigmas,  however,  we  shall  here  consider 
only  two — namely,  the  third  and  the  sixth,  which  latter 
point  will  be  found  to  coincide  with  the  third  part  of 
our  discussion  relating  as  it  does  to  the  origin  of  man. 

Evolutionary  theory  of  the  origin  of  life  not  certain. 
There  was  a  time  when  life  did  not  exist  on  the  earth. 

"  There  has  been,"  says  Virchow,  "  a  beginning  of  life, 
since  geology  points  to  epochs  in  the  formation  of  the  earth 
when  life  was  impossible,  and  when  no  vestige  of  it  is  to  be 
found." 

"  There  was  a  time,"  says  Tyndall,  "  when  the  earth  was 
a  red-hot  molten  globe  on  which  no  life  could  exist." 

How,  then,  did  life  arise  on  the  earth  ?  Professor 
Huxley  asserts  that  it  must  have  come  into  existence  by 
spontaneous  generation — that  is,  it  must  have  proceeded 
out  of  dead  matter  ;  and  he  makes  this  supposition 
because  it  is,  he  believes,  the  only  one  which  is  agreeable 
to  science.  Now,  for  many  years,  and  in  every  de- 
partment of  enquiry,  in  Chemistry,  in  Biology,  and  in 
Geology,  scientists  have  been  labouring  to  establish  this 
assumption  which  Huxley  would  scarcely  regard  as  a 
mere  assumption,  so  agreeable  is  it  to  science  and  the 
scientific  mind  ;  but,  on  their  own  testimony,  it  is  not 
yet  nearly  established,  nor  likely  ever  to  be  established. 

"  Of  the  causes  which  have  led  to  the  origination  of  living 
matter,"  writes  Huxley  himself,  "  it  may  be  said  that  we 

•  Reden  von  Emil  Du  Bois-Reymond,  XIII. 

We  wish  to  state  from  the  outset  that  we  arc  not  an  authority  on 
the  general  subject  of  Evolution.  Nor  is  it  necessary  that  we  should 
be  so  for  the  purposes  of  our  present  question.  Our  task  is  to  show 
that  the  Evolutionary  philosophers  themselves  are  not  agreed  about, 
and  arc  not  likely  to  agree  about,  the  universality  of  Iwolution.  The 
testimonies  ^jiven  here  arc  only  a  few  of  those  that  mi^'ht  be  (luoted. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  399 

know  absolutely  nothing.  .  .  .  Science  has  no  means  to 
form  an  opinion  on  the  commencement  of  life — we  can  only 
make  conjectures  without  scientific  value." 

And  Tyndall : — 

"  Here,  as  in  all  other  cases,  the  evidence  in  favour  of 
spontaneous  generation  crumbles  in  the  grasp  of  the  com- 
petent enquirer."  * 

And  Darwin  : — 

"  No  evidence  worth  anything  has  as  yet,  m  my  opinion, 
been  advanced  in  favour  of  a  living  being  being  developed 
from  inorganic  matter." 

Again,  M.  de  Quatrefages  sums  up  the  results  of  his 
own  minute  studies  on  the  lowest  forms  of  life,  thus  : — 

"  To  attempt  to  confound  these  two  (animate  and  in- 
animate) is  to  go  in  direct  opposition  to  all  the  progress 
made  for  a  century.  ...  It  is  inexplicable  that  people 
should  recently  again  have  compared  crystals  to  the  simpler 
forms  of  life."  f 

And  Professor  Virchow  (the  eminent  Evolutionist), 
speaking  at  the  Munich  Congress  of  1877,  said  : — 

"  Whoever  recalls  to  mind  the  lamentable  failure  of  all  the 
attempts  to  discover  a  decided  support  for  the  generatio 
acqiiivoca  in  the  lower  forms  of  transition  from  the  inorganic 
to  the  organic  world  will  feel  it  doubly  serious  to  demand  that 
this  theory,  so  utterly  discredited,  should  be  in  any  way 
accepted  as  the  basis  of  all  our  views  of  life." 

Nor  are  the  scientists  of  more  recent  date  any  nearer 
to  the  solution  of  the  problem  than  Huxley  and  Tyndall 
were. 

"  The  more  closely,"  writes  G.  V.  Bunge,J  ..."  and  the 
more  deeply  we  examine  the  phenomena  of  life  the  more  we 
come  to  see  that  processes  which  w^e  had  thought  to  explain 

*  "  Fragments  of  Science,"  II.,  page  321. 

t  "  The  Human  Species,"  page  3. 

X  "  Lchrbuch  dcr  Physiologic  dcs  Mcnschcn  "  (1905).  Quoted 
from  Wasmann's  "  Die  modcrne  Biologic  und  die  Entwicklungstheoric," 
paije  245. 


400  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

as  results  of  physical  or  chemical  laws  .  .  .  simply  deride 
every  attempt  at  a  mechanical  explanation." 

And  Dr.  Hertwig  *  writes  : — 

"  The  development  of  the  eye  and  ear  .  .  .  cannot  be 
regarded  as  a  mechanical  process.  And  the  same  can  be 
said  of  every  process  of  development,  for  everywhere  we 
meet  with  a  factor  which  is  absolutely  distinct  from  any 
form  of  mechanism — a  factor,  too,  which  has  the  principal 
part  to  play  in  the  cell-organism." 

To  the  same  effect  we  have  the  recent  declarations  of 
the  Evolutionary  physiologist,  Hans  Driesch,t  who  now 
rejects  as  groundless  the  "  Maschinentheorie "  which 
once  he  defended. 

"  In  the  course  of  the  individual  development,"  he  writes, 
"  all  eggs  have  originated  in  the  breaking  up  of  one  cell. 
How  can  a  complicated  piece  of  machinery  continue  to  divide 
itself  up  in  this  way  and  yet  always  continue  to  exist  ?  It 
is  impossible,  and  consequently  we  may  regard  the  machine- 
theory  as  overthrown."  % 

We  close  this  series  of  testimonies  by  a  quotation  from 
Dr.  Wilson,  the  eminent  P:ofessor  of  Zoology  in  the 
University  of  Columbia.  Summing  up  the  results  of 
recent  science  in  regard  to  this  question  of  the  develop- 
ment of  life  from  non-living  matter,  he  writes  : —  § 

"  It  is  true  that  we  may  trace  in  organic  nature  long  and 
finely  graduated  series  leading  upward  from  the  lower  to  the 
higher  forms,  and  we  must  believe  that  the  wonderful  adaptive 
manifestations  of  the  more  complex  forms  have  been  derived 
from  simpler  conditions  through  the  progressive  operations  of 
natural  causes.  But  when  all  these  admissions  are  made  and 
when  the  conserving  action  of  natural  selection  is  in  the  fullest 
degree  recognised,  we  cannot  close  our  eyes  to  two  facts, 
first,  that  we  are  utterly  ignorant  of  the  manner  in  which  the 
idioplasm  of  the  germ  cell  can  so  respond  to  the  influence  of 
the  environment  as  to  call  forth  an  adaptive  variation  ;  and, 
second,  that  the  study  of  the  cell  has  on  the  whole  seemed  to 

•  "  Universal  Biology  "  (1906).     Quoted  from  Wasmann,  page  246. 

I  Sec  Wasmann,  pages  248-251. 

J  Wasmann,  page  249. 

§  "  The  Cell  in  Development  and  Inheritance  "  (igof)),  page  434. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  401 

widen  rather  than  to  narrow  the  enormous  gap  that  separates 
even  the  lowest  forms  of  life  from  the  inorganic  world." 

(c)   The  evolution  of  Reason  not  proved. 

Everything  that  can  be  said  of  the  relation  of  the 
inorganic  to  the  organic  world — that  history  has  left  no 
trace  of  any  transition  between  them,  that  experiment, 
wide-extending  and  long-continued  as  it  has  been,  has 
failed  utterly  to  bridge  over  the  chasm  between  them, 
that  the  more  science  advances  the  less  seems  to  be  the 
chance  of  finding  the  link  that  is  to  bind  one  species  to 
the  other,  all  this  holds  with  equal  force  in  the  case  of 
tlie  relation  of  animal  to  man.  History  has  left  us  no 
trace  of  any  link  between  them.  Experiment  has  failed 
utterly  to  produce  out  of  the  animal  consciousness  any- 
thing approaching  even  to  Reason,  and  the  most  recent 
discoveries  in  Palaeontology  have  only  helped  to  destroy 
the  hopes  of  the  Darwinists  that  sooner  or  later  the 
earth  would  yield  up  out  of  its  hiding-places  the  long- 
looked-for  link  between  animal  and  man. 

The  attempted  proofs  of  evolutionists  in  this  matter 
are  not  of  a  very  high  order.  Some  Darwinists  have 
been  wont  to  point  out  certain  likenesses  between  the 
sense  powers  of  the  animals  and  Reason  as  proof  of  the 
possible  origin  of  the  latter  from  the  former,  and  of  the 
possible  future  development  of  present  brute-powers  into 
a  power  of  Reason.  Now,  between  animal  and  man 
some  likenesses  are  to  be  expected,  both  as  regards 
action  and  as  regards  knowledge.  It  would  be  a  strange 
thing,  indeed,  if  sense,  which  is  a  genuine  source  of 
knowledge,  did  not  evince  in  its  effects  some  likeness  to 
Reason.*  But,  judging  from  the  methods  of  the  com- 
parative sciences  generally,  we  should  think  that  the 
relation  between  sense  and  Reason  is  to  be  discovered, 
not  by  emphasising  certain  very  trifling  points  either  of 
likeness  or  of  difference  in  the  effects  of  these  two  powers 
respectively,    but    by   considering   these   effects   in   the 

*  The  "  ratio  participata  "  of  St.  Thomas  Aquinas. 
Vol.  1 — 2G 


402  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

broadest  possible  manner — by  considering,  for  instance, 
the  general  character  of  the  works  of  men  upon  the  earth 
and  the  progressiveness  of  which  these  works  are  the 
certain  witness,  and  comparing  them  with  the  general 
unprogressiveness  of  animals.  And  comparing  sense 
and  Reason  in  this  way,  we  find  that  whereas  there  are 
innumerable  races  of  animals  in  the  world  to-day,  yet 
in  not  one  of  these  races  is  there  the  slightest  sign  of 
a  possibility  that  it  will  one  day  develop  into  a  race  of 
rational  beings.  Man  is  a  creature  of  development,  the 
brute  beast  is  incapable  of  development.  The  animals 
of  the  forest,  the  cattle  in  our  fields,  reach  their  full  per- 
fection before  they  are  a  couple  of  years  old  ;  and  that 
degree  of  perfection  which  is  marked  out  for  them,  not, 
indeed,  by  their  own  exertion,  but  by  nature  itself,  they 
never  seem  capable  of  exceeding.  The  most  intelligent 
animal  of  our  acquaintance  is  no  nearer  to  producing 
the  simplest  work  of  man  than  were  the  animals  of 
thousands  of  years  ago.  Animals  have  no  history,  and 
are  capable  of  none.  They  simply  live  and  die,  and  of 
their  labour  no  result  appears.  In  this  inability  to 
develop  beyond  a  certain  point  we  have  a  most  striking 
proof  of  the  impassable  gulf  that  separates  sense  from 
Reason,  animal  from  man.  And  of  this  inability  it  is 
easy  to  assign  the  cause.  Sense  cannot  rise  above  the 
passing  individual  impression.  Man  can  think  of  the 
most  universal  relations.  The  animal  lives  only  from 
moment  to  moment,  from  feeling  to  feeling,  whereas  for 
development  we  have  to  think  beyond  the  present,  and, 
indeed,  beyond  all  individual  conditions.  We  have  to 
gauge  the  future  from  the  past,  to  consider  invisible  and 
immaterial  relations  beyond  the  reach  of  sense — we  have 
to  fashion  and  to  follow  ideals.  In  this  we  have  the 
reason  why  development  is  not  possible  for  the  animal 
species. 

Some  claim,  indeed,  that  if  animals  had  language  they 
would  develop  just  as  men.  But  is  not  this  an  utter 
subversion  of  the  evident  order  in  which  language  stands 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  403 

to  Reason  ?  Language  is  not  the  ground  of  Reason,  but 
is  itself  made  by  Reason.  Language  supposes  a  power 
of  thinking,  of  using  symbols — that  is,  a  power  of  ab- 
stracting from  the  individual  thing  and  thinking  many 
individual  things  under  the  one  symbol.  This  only  a 
rational  thing  can  do.  Only  Reason  can  abstract  and 
universalise.  No  animal  has  ever  used  a  symbol.*  It 
has  never  known,  and  could  never  know,  the  meaning  of 
"  X  "  or  of  "  y  "  as  a  symbol  of  quantit}'.  But  language 
is  nothing  else  than  the  expression  of  thoughts  and 
things  in  symbols  ;  every  word  composing  the  language 
expresses  a  universal  conception — a  conception  of  the 
Reason ;  and,  therefore,  Reason  is  the  ground  of 
language,  not  language  of  Reason,  and  to  claim  that  if 
animals  had  language  they  would  become  like  to 
rational  beings  is  to  put  the  effect  in  the  place  of  the 
cause. 

But  our  principal  aim  in  this  section  is  to  show,  not 
that  universal  evolution  is  not  and  could  not  be  true, 
but  that  it  is  not  proved  or  certain.  And,  therefore, 
we  go  on  to  quote  some  testimonies  of  scientists  to  the 
effect  that  the  supposed  evolution  of  man  from  animal 
has  not  been  established  by  science,  but  is  still  a  mere 
hypothesis. 

On  this  point  we  have  the  decisive  testimony  of 
Wallace,  who,  "  while  he  agrees  with  Darwin  that  man 
must  be  a  descendant  of  apes  as  to  his  bodily  frame, 
maintains  that  his  higher  mental  and  moral  faculties 
must  have  had  another  origin."  j 

*  The  difference  between  man  and  animal  in  respect  of  language 
cannot  be  the  presence  of  the  speaking  mechanism  in  the  case  of  man 
and  its  absence  in  the  animal.  As  a  matter  of  fact  the  mechanism 
and  power  of  forming  words  are  possessed  by  some  animals,  e.g.,  the 
parrot.  Yet  they  have  no  language  which  is  the  power  to  give  ex- 
pression to  all  one's  varying  thought.  Clearly  then  the  difference 
lies  in  the  absence  of  the  power  to  form  universal  conceptions  in  one 
species  and  its  presence  in  the  other,  As  we  have  said  above,  language 
consists  of  a  string  of  universal  terms,  every  one  of  which  terms  the 
speaker  knows  the  meaning  of,  taken  as  a  universal ;  and  therefore 
behind  these  terms  are  universal  conceptions. 

I  See  "  Darwinism,"  page  474. 


404  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Also  of  Mivart,  a  convinced  evolutionist,  whose 
"  Reason  abundantly  sufficed  to  convince  him  that 
there  was  a  wider  break  in  nature  between  man  and 
the  highest  ape  than  between  the  highest  ape  and  an 
oyster,"  * 

And  Spencer  himself,  though  he  does  not  believe  that 
the  transition  from  animal  to  man  is  impossible  (on  the 
contrary,  he  regards  it  as  necessary),  still  seems  to  recog- 
nise an  essential  difference  between  animal  and  man 
when  he  says,  speaking  of  certain  correspondences  found 
to  be  present  in  movements  executed  by  thought,  that 
he  finds  this 

"  higher  order  of  correspondence  in  time  scarcely  more  than 
foreshadowed  among  the  higher  animals  and  definitely  ex- 
hibited only  when  we  come  to  the  human  race."  f 

And  again : — 

"  The  animal's  nervous  system  is  played  on  by  external 
objects  ...  it  cannot  evolve  a  consciousness  that  is  inde- 
pendent of  the  immediate  environment."  Yet  we  know 
that  it  is  the  privilege  of  reason  to  think  beyond  the  widest 
bounds  of  environment. 

These  testimonies  go  to  show  that  there  is  something 
in  human  Reason  that  could  not  possibly  be  developed 
out  of  the  animal  faculties. 

Lewes,  also,  in  his  "  Problems  of  Life  and  Mind," 
says  that 

"  brutes  have  no  conceptions,  no  general  ideas,  no  symbols 
of  logical  operations." 

And  he  regards  the  absurdity  of  thinking  that  brutes 
could  be  rational  as  so  glaring  that 

"  we  need  not  wonder  at  profoundly  meditative  minds 
having  been  led  to  reject  with  scorn  the  hypothesis  whicli 
seeks  for  an  explanation  of  human  intelligence  in  the  func- 
tions of  the  bodily  organism  common  to  man  and  animals."  I 

*  See  "  Lessons  from  Nature,"  pages  180-184. 

t  "  Psychology,"  I.,  page  326. 

J  "  Problems  of  Life  and  Mind,"  I.,  page  157. 


I 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  405 

Miiller,  also,  in  his  work  on  "  Physiology,"  clearly 
lays  it  down  that 

"  the  cause  of  this  difference  between  man  and  beasts  does 
not  lie  in  the  comparative  lucidity  or  obscurity  of  the  impres- 
sions made  on  their  minds  respectively  ;  for  in  this  respect 
there  is  no  superiority  in  the  liuman  mind.  ...  I  am  there- 
fore of  opinion  that  the  human  mind  also  would  never  derive 
from  the  mere  experience  afforded  by  the  senses  and  from 
habit  the  general  abstract  idea  of  causality  unless  it  had 
a  certain  power  of  abstraction,  &c."  * 

These  testimonies  are  confirmed  by  recent  wTiters  on 
palaeontology,  who  claim  that  so  far  at  all  events  as  that 
science  goes,  the  possibility  of  man  having  developed 
from  the  brute  is  remote  in  the  extreme.  The  missing 
link,  in  spite  of  much  energy  spent  in  the  search  for  him, 
is  still  missing.  And  the  search  for  him  has  only  helped 
to  confirm  the  already  well-grounded  judgment  of  many 
of  the  soberer  school  of  evolutionists,  who  believed  not 
only  that  mind  was  not  an  evolution  from  sense,  but 
that  the  human  body  f  also  was  not  an  evolution  ;  that 
it  appeared  on  the  earth  suddenly  and  without  any  pre- 
cursor. Skeletons  and  skulls  have,  indeed,  on  various 
occasions  been  discovered  which,  it  was  thought,  sup- 
plied the  link,  or  something  like  the  link,  between  animal 
and  man.  But  the  results  of  the  investigations  to  which 
these  facts  gave  rise  were  thus  summed  up  by  Professor 
W.  Branco  (Director  of  the  Geological-Palaeontological 
Institute  of  the  University  of  Berlin)  in  1901  : — 

"  Man  confronts  us  in  the  bowels  of  the  earth — a  true 
noviis  homo.  .  .  .  He  appears  to  us  quite  suddenly  in  the 
post-tertian  period,  without  any  forerunners.  Tertiary  human 
remains  are  wanting  utterly,  and  the  traces  of  human  activity 
which  it  was  believed  the  tertiary  period  preserved  to  us  are 
of  the  most  doubtful  character.     But  post-tertiary  human 

I  remains  we  have  in  plenty  ;   and  post-tertiary  man  confronts 
*  Vol.  II.,  page  1349. 
t  Even  if  man's  body  were  evolved  from  that  of  the  brute,  we 
could  not  speak  of  man  as  evolved,  unless  Reason  also  was  evolved 


4o6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

lis — a  fully  developed  Homo  Sapiens.  Most  of  those  primitive 
men  had  skulls  of  which  any  man  might  be  proud.  They  had 
neither  long  ape-like  arms  nor  ape-like  teeth.  No,  post- 
tertiary  man  was  in  every  way  a  genuine  human  being."  ♦ 

These  testimonies  will  suffice  to  show  that  Spencer 
was  not  justified  in  his  assumption — an  assumption  on 
which  he  attempted  to  base  the  whole  science  of  Ethics 
— that  the  whole  universe  is  subject  to  evolution,  and 
that  the  moral  law,  as  part  of  the  universe,  must  be 
subject  to  the  same. 

Having  considered  the  general  question  whether  the 
moral  law  is  subject  to  evolution,  and  having  examined 
the  chief  arguments  of  the  evolutionists  in  this  connec- 
tion, we  now  go  on  to  consider  certain  other  parts  and 
aspects  of  the  evolutionist  theory.  But  before  doing 
so  we  may  be  allowed  to  present  to  the  reader  one  or  two 
expressions  of  opinion  by  recent  philosophers  concerning 
the  general  principle  and  method  of  the  Ethics  of 
Biological  Evolution. 

{a)  Some  excellent  remarks  on  the  relation  between  evolu- 
tion of  structure  and  the  moral  instincts  are  to  be  found  in 
Martineau's  "  Types  of  Ethical  Theory."  On  the  time  re- 
quirements of  evolution  he  says  :  "  By  spinning  out  your 
process  indefinitely  you  gain  time  enough  for  anything  to 
take  place,  but  too  much  for  anything  to  be  seen  :  in  the  very 
act  of  creating  the  evidence,  you  hide  it  all  away  :  and  the 
real  result  is  that  you  make  the  story  what  you  please,  and 
no  one  can  put  it  to  the  test  "  (page  365). 

•  Wasmann,  page  488.     See  also  Virchow's  Munich  Address. 

On  the  general  question  whether  any  one  species  develops  out  of 
another  it  is  not  within  our  province  to  speak  in  this  work.  It  is  well, 
however,  to  remember  that  the  possibility  of  transformation  of  one 
species  into  another  is  by  no  means  an  established  fact,  as  the  follow- 
ing testimony  from  Y.  Delage  ("  H6r6dit6,"  page  184)  makes  abun- 
dantly evident  :  "  Je  reconnais  .sans  peine  que  Ton  n'a  jamais  vu  une 
espfcce  en  cngcndrer  une  autre,  ni  se  transformer  eii  une  autre,  et 
que  Ton  n'a  aucune  observation  absolument  formelle  dd-niontrant  que 
Cfia  ait  jamais  eu  lieu." 

M.  Y.  Delage,  it  should  l>e  remembered,  is  an  Evolutionist. 

This  assumption,  however,  that  no  species  has  ever  been  known 
with  certainty  to  have  tU;v('lo]H(l  from  another,  though  nienlioncd 
here,  is,  as  wo  have  shown  above,  no  micssaiv  part  of  our  argument 
agaii.st  Evolutionary  Ethics. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  407 

Again,  on  the  argument  from  the  development  of  organism, 
he  writes :  "  The  evokition  theory  rests  mainly  on  the 
evidence  from  organisms  ;  and  when  they  have  been  duly 
disposed  in  the  probable  order  of  their  development,  their 
animating  instincts  and  functional  activities  are  obliged,  it 
is  supposed,  to  follow  suit ;  and  it  is  therefore  taken  for 
granted  rather  than  shown  that,  by  parallel  internal  history, 
the  most  rudimentary  animal  tendencies  have  transmuted 
themselves  into  the  attributes  of  a  moral  and  spiritual  nature. 
But  the  essential  difference  between  the  two  cases  must  not 
be  overlooked.  The  crust  of  the  earth  preserves  in  its  strata 
the  memorials  of  a  living  structure  in  an  order  which  cannot 
be  mistaken  .  .  .  but  .  .  .  the  fossil  organ  is  silent  about 
the  passion  that  stirred  it,  the  instinct  that  directed  it,  the 
precise  range  and  kind  of  consciousness  which  belonged  to 
its  possessor.  ...  To  a  certain  extent  there  is  no  doubt  a 
definite  and  known  relation  between  structure  and  function 
in  animals  enabling  you  from  the  presence  of  one  to  infer  the 
other.  ,  .  .  The  jaw,  the  teeth,  the  condyles  for  the  connected 
muscles  disclose  his  food  appetite,  and  his  modes  both  of 
pursuit  and  of  self-defence.  But  long  before  we  reach  the 
problem  which  engages  us  we  come  to  an  end  of  this  line  of 
inference.  There  are  no  bones,  or  muscles,  or  feathers  appro- 
priated to  the  exclusive  use  of  self-love  ;  no  additional  eye 
or  limb  set  apart  for  the  service  of  benevolence,  &c." 

{b)  It  will  probably  have  already  suggested  itself  to  th« 
reader  that  Spencer,  like  many  other  evolutionists,  mistakenly 
regards  the  serial  order  of  the  Universe  as  proof  that  the 
higher  has  been  developed  from  the  lower.  On  this  point  we 
have  the  following  interesting  criticism  from  M.  Henri 
Bergson  ("  L'Evolution  Creatrice,"  page  393)  : — 

"  Nous  n'avons  pas  a  entrer  dans  un  examen  approfondi  de 
.cette  philosophic.  Disons  simplement  que  I'artifice  ordinaire 
de  la  methode  de  Spencer  consiste  a  reconstituer  revolution 
avec  des  fragments  de  I'evolue.  Si  je  colle  une  image  sur  un 
carton  et  que  je  decoupe  ensuite  le  carton  en  morceaux  je 
pourrai,  en  groupant  comme  il  faut  les  petits  cartons  repro- 
duire  I'image,  Et  I'enfant  qui  travaille  ainsi  sur  les  pieces 
d'un  jeu  de  patience  .  .  .  s'imagine  sans  doute  avoir  pro- 
dnit  du  dessin  et  de  la  couleur.  .  .  .  Telle  est  pourtant 
I'illusion  de  Spencer.  II  prend  la  realite  sous  sa  forme 
actuelle,  il  la  brise,  il  I'eparpille  en  fragments  qu'il  jette  au 
vent ;  puis  il  '  integre  '  ces  fragments  et  il  en  dissipe  le 
mouvcment.  Ay  ant  imite  le  Tout  par  un  travail  de  mosaique, 
il  s'imagine  en  avoir  retrace  le  dessin  et  fait  la  genese." 


4o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(2)  Spencer's  Argument  from  Parallelism  between 
Development  of  Structure  and  Function,  on 
THE  ONE  Hand  and  Conduct  on  the  other — 
AN  Unsound  Argument.* 

Spencer  attempts  to  show  that  human  or  moral  con-- 
duct  is  nothing  more  than  highly-developed  animal  con- 
duct not  only  indirectly,  by  his  assumption  that  evolu- 
tion obtains  universally  in  the  world,  but  also  directly, 
by  showing  that  conduct  evolves  pa^i  passu  with  de- 
velopment of  structure  and  function.  This  argument 
we  have  already  drawn  out  at  considerable  length  in 
our  account  of  Spencer's  theory,  and  it  only  remains 
for  us  now  to  show  that  the  argument  is  unsound  and 
inconclusive.  Leaving  aside  all  minor  points,  we  shall 
here  call  the  attention  of  the  reader  to  that  portion 
of  Spencer's  argument  in  which  he  deals  with  what  he 
calls  emphatically  moral  conduct  (we  should  add,  "  and 
emphatically  human  conduct  ") — that  is,  conduct  which 
is,  in  the  admission  of  all  men,  moral,  as  opposed  to 
the  lower  kinds  of  conduct  which  not  all  would  admit 
to  be  moral.  In  treating  of  kinds  of  conduct  at  all 
Spencer's  aim  was  to  show  that  development  in  structure 
and  function  is  always  accompanied  by  development  of 
conduct,  and,  therefore,  by  a  nearer  and  nearer  approach 
in  animal  conduct  to  that  which  we  call  moral  conduct 
in  man.  This  parallelism,  he  claims,  is  clearly  seen  to 
hold  for  the  two  lowest  kinds  of  conduct  ;  for  animals* 
of  more  developed  structure  and  function  are  evidently 
better  able  to  maintain  their  own  lives  and  the  lives  of 
their  race  or  tribe  than  other  animals  are.  But  now  he 
comes  to  deal  with  conduct  that  is  "  emphatically 
moral  " — namely,  with  altruistic  conduct — and  here  he 
is  confronted  with  a  gap  in  the  supposed  evolutionary 
scries,  which  is  all  the  more  unfortunate  for  Spencer 

•  Some  excellent  remarks  on  tliis  part  of  Spencer's  llicory  arc  to 
be  found  in  a  scries  of  articles  in  the  Rcvuc  Nco-Scolastiquc  of  igoo,  by 
M.  J.  Hallcux.  This  chapter  was  fully  written  before  \vc  had  seen 
these  articles. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  409 

that  it  occurs  just  at  the  point  which  marks  the  be- 
ginning of  the  only  admittedly  moral  stage.  Animals  1 
of  more  highly-developed  structure  and  function  dol 
not  tend  to  the  more  altruistic  life — they  do  not  show) 
more  regard  for  the  peace  and  welfare  of  their  own  and 
other  tribes  than  do  »those  of  less  developed  structure/ 
and  function. 

This  is  the  fatal  gap  in  the  evolutionary  series,  a  gap 
which  there  is  no  denying.  It  is  a  vital  defect,  and  we 
are  quite  unable  to  see  how  any  defence  can  be  made 
for  it  in  the  Ethics  of  the  evolutionist.  And  we  would 
impress  on  the  reader  that  no  matter  what  else  Spencer 
may  now  achieve  in  his  work,  it  would  be  wrong  to 
forget  that  he  has  failed  to  establish  this  thesis  which 
he  set  out  to  prove — namely,  that  with  the  develop- 
ment of  structure  and  function  we  witness  a  nearer  and 
nearer  approach  amongst  the  animals  to  that  kind  of 
conduct  which  we  call  moral  in  men.  To  fail  in  this  is  to 
fail  in  the  only  vital  part  of  his  whole  evolutionary  system. 

But  more  remarkable  than  his  failure  to  establish  this 
parallelism  is  Spencer's  attempt  to  bolster  up  the  theory 
by  getting  moral  conduct  into  line  with  the  evolutionary 
series  through  the  law  of  "  association  " — a  point  to 
which  we  have  already  called  the  reader's  attention  in 
the  present  chapter,  (i)  He  tells  us  that  the  actual 
characteristics  of  the  higher  animals  are  not,  any  more 
than  in  the  lower,  those  of  regard  for  life  generally,  for 
peace,  and  for  the  helping  of  other  tribes  to  live.  From 
this  he  infers  (2)  that  "  there  is  room  for  modifications  " 
which  would  make  for  this  same  desire  for  peace  and 
for  altruistic  action.  Again,  he  tells  us  (3)  that  since 
regard  for  the  life  of  others  is  not  the  characteristic  of 
the  higher  animals,  we  are  led  "  by  association  "  to 
think  of  regard  for  life  as  their  characteristics.  From 
these  three  statements  as  premisses  he  deduces  the 
following  conclusion  :  "  That  the  highest  form  of  con- 
duct must  be  so  distinguished  (distinguished,  viz.,  by 
regard  for  life)  is  an  inevitable  implication."     No  such 


410  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

extraordinar}^  argument,  we  believe,  is  to  be  found  in 
the  history  of  Ethical  Science.  His  words  are — "  This 
imperfectly  evolved  conduct "  (that  is,  the  mutually 
antagonistic  conduct  of  the  higher  animals)  "  introduces 
us  hy  association  to  conduct  that  is  perfectly  evolved. 
Contemplating  these  adjustments  .of  acts  to  ends  which 
miss  completeness,  because  they  cannot  be  made  by 
one  creature  without  other  creatures  being  prevented 
from  making  them,  raises  the  thought  of  adjustments  such 
that  each  creature  may  make  them  without  preventing 
them  from  being  made  by  other  creatures.  That  the 
highest  form  of  conduct  must  be  so  distinguished  is  an 
inevitable  implication,  for  while  the  form  "  {i.e.,  the 
actual  form  of  conduct  of  the  animals  referred  to)  "  of 
conduct  is  such  that  adjustment  of  acts  to  ends  by  some 
necessitates  non-adjustment  by  others,  there  remains 
room  for  modifications  which  bring  conduct  into  a  form 
avoiding  this  and  so  making  the  totality  of  life  greater  " 
("  Data  of  Ethics  "  page  i8).  We  must  remember  that 
Spencer  is  here  attempting  to  show  that  the  end  of  the 
whole  evolutionary  process  and  of  moral  conduct  is 
"  life."  To  do  this  he  undertakes  to  show  that  develop- 
ment of  structure  and  function  runs  parallel  with 
development  in  the  power  of  maintaining  life.  But 
here  we  find  the  higher  animals  not  characterised  by  any 
particular  desire  to  maintain  life  in  the  two  ways  which, 
according  to  Spencer,  are  most  "  emphatically  moral." 
and  he  contends  that  these  two  ways  of  maintaining 
life  must  therefore  be  characteristic  of  the  highest  animals. 
Might  we  not  as  well  argue  that  because  the  higher 
animals  do  evince  a  greater  care  in  the  maintenance  of 
the  life  of  their  young,  and  since  greater  care  suggests 
hy  association  less  care,  therefore  the  highest  animals 
neglect  their  young  ?  Had  Spencer  already  proved  that 
life  was  the  end,  we  might  then  take  it  for  granted, 
without  having  recourse  to  this  very  extraordinary 
argument,  that  the  highest  animals  must  have  a  regard 
for  life  generally  in  all  its  forms.     But  he  has  not  proved 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  411 

that  life  is  the  end.  That  is  the  very  point  which  he 
has  here  set  out  to  prove  ;  and  the  argument  drawn 
from  association  is  necessary  to  the  chain  of  proof. 
His  argument  is,  therefore,  not  only  illogical  and  un- 
convincing, it  is  contradictory  in  its  very  terms.* 

Everything,  therefore,  in  Spencer's  Ethical  system 
that  follows  this  extraordinary  argument  (it  occurs 
early  in  the  book,  and  is,  as  we  said,  essential  to  the 
chain  of  reasoning  by  which  he  attempts  to  connect 
evolution  with  morals)  is  vitiated  by  his  failure  at  this 
point ;  and  without  proceeding  further  with  our  argu- 
ment against  the  theory  of  Biological  Evolution,  we 
might  on  this  account  alone  regard  his  evolutionary 
system  as  a  failure  in  its  argument  and  its  conclusions. 
We  shall  now,  however,  examine  some  of  these  con- 
clusions in  greater  detail — namely,  those  that  concern 
the  end  of  human  action  and  the  moral  criterion. 

(3)  Is  Life  Man's  Ultimate  End  ? 

We  shall  in  this  section  consider  Herbert  Spencer's 
principle  that  the  end  of  man  is  the  attainment  of  the 
maximum  of  life.  This  principle  he  attempts  to  prove 
from  a  supposed  law  of  nature — the  law,  namely,  that 
the  higher  we  mount  up  in  the  scale  of  animal  existence 
the  greater  the  quantity  of  life  attained.  "  Along,"  he 
writes,  "  with  greater  elaboration  of  life  produced  by 
pursuit  of  more  numerous  ends,  there  goes  that  increased 
duration  of  life  which  constitutes  the  supreme  end  " 
(page  14  "  Data  ").  Let  us  see  whether  Spencer's  prin- 
ciple on  this  point  is  true.  Can  Spencer  really  maintain 
that  along  with  the  pursuit  of  more  numerous  ends  (the 
pursuit  of  more  numerous  ends  being  the  mark  of  the 

*  Spencer  several  times  returns  to  this  point,  which  seems  to  have 
troubled  him  exceedingly.  He  tells  us  (page  -i^})  that  "  there  are 
inferior  species  displaying  considerable  degrees  of  sociality."  But 
this,  of  course,  would  not  prove  that  along  with  development  of 
structure  and  function  there  goes  increased  care  for  the  lives  of  others. 
He  also  maintains  that  sociality  accompaiiits  increased  civilisation, 
a  theory  which  many  Evolutionisls  deny. 


41^  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS, 

higher  animals)  there  goes  always  either  increased 
duration  or  increased  quantity  of  life  ?  As  regards 
length  of  life,  it  is  certain  that  no  such  law  obtains. 
The  elephant,  for  instance,  lives  longer  than  the  man, 
though  lower  in  the  line  of  organism.  Some  insects 
more  highly  organised  than  many  of  the  larger  animals 
live  but  a  moment. 

Then,  again,  as  to  quantity  of  life,  Herbert  Spencer 
maintains  that  the  higher  the  animal  the  more  the  life 
that  is  lived  each  moment — "  the  sum  of  vital  activities 
during  any  given  interval  is  greater  in  the  case  of  man." 
This  we  cannot  grant.  Man  exerts  a  greater  number  of 
kinds  of  activities  than  the  animals,  but  he  does  not  put 
forth  more  vital  energy.  For  instance,  the  dog  or  the 
eagle  puts  forth  more  vital  activity  during  one  of  its 
ordinary  waking  hours  than  do  most  men.  Nor  can  it 
be  said  that  the  intellectual  activity  of  the  man  counts 
for  more  than  the  sense  activity  of  the  dog  or  the  eagle. 
Intellectual  activity  may  be  qualitatively  higher,  but  it 
certainly  is  not  quantitatively  greater  than  the  activity 
of  any  lower  faculty.  Intellect,  therefore,  does  not  con- 
tribute more  to  the  sum  of  vital  energy  expended.  But 
in  Spencer's  theory  quantity  is  the  only  characteristic 
taken  account  of.  "  Maximum  "  means  that  which  is 
"  quantitatively  greatest."  We  claim,  therefore,  that  it 
is  neither  evident  nor  true  that  the  sum  of  the  vital 
activities  is  greater  in  the  case  of  the  higher  animals. 

The  distinction,  however,  which  we  have  just  drawn 
between  quality  and  quantity  of  vital  activity  suggests 
to  us  the  true  theory  of  the  end  of  man  and  the  conclu- 
sion to  which  Spencer's  premisses  should  really  lead  in 
so  far  as  they  may  be  supposed  to  lead  anywhere. 
Development  of  structure  and  function  is  certainly 
accompanied  by  advance,  not  in  the  amount  of  vital 
activity  that  is  put  forth,  but  in  the  quality  of  the 
activity.  And  because  development  in  structure  and 
function  is  so  accompanied,  therefore  we  maintain  that 
the  end  of  man  must  be  to  attain  to  the  highest  exercise 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  413 

of  his  highest  faculty — i.e.,  the  facuUy  of  Reason,  or  to 
the  exercise  of  Reason  in  regard  to  its  highest  object  in 
the  most  perfect  life.  Not  quantity  of  life,  therefore, 
but  the  qualitatively  highest  act  of  life  will,  if  Spencer's 
premisses  are  true,  be  our  highest  end.  And  this  is  the 
Aristotelian  definition  of  man's  last  end — the  highest 
act  of  intelligence  in  a  perfect  life.  In  this  sense  life 
may  be  held  to  be  man's  end.*  St.  Thomas  is  interesting 
on  the  point  :  "  Life,"  he  tells  us,  "  may  be  understood 
in  a  two-fold  sense — first,  as  the  living  being  itself 
{ipsum  esse  viventis,  including,  therefore,  the  principle 
of  life),  and  in  that  sense  life  is  not  the  end,  for  no  man 
is  his  own  end.  .  .  .  Secondly,  the  vital  operation  by 
which  the  principle  of  life  is  reduced  to  act,  and  in  that 
sense  life  ...  is  our  end."  |  He  adds  that  our 
highest  vital  operation  is  to  know  God. 

Spencer  was,  therefore,  wrong  in  regarding  the 
maximum  of  life  as  our  final  end.  Of  course  it  is 
possible  to  understand  the  "  maximum  of  life  "  in  such 
a  sense  as  to  make  it  identical  with  that  of  the  highest 
act  of  life.  It  is  possible,  for  instance,  that  Spencer 
would  regard  the  lower  operations  as  of  practically  no 
account  in  comparison  with  the  higher.  But  we  do  not 
think  that  this  is  Spencer's  meaning,  since  he  is  all 
through  insisting  on  the  quantity  of  life  attainable.  If, 
however,  "  maximum  of  life "  means  "  highest  vital 
operation,"  then  we  can  only  say  that  Evolution  has 
led  us  to  no  new  conclusion.  It  is  only  Aristotelianism 
in  a  new  garb. 

(4)  On   Adjustment  to   Environment  as   Criterion 
OF  THE  Good 

It  is  not  always  easy  to  say  from  a  perusal  of  Spencer's 
work  what  precisely  is  the  part  played  by  "  adaptation 
to  environment  "  in  his  system.  Passages  could  be  pro- 
duced from  his  works  in  which  adaptation  to  environment 

*  That  is,  our  final  subjective  end 
\  1^,  He.,  Q.  HI.,  Art.  2. 


414  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

seems  to  be  regarded  as  the  end  of  all.  But  in  other 
passages  he  seems  to  regard  it  rather  as  the  essential 
means  to  the  attainment  of  the  final  end.  And,  indeed, 
in  the  "  Data  of  Ethics  "  so  strongly  does  he  insist  that 
the  end  is  Life  that  we  believe  that  this  second  is  the 
proper  interpretation — that  "  adaptation  to  environ- 
ment "  is  regarded  as  the  one  essential  means  for  the 
attainment  of  fulness  of  life  in  length  and  in  breadth, 
and  that  it  is  in  order  to  secure  better  adaptation,  and, 
through  this,  greater  life,  that  the  higher  animals  are 
endowed  with  greater  complexity  in  structure  and 
function.  This,  also,  is  the  view  taken  of  Spencer's 
work  by  Sorle3\*  In  Spencer's  system,  he  tells  us, 
adaptation  to  environment  is  connected  with  the  end, 
which  is  self-preservation,  as  "  essential  means."  And 
again  (speaking  of  Spencer's  system),  he  describes  the 
end  as  "  self-preservation  as  interpreted  by  adaptation." 

But  in  biological  Ethics  adaptation  to  environment  is 
not  the  only  criterion  of  what  acts  are  life-maintaining. 
"  Pleasure  "  and  "  health  "  are  also  used  as  criteria,  and 
Leslie  Stephen  states  explicitly  that  the  difference  be- 
tween the  utilitarian  and  the  evolutionist  criterion  is 
that  "  the  one  lays  down  as  a  criterion  the  happiness, 
the  other  the  health,  of  Society."  f 

Now,  these  three  factors  of  the  evolutionary  process, 

*  "  Ethics  of  Naturalism." 

f  "  Science  of  Ethics,"  page  366.  We  have  some  difficulty  in 
reconciling  this  statement  of  Leslie  Stephen's,  that  the  evolutionist 
docs  not  make  happiness  the  criterion  of  good  action,  with  some  ex- 
pressions of  Spencer,  who,  like  Leslie  Stephen  himself,  is  certainly  to 
be  regarded  as  an  evolutionist.  In  his  letter  to  Mill,  Spencer  speaks 
of  happiness  not  merely  as  criterion,  but  even  as  the  end  of  all  action. 
In  the  "  Data  of  Ethics  "  he  represents  life  as  the  end,  and  pleasure 
as,  at  least,  a  criterion.  Leslie  Stephen's  assertion,  therefore,  is 
Hcarccly  true.  But  it  contains  some  truth.  For  in  the  evolutionary 
system  happiness  may  be  regarded  as  a  remoter  criterion,  health  as  a 
more  proximate.  In  the  utilitarian  theory,  on  the  other  hand, 
happiness  is  the  more  proximate.  But  how  shall  we  reconcile  those 
passages  in  Spencer  whicli  represent  at  one  time  happiness  as  the 
end  and  at  aiiotiier  time  as  means  only  to  life  ?  One  mode  of  recon- 
ciliation would  be  to  say  that  life  in  Spencer's  theory  is  valuable 
because  it  is  essentially  pleasurable.  Another  (and  perhaps  better) 
possible  mode  of  reconciliation  may  be  found  in  the  distinction  drawn 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  415 

though  very  different  in  idea,  are  all  closely  related  in 
the  evolutionist  system— adjustment  to  environment, 
health,  and  life — and,  therefore,  it  is  not  surprising  to 
find  that  the  precise  relation  they  severally  bear  to 
Ethics  is  not  always  clearly  indicated.  But  we  are 
safe  at  all  events  in  declaring  that  in  the  Ethics  of 
Biological  Evolution  "  adaptation  to  environment  "  is 
at  least  a  prominent  criterion  of  good,  since  it  is  at 
least  a  necessary  means  to  the  final  end,  and,  therefore, 
we  shall  in  the  present  section  say  what  is  to  be  thought 
of  adjustment  to  environment  as  a  criterion  of  good 
conduct.  In  the  next  we  shall  say  something  on 
"  health  "  as  criterion. 

(a)  We  must,  in  the  first  place,  admit  that  adaptation 
to  the  world  around  us  is  in  some  sense  a  criterion  of 
good.  It  is  certainly  a  negative  criterion  in  the  sense 
that  conduct  that  puts  the  whole  world  at  sixes  and 
sevens  can  scarcely  be  good  or  natural  conduct.  The 
natural  is  always  harmonious  and  in  the  main  happiness- 
producing,  and,  therefore,  its  essential  effect  is  not  dis- 
turbance, but  rather  rest,  adjustment,  and  equilibrium. 
Again,  adjustment  to  our  environment  is  in  some  sense 
a  positive  criterion  of  good,  for  man  has  a  duty  to  strive 
to  accommodate  himself  to  his  surroundings,  to  respect 
the  rights  and  views  of  other  men  and  to  seek  their  good. 
For  every  man  has  much  to  learn  and  a  great  deal  to 
gain  from  his  social  environment — he  owes  much  to  it, 
and  should  strive  to  make  it  some  return.  And  even  if 
we  had  nothing  to  gain  from  the  world  it  is  necessaiy 
that  we  adapt  ourselves  to  the  tone,  and  in  a  certain 
sense  to  the  ideals,  of  the  age  we  live  in,  and  in  many 
cases  these  ideals  may  even  give  rise  to  important  moral 
laws  and  duties. 

(b)  But  when  we  have  said  all  this,  there  still  remains 

by  Leslie  Stephen  between  the  cause  of  morality  and  its  reason.  The 
cause  would '  correspond  to  the  natural  end  of  action,  the  end  which 
nature  intends.  This  is  life.  The  reason  of  morality  would  corre- 
spontl  to  the  constant  individual  motive  or  end  of  action,  which  on 
both  theories  (that  of  Spencer  and  of  Leslie  Stephen)  is  happiness. 


4i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  important  consideration  that  adaptation  to  environ- 
ment is  not  a  man's  whole  good,  nor  a  criterion  of  all 
human  good,  and  that  sometimes  it  is  even  positively 
evil.  It  is  not  the  universal  criterion  of  good,  for  many 
acts  are  good  and  many  are  bad  independently  of  their 
relation  to  environment.  Study  is  a  good  act,  and 
private  immorality  is  bad,  even  though  these  acts  may 
have  no  relation  to  social  environment.  Often,  too,  it  is 
positively  evil  to  adapt  one's  self  to  environment,  for 
though  to  adapt  one's  self  to  a  good  environment  may 
be  good,  to  adapt  one's  self  to  a  bad  environment  is 
bad.  In  fact,  universal  adaptation  to  environment, 
whether  good  or  bad,  always  includes  some  evil  ;  be- 
cause our  social  environment  is  made  up  of  individuals, 
and  since  every  individual  has  in  him  some  downward 
tendencies  it  follows  that  environment  (which  is  simply 
the  sum  of  a  number  of  co-existent  individuals)  must 
also  have  downward  tendencies,  and,  therefore,  unless 
some  refuse  to  accommodate  themselves  to  environment 
the  whole  environment  must  gradually  become  debased 
in  tone.  It  is  obvious,  both  from  experience  and  from 
common  sense,  that  7nere  adaptation  as  a  principle  of 
conduct  must  necessarily  mean  "  drift  "  and  inactivity, 
and  perhaps  even  all-round  degeneracy. 

Again,  the  final  standard  of  morals  cannot  lie  in  our 
environment,  since  our  final  end — the  perfect  good — lies 
altogether  outside  of  our  environment.  Were  our 
environment  to  disappear,  our  final  end  would  still 
remain,  and  the  moral  standard  should  consequently 
still  be  a  reality. 

Finally,  the  theory  of  adaptation  as  criterion  of  good 
is  simply  an  analogy  built  upon  the  biological  laws  of 
the  relation  of  cell  to  tissue  in  the  living  body,  and 
like  all  other  analogies  it  may  easily  be,  and  often  is, 
carried  beyond  the  legitimate  limits.  A  cell  must  ad- 
just itself  to  its  surroundings  because  it  has  no  end  of 
its  own  beyond  the  good  of  the  whole  bod3\  But  the 
individual  man  is  not  like  a  cell  in  the  social  organism. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  417 

He  is  to  a  large  extent  an  independent  unit,  and,  as  we 
have  said,  his  final  end  is  not  the  good  of  society. 
Hence,  the  analogy  of  the  cell  in  this  connection  is 
misleading  and  unjustifiable.  It  may,  indeed,  be  used 
for  purposes  of  illustration.  But  even  then  it  should 
not  be  forgotten  that  if  a  cell  must  adapt  itself  to  its 
environment  it  must  do  so  only  when  its  environment  is 
a  good  one,  adjustment  to  a  decaying  environment  being 
rather  a  cause  of  degeneration  than  of  good.  We  should 
remember,  also,  that,  even  in  Biology,  adaptation  is 
not  the  sole  criterion  of  well-being.  The  eye  has  a 
certain  individuality  of  its  own,  and  its  perfection  or 
imperfection  is  not  determined  solely  or  principally  by 
the  degree  of  adjustment  to  its  environment  which  it 
attains,  but  rather  by  its  own  intrinsic  structure  and 
health.  So,  also,  adaptation  is  not  the  supreme  or  the 
sole  criterion  of  the  individual  good. 

(5)  Health  as  Criterion  of  Morality 

(a)  As  we  have  seen,  many  Biological  Evolutionists 
regard  health  as  the  only  sure  criterion  of  moral  good. 
Now,  if  health  means  the  health  of  the  body  only,  it 
certainly  is  not  the  criterion  of  morality,  since  so  much 
of  our  life  transcends  the  body,  and  common  sense 
would  describe  the  healthy  condition  of  the  individual 
as  7nens  sana  in  corpore  sano.  But  if  this  be  the 
criterion,  we  meet  at  once  the  difficulty  of  determining 
what  is  meant  by  mental  health.  If  it  means  a  mind 
which  tends  to  truthfulness,  to  justice,  and  in  general 
to  goodness,  then  the  theory  that  health  is  a  criterion 
of  goodness  is  little  better  than  a  tautology.  If,  on  the 
other  hand,  it  means  a  clever  mind,  sharp,  intellectual, 
resolute,  &c.,  then  we  can  hardly  see  how  one  can  speak 
of  good  conduct  as  necessarily  promoting  health,  for  we 
are  quite  sure  that  some  kinds  of  good  conduct  do  not 
tend  to  make  the  race  sharper  or  more  intellectual,  and 
some  evil  kinds  have  no  tendency  to  make  it  duller  or 
less  receptive. 
VoL  I — 27 


4i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

But  health  of  mind  may  be  understood  in  another 
sense.  A  healthy  mind  may  mean  a  mind  that  can  best 
fulfil  its  highest  functions,  just  as  a  healthy  body  is  that 
body  which  can  best  fulfil  its  proper  functions.  If 
health  in  this  sense  be  the  criterion,  then  we  are  back 
again  to  Aristotelianism,  with  just  this  difference  that 
what  is  in  the  Aristotelian  philosophy  represented  as 
the  subjective  end  of  man  is  here  made  the  criterion  of 
good.  But,  then,  the  question  arises — how  are  we  to 
know  whether  any  course  of  conduct  is  healthy  or  un- 
healthy in  the  sense  explained,  and,  therefore,  good  or 
bad  ?  Aristotle's  way  is  simple  enough.  He  determines 
empirically  what  acts  are  natural,  and  these  he  declares 
must  lead  to  the  last  end,  to  the  highest  function. 
Spencer  may  adopt  the  same  criterion,  and  then  the 
criterion  of  right  and  wrong  is  nature — not  health. 
Or  he  may  determine  what  acts  are  healthy  (that  is, 
will  lead  to  proper  functioning)  by  the  beneficial  or 
injurious  effects  of  actions  on  the  race,  and  then  his 
criterion  is  simply  utihtarian,  whereas  Spencer's  philo- 
sophy was  meant  to  supersede  Utilitarianism. 

However,  we  will  suppose  that  in  some  way  or  other 
Spencer  is  able  to  determine  the  conditions  of  the  health 
of  the  social  organism — that  is,  that  he  is  able  to  deter- 
mine from  the  laws  or  the  conditions  of  life  what  acts 
are  healthy  and  what  are  not,  and  the  question  then 
arises,  how  far  are  we  going  to  apply  this  criterion  in 
the  determining  of  moral  conduct  ?  Now,  an  ethical 
theory  or  an  ethical  criterion  must  stand  the  test  of 
being  applied  as  a  universal  rule.  And  when  we  apply 
universally  the  criterion  of  the  health  of  society  we 
arrive  at  a  conclusion  that  clearly  follows  from  it,  but 
which  places  our  argument  in  a  position  which  is  the 
negation  of  all  Ethics.  For  if  the  health  of  the  social 
organism  be  our  primary  criterion  we  must  apply  it  in 
every  case,  and  consequently  we  must  not  spare  and 
maintain  in  life  the  old  and  infirm,  the  stupid  and  the 
ill-conditioned,    whose   only   effect   upon   Society   is   to 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  419 

weaken  its  fibre,  to  destroy,  as  Leslie  Stephen  would 
say,  "  the  social  tissue."  If  health  be  the  criterion, 
then  the  proper  directing  of  the  struggle  for  existence 
would  involve  the  weeding  out  of  all  that  takes  the 
place  of  good,  healthy  growth  ;  and  as,  in  a  limited 
world,  the  old  and  weak  and  the  stupid  are  often  in  the 
way  of  healthy  growth  or  of  progress,  their  only  fate 
must  be  extermination.  However,  we  believe  that  the 
common  sense  of  the  world  would  revolt  against  the 
evident  injustice  of  such  procedure,  and  it  would  revolt 
also,  if  logical,  against  the  Ethical  system  which  authorises 
such  procedure.  Hence  Huxley's  remark — "  Since  law 
and  morals  are  restrainers  upon  the  struggle  for  existence 
between  man  and  society,  the  ethical  process  is  in  opposi- 
tion to  the  principle  of  the  cosmic  process  "  (that  is,  the 
evolutionary  process,  based  on  the  law  of  the  "  survival 
of  the  Fittest  "  *).  And  again —  "  It  (Ethics)  repudiates 
the  gladiatorial  theory  of  existence."  We  repeat — if 
the  health  of  society  be  the  only  criterion,  then  the 
gladiatorial  theory  of  existence — that  is,  the  theory  of 
the  struggle  for  existence — becomes  a  necessity  ;  and 
since  the  struggle  for  existence  is  mainly  a  struggle  in 
which  the  weak  are  worsted,  then  it  becomes  our  duty 
forcibly  and  unhesitatingly  to  send  "  life's  disinherited 
and  condemned  ones  "  (as  Nietzsche  f  terms  them)  to 
destruction,  seeing  that  they  only  stand  in  the  way  of 

*  We  should,  in  fairness  to  Spencer,  remark  that  he  has  expressly 
repudiated  the  interpretation  which  some  ethicians  have  put  upon  the 
expression  "  survival  of  the  fittest  " — namely,  that  it  means  "  survival 
of  the  strongest."  By  "  fittest,"  he  explains  ("  Collected  Essays," 
!•)  379)>  is  meant  "  those  who  are  constitutionally  fittest  to  thrive 
under  the  conditions  in  which  they  are  placed,  and  very  often  that 
which,  humanly  speaking,  is  inferiority,  causes  the  survival."  We 
need  not  sa}^  however,  that  the  criticism  given  in  the  text  still  holds 
in  spite  of  this  explanation.  If  the  health  of  the  social  organism  is 
the  criterion,  why  should  dangerous  individuals  survive  ? 

t  Huxley's  view  of  the  opposition  of  the  Ethical  process  and  the 
Cosmic  process  is  also  set  out  by  Nietzsche.  "  Sympathy,"  he  writes 
"  thwarts  on  the  whole,  in  general,  the  law  of  development,  which  is 
the  law  of  selection.  It  preserves  what  is  ripe  for  extinction  ;  it 
resists  in  favour  of  life's  disinherited  and  condemned  ones.  It  gives 
to  life  a  gloomy  and  questionable  aspect  by  the  abundance  of  the  ill- 
conditioned  whom  it  maintains  in  life.'- 


420  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

healthy  progress.  We  may,  then,  consider  the  apphca- 
tion  of  such  a  test  as  the  heahh  of  the  social  organism 
to  morality  as  a  redudio  ad  ahsurdum  of  the  Ethics  of 
Biological  Evolution. 

Note. — "  It  may  be  well  at  this  point  to  consider  what  is 
the  best  answer  which,  in  our  view,  might  be  made  to  the 
above  line  of  reasoning  consistently  with  the  Spencerian 
doctrine  of  Ethics.  Our  argument  is  that  if  the  health  of 
the  social  organism  is  either  the  fundamental  criterion  or  the 
end  of  good  human  action,  then  it  would  be  impossible  to 
defend  our  maintaining  or  allowing  to  be  maintained  in  life 
those  individuals  whose  physical  condition  is  necessarily  a 
cause  of  danger  and  even  of  actual  evil  to  the  social  organism. 

To  this  we  can  conceive  a  philosopher  of  the  Spencerian 
school  replying  in  either  of  the  three  following  ways  :  He 
might  say  with  Spencer  that  "  the  character  of  the  aggregate 
is  determined  by  the  characters  of  the  units  "  ("  Studies  in 
Sociology  ")  ;  and  from  this  he  might  draw  the  conclusion 
that  in  order  to  secure  the  welfare  of  the  social  organism  it 
is  necessary  to  secure  the  welfare  of  the  units  that  make  it 
up,  and  that  consequently  it  would  not  be  lawful  to  kill  off 
units  simply  for  the  sake  of  the  organism.  Now,  this  reply, 
we  maintain,  at  once  gets  rid  of  the  difficulty  and  the  system 
of  which  it  is  a  difficulty ;  for  we  suppose  a  case  in  which 
the  social  welfare  is  actually  and  certainly  impaired  by  the 
maintaining  in  life  of  a  particular  individual,  and  if  the 
welfare  of  such  an  individual  is  to  be  considered  before  the 
welfare  of  the  social  organism,  then  the  health  of  the  social 
organism  is  not  the  end  of  good  conduct,  nor  the  criterion 
of  good. 

Secondly,  we  may  be  told  that  though  the  health  of  the 
social  organism  is  the  criterion  of  good,  still  there  are  certain 
laws  and  beliefs  which  are  ultimate,  and  a  priori,  "  having 
(their)  origin  in  the  experiences  of  the  race,"  that  these 
a  priori  laws  simply  must  be  accepted  as  a  starting  point  in 
all  Ethical  reasoning,  that  Justice  (as  Spencer  insists)  is  one 
of  these  a  priori  laws  and  that  the  law  of  Justice  is  the  law 
of  the  "  equal  freedom  of  all  men  "  (see  Spencer's  "  Justice," 
page  6i).  Now,  this  reply  we  should  have  no  difficulty  in 
accepting,  provided  it  be  also  admitted  that  between  this 
Spencerian  theory  of  the  ground  of  Justice  and  the  theory 
that  the  health  of  the  social  organism  is  the  primary  ethical 
criterion  there  is  an  irreconcilable  antagonism,  which  like 
the  first  reply  is  tantamount  to  a  denial  of  the  Evolutionary 
system  altogether  in  so  far  as  it  bears  on  Ethics.    We  are. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  421 

as  we  said,  quite  willing  to  accept  Spencer's  a  priori  view  of 
Justice  and  his  theory  of  the  rights  of  individuals  for  the 
sake  of  argument,  but  our  question  is^ — how  is  this  view  to 
be  reconciled  with  the  theory  that  the  health  of  the  social 
organism  is  the  criterion  of  "  good  "  ?  * 

A  third  possible  reply  is  that  unless  in  general  there  was 
an  understanding  that  men  when  they  become  old  and  infirm 
will  be  protected,  the  social  organism  could  not  develop, 
since  a  feeling  of  security  is  a  necessary  condition  of  all  true 
systematic  progress.  To  this  argument  our  reply  is  as 
follows  :  We  quite  admit  that  the  welfare  of  society  could 
not  be  maintained  unless  there  was  a  general  understanding 
that  the  units  would  be  secure  against  aggression  when 
infirmity  had  come  upon  them.  But  in  Ethics  we  have  to 
do  with  individual  actions,  and  our  present  question  is — 
granted  the  general  understanding  of  security,  still  if  in  an 
individual  case  the  ethician  were  asked  in  the  seclusion  of 
his  study  whether  it  was  not  his  duty,  let  us  say  as  a  legis- 
lator, to  obviate  danger  by  removing  a  certain  individual  he 
would  not  be  bound  to  answer  in  the  affirmative,  and  remove 
the  individual.  It  will  be  said  that  the  proper  answer  in 
this  case  would  be  that  a  man  should  stick  to  his  public 
assurances  and  save  the  life  of  him  to  whom  protection  was 
guaranteed  :  and  with  that  contention  we  fully  sympathise. 
Still  this  view  of  the  case  is  not  without  its  strange  and 
awkward  possibilities.  For  it  is  possible  that  by  keeping  a 
certain  diseased  individual  in  life  the  whole  community 
might  catch  the  contagion  and  disappear,  and  our  point  is — 
should  we  still  protect  the  unit  and  let  the  rest  of  the  com- 
munity go,  remembering  all  the  time  that  the  good  of  the 
community  is  the  criterion  of  right  conduct  and  the  end 
and  purpose  of  the  individual  life  ?  If  we  answer  in  the 
affirmative,  then  the  present  criterion  is  to  our  mind  utterly 
and  hopelessly  negatived  by  our  answer.  If  in  the  negative, 
what    about    the    individual    right  ?     We    have    of    course 


•  A  follower  of  Spencer  might  answer  the  above,  saying  that, 
though  at  present  justice  to  the  individual  is  not  always  best  for  the 
Social  Organism,  in  the  state  of  "  absolute  good  "  it  shall  be  best — 
"  The  requirements  of  Absolute  Ethics,"  says  Sp.,  "  can  be  wholly 
conformed  to  only  in  a  state  of  permanent  peace."  But  really  it  is 
absurd  to  expect  us  to  content  ourselves  every  time  that  we  point 
out  a  weakness  in  this  and  the  other  Evolutionary  systems  by  con- 
sidering that  the  criterion  in  question  does  not  work  well  at  the  present 
moment  but  that  some  day  it  will  be  found  to  work.  After  all  Ethics 
is  of  very  little  value  as  a  science  if  it  cannot  deal  satisfactorily  with 
present  conditions. 


422  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

selected  an  extreme  case.     But  a  fundamental  moral  theory 
should  apply  to  every  case.* 

(6)  Concerning  the  criterion  afforded  by  the  health  of 
Society  just  one  point  remains — the  eternal  difficulty  of 
the  individual  act.  If  health  be  the  criterion  of  morality 
and  the  promotion  of  life  the  end,  then  the  act  that 
makes  now  for  the  life  of  the  social  organism  is  good 
and  that  which  impairs  the  vitality  of  the  social  organ- 
ism is  bad.  Now,  some  acts  must  always  have  the 
same  effect  on  the  health  of  society  no  matter  what  be 
the  circumstances  under  which  they  are  performed,  like 
the  murder  of  people  who  are  innocent.  Such  an  act 
must  impair  the  health  of  the  bod}'  politic  and  lower  its 
vitality.  But  of  other  acts  the  effects  are  very  variable, 
and  these  acts  must  present  a  great  difficulty  to  the 
evolutionist  ethician.  For  instance,  lies  and  injustice 
often  do  more  good  than  harm,  if  good  and  harm  are 
to  be  judged  by  effects  only,  and  still  we  speak  of  lies 
and  injustice  as  always  bad.  This  difficulty  is,  indeed, 
so  obvious  that  no  theory  can  afford  to  overlook  it  or 
to  treat  it  lightly,  and  the  reader  may  be  interested  in 
the  following  solution  of  it — a  solution  which  is  given 
by  Herbert  Spencer,  and  which  is  regarded  by  some  as 
one  of  the  most  important  points  of  his  ethical  theory. 
He  maintains  that  in  a  perfect  state,  and  under  the  rule 
of  an  "  absolute  Ethics,"  truth  and  justice  would  bring 
as  effects  pleasure  and  health  only  ;  but  that  in  our 
present  state  these  normal  and  natural  effects  are  pre- 
vented by  circumstances  from  realising  themselves,  find 
that,  so,  we  often  find  bad  actions  leading  to  pleasure 
and  good  acts  to  pain.  He  tells  us,  however,  that 
though  in  our  present  life  it  is  not  easy  to  know  whether 
the  particular  act  impairs  health  or  promotes  it,  we 
ought  at  the  same  time  to  be  guided  by  what  follows 
normally  from  these  acts,   and  that  in  following  these 

•  On  this  question  of  the  relation  of  the  individual  to  Society  in 
Sfxrnci;r'.s  theory  \v(>  wouUl  recommend  the  reading  of  Cairne's  articles 
in  the  Fortnightly  Review  (1875)  — "  Mr.  Sp.;ncer  on  Social  Evolution." 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  423 

rules  we  shall  be  following  "  courses  which  tend  most  in 
the  direction  of  the  normal  "  ("  Data,"  page  277). 

But  is  not  all  this  very  unsatisfactory  ?  Nobody 
could  rationally  expect  that  a  fundamental  moral 
criterion  should  be  easy  of  application  in  every  case. 
But  it  is  not  too  much  to  ask  that  a  moral  criterion, 
and  in  particular  the  fundamental  moral  criterion, 
should  be  capable  of  affording  plain  and  certain  infor- 
mation on  most  individual  acts.  Yet,  according  to 
Spencer,  the  best  information  which  this  criterion  is 
capable  of  affording  is  that  in  our  present  state  certain 
acts  will  probably  injure  or  further  life,  and  that  under 
other  conditions — in  the  ideal  state — they  would  cer- 
tainly  injure  or  further  it.  Now,  in  reference  to  this  last 
statement  of  Spencer's,  we  have  no  hesitation  in  saying, 
first,  that  a  criterion  that  can  in  most  individual  cases 
afford  no  more  than  a  high  degree  of  probability  is  not 
and  cannot  be  the  fundamental  criterion.  And  secondly, 
though  it  may  be  that  in  the  ideal  state  bad  acts  will 
injure,  still  as  a  rational  being  with  present  responsi- 
bilities I  am  interested  not  in  an  ideal  future  state  but 
in  the  present  actual  state,  and  it  is  no  use  telling  me 
what  the  moral  quality  of  an  act  would  be  in  such  a 
future  state  *  when  an  action  is  to  be  done  here  and 
now.     Hence,  we  must  regard  this  theory  as  useless  and 

•  We  know  of  no  evolutionist  who  has  approached  this  question 
of  individual  action  with  more  candour  than  Leslie  Stephen.  He 
insists,  as  we  do,  that  it  is  idle  for  the  utilitarian  or  the  evolutionist 
to  ignore  the  accidental  and  concrete  circumstances  and  effects.  If 
acts  are  good  by  promoting  the  general  vitality  then,  even  though  as 
a  rule  a  certain  act  impairs  vitality,  yet  let  it  only  in  this  case  promote 
the  general  vitality,  and  he  "  cannot  see  in  what  sense  it  is  morally 
blameworthy.  To  adhere  to  the  (general)  rule  when  the  rule  clearly 
docs  not  apply  is  not  to  be  moral  but  a  moral  pedant  "  (page  392). 
He  admits  that  this  is  an  awkward  consequence  for  the  evolutionary 
ethician,  this  .setting  aside  of  the  general  laws.  But  he  claims  that 
the  ethician  will  simply  have  to  be  satisfied  with  the  situation.  No 
general  laws  that  we  can  make  will,  he  admits,  cover  the  morality  of 
particular  cases.  What,  then,  are  we  ethiciains  to  do  in  the  case  of 
( oncrete  action — we,  whose  business  it  is  to  direct  other  people's 
conduct  ?  We  must,  Leslie  Stephen  tells  us,  by  means  of  our  general 
rules,  create  a  "  fine  moral  taste  "  amongst  men,  and  then,  as  the 
soldier  on  the  battlefield  will,  if  he  has  genius  enough,  know  when  to 
disoLey  with  profit  to  his  country,  so  will  the  man  of  "  fine  moral 


424  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

impracticable,  since  it  affords  us  no  hope  of  certainty 
about  that  which  most  interests  us — namely,  the  good 
or  evil  of  our  present  individual  acts. 

To  sum  up  our  criticism  of  this  theory — Biological 
Evolution  is  untenable  because,  first,  the  fundamental 
principles  of  morals  objectively  regarded  do  not  evolve, 
they  are  as  constant  as  human  nature  itself  ;  second,  it 
is  based  on  the  false  assumption  that  everything  in  the 
universe  evolves,  and  on  a  supposed  but  unreal  parallel- 
ism between  structure  and  function  on  the  one  hand, 
and  fulness  of  life  on  the  other  ;  thirdly,  because  it 
falsely  represents  life  as  the  end  of  human  action,  and 
health  and  adjustment  to  environment  as  the  criterion 
of  good. 

.    ETHICS  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EVOLUTION 

(l)    STATEMENT   OF  THE   THEORY 

The  theory  of  Psychological  Evolution  has  been  put 
forward  in  a  variety  of  ways,  oply  two  of  which  can  be 
noticed  here — that,  viz.,  connected  with  the  names  of 
Mill,*  on  the  one  hand,  and  that,  on  the  other  hand,  con- 
nected with  the  names  of  Spencer  and  M.  Levy-Bruhl. 

As  we  have  already  remarked  in  our  chapter  on 
"  Duty,"  these  two  theories  of  morality  are  markedly 
distinct.  For,  first,  the  evolutionary  process,  according 
to  Mill,  is  completed  during  the  hfe  of  each  individual, 
whereas  according  to  Spencer  and  L6vy-Bruhl  it  will 
end    only    with   the   complete   evolution    of   the   race. 

taste  "  know  when  to  deviate  from  the  general  law.  But  surely  this 
is  a  very  unsatisfactory  conclusion  to  a  supposed  practical  "  Theory 
of  Ethics." 

*  Wc  do  not  know  whether  we  arc  justified  in  calling  John  Stuart 
Mill's  theory  (which  is  generally  spoken  of  as  "  associationist  ")  an 
evolutionary  theory.  If  it  is  evolutionary  at  all,  it  is  evolutionary 
without  the  element  of  heredity.  This  the  reader  can  bear  in  mind 
in  the  pages  that  follow.  But  we  have  called  it  evolutionary  because 
the  theory  represents  our  moral  ideas  as  a  growth  or  a  ilevelopmcnt 
(brought  to  completion  within  the  lifetime  of  an  individual)  out  of 
aoa-moral  elements. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  425 

Secondly,  according  to  Mill,  the  process  of  psychological 
development  begins  in  childhood,  with  the  child's  first 
ideas  of  pleasure,  pain,  or  fear.  On  Spencer's  theory,  on 
the  other  hand,  our  moral  beliefs  had  their  beginnings 
in  far-off  ages  long  ago,  when  as  yet  there  were  no  ideas, 
but  only  life  in  its  lower  and  cruder  forms.  Nay,  they 
had  begun  to  form,  according  to  Spencer,  even  before 
life  had  appeared,  when  as  yet  there  existed  only  dead 
matter  and  its  movements.  Thus  did  the  physical  fis- 
sure of  rocks  image  forth  the  future  law  of  self-sacrifice 
and  sympathy,  the  dividing  off  of  one's  self  from  one's 
interests  through  self-abnegation.  Our  present  beliefs 
are,  according  to  Spencer,  the  result  of  the  accumulated 
experiences  of  all  the  ages — experiences  that  have  solidi- 
fied with  time  and  become  organised  into  moral  con- 
sciousness, which  moral  consciousness  is  easily  awakened 
into  action,  as  Mr.  Royce  (another  upholder  of  the 
theory)  says,  by  the  renewed  presence  of  any  one  of  the 
activities  or  experiences  that  went  to  form  it  in  bygone 
ages.* 

The  general  principle  of  Psychological  Evolution  has 
many  bearings  in  Ethics.  It  is  supposed  to  account  not 
only  for  our  ideas  of  good  and  evil,  but  for  our  ideas 
of  obligation,  sanction,  merit,  and  responsibility.  At 
present  we  are  concerned  only  with  ideas  of  moral  good 
and  evil,  with  our  beliefs  that  certain  actions  are  good 
and  certain  others  evil,  and  in  the  present  chapter  we 
shall  consider  Psychological  Evolution  in  its  relation  to 
these  ideas  and  beliefs  exclusively. 

Three  preliminary  remarks  must  be  made.  First,  to 
some  the  present  enquiry  might  seem  somewhat  out  of 
place,  concerning  as  it  does  the  origin  of  moral  ideas, 
whereas  in  these  chapters  we  are  dealing  exclusively 
with  theories  of  the  reality,  the  nature,  and  the  criterion 

•  Some  French  evolutionists — e.g.,  M.  Fouillee — consider  that 
besides  the  factor  of  evolution,  we  must  also  introduce  into  our  ex- 
planation of  the  origin  of  moral  ideas  another  factor — that,  namely, 
of  the  idee-force,  a  term  which  we  have  already  explained  in  our  chapter 
on  Duty,  page  249. 


426  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of  good.  But  we  believe  the  enquiry  is  quite  relevant  to 
our  present  purpose  ;  for,  if  the  theory  of  Psychological 
Evolution  be  true,  then,  we  maintain,  there  could  be  no 
such  thing  as  natural  law  or  morals.  This  we  shall  show 
later  in  the  present  chapter. 

Our  second  remark  (we  are  sure  it  will  be  readily 
admitted)  is  that  if  we  can  succeed  in  disposing  of  the 
theory  of  Psychological  Evolution  as  advocated  by 
Spencer,  then  Mill's  theory  also  will  be  disproved 
thereby,  since,  if  our  moral  ideas  cannot  result  from 
the  accumulated  pleasure  and  pain  of  all  the  ages, 
including  our  own  experience,  they  certainly  could  not 
originate  in  the  experience  of  the  individual  alone.  We 
shall,  therefore,  treat  only  of  the  larger  theory  adopted 
by  Spencer — that,  namely,  of  the  racial  evolution  of 
moral  ideas. 

Thirdly,  the  reader  must  carefully  distinguish  between 
the  theory  of  Psychological  Evolution  and  the  Aristo- 
telian and  scholastic  doctrine  on  "  the  effects  of  action — 
a  criterion  of  morality."  It  will  be  remembered  that  the 
very  first  of  our  secondary  criteria  concerned  the  effects 
of  actions.  That  act,  we  said,  is  unnatural,  and  there- 
fore bad,  which,  when  raised  to  a  general  line  of  conduct 
necessarily  injures  the  race — its  opposite  is  good.  Now, 
every  scholastic  will  admit  that  it  was  largely  by  using 
the  criterion  of  the  "  effects  of  action  "  that  our  remote 
ancestors  would,  revelation  apart,  have  judged  of  the 
morality  of  action.  But  between  the  growth  of  moral 
ideas  due  to  the  use  of  this  criterion  and  the  growth 
which  is  described  by  the  Psychological  Evolutionist 
there  are  very  large  differences.  In  the  first  place, 
our  ancestors,  according  to  the  scholastic  conception, 
performed  an  act  of  reasoning  in  judging  of  the  general 
effect  and  determining  by  means  of  it  the  morality  of 
actions  ;  and,  in  the  second  place,  the  act  was  a  con- 
scious process,  not  subconscious  or  unconscious.  This 
conscious  act  of  reasoning  may  have  been  formal  and 
explicit,   or  it   may  have  been   informal   and   impli(  it, 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  427 

but  its  logical  character  as  a  reasoning  process  may  be 
shown  by  casting  it  into  the  form  of  a  syllogism  thus  : — 
such  and  such  acts  work  out  harmfully  for  the  race  ; 
acts  that  work  out  harmfully  cannot  be  good  ;  therefore 
such  and  such  acts  cannot  be  morally  good.  This 
reasoning,  it  will  be  observed,  presupposes  the  idea  of 
moral  good  and  evil  already  possessed.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  Psychological  Evolutionists  represent  our 
moral  beliefs  as  resulting,  not  from  reasoning,  but  from 
mere  inherited  associations  of  certain  feelings  with  the 
conception  of  certain  acts.  And,  secondly,  this  process 
of  association  is  represented  as  for  the  most  part  a  sub- 
conscious process. 

In  justice,  however,  to  the  Psychological  Evolutionists 
we  should  add  that  they  do  not  claim  that  mere  experi- 
ences of  pleasure  and  pain  could,  unaided,  form  into 
Ethical  beliefs.  These  experiences,  they  contend,  must 
be  driven  into  the  brain  of  the  race  by  means  of  sanc- 
tions, public  and  private^  and  by  parental  instruction — 
forces  which  have  the  power  of  creating  many  associa- 
tions of  pleasure  and  pain  for  the  acts  of  men,  and  of 
transmitting  such  associations  of  feeling  to  posterity. 

(11)     CRITICISM      OF      THE      THEORY      OF      PSYCHOLOGICAL 
EVOLUTION 

We  shall  now  attempt  to  prove  that  this  theory  of 
Psychological  Evolution  is  untrue — the  theory,  namely, 
that  moral  beliefs  are  derived  from  associations  of 
feeling,  and  that  these  same  associations  are  created 
partly  by  our  own  experience  and  partly  by  the  ex- 
perience of  our  ancestors. 

And  in  order  to  establish  the  falsity  of  this  theory  we 
shall  show,  first,  that  our  moral  beliefs  are,  some  of 
them,  self-evident  truths  of  intellect  ;  others,  felt  to  be 
equally  necessary  with  the  first,  are  derived  from 
reasoning ;  that  therefore  our  present  moral  beliefs 
could  not  have  been  derived  by  association.     Secondly, 


428  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

we  shall   show  that   they   could   not   be   derived   from 
associations  of  pleasure  and  pain. 


(i)  Our  moral  beliefs  are  derived  from  reasoning. 

In  proof  of  this  proposition  we  appeal  {a)  to  our  con- 
sciousness, {h)  to  history,  (c)  to  the  Science  of  Ethics 
itself. 

{a)  Our  consciousness  tells  us  that  at  present  we 
accept  moral  propositions  because  our  intellect  under- 
stands the  reasons  for  accepting  them — reasons  which 
the  intellect  (at  least  in  the  case  of  an  educated  man) 
is  capable  of  explaining.  These  reasons  are  either  that 
the  proposition  is  self-evident  and  can  be  shown  to  be 
so,  or  because  the  proposition  is  provable  intellectually, 
on  grounds  that  are  perfectly  definite  and  intelligible. 
And  the  individual  man  knows  that  this  knowledge  and 
the  reasons  for  accepting  it  are  not  peculiar  to  himself, 
for  he  knows  that  man}^  other  persons  accept  such  beliefs 
for  reasons  similar  to  his.  For  instance,  we  know  why 
we  believe  murder  to  be  bad,  or  lying,  or  disobedience, 
or  stealing,  and  we  know  that  many  other  men  believe 
these  things  to  be  bad  also,  and  that  if  sufficiently  edu- 
cated they  would  be  able  to  state  the  intellectual  grounds 
for  their  belief.  We  admit,  indeed,  that  many  men  re- 
ceive their  moral  code  merely  on  the  authority  of  others. 
But  the  belief  of  the  disciple  in  his  master  and  the  conse- 
quent acceptance  by  the  disciple  of  the  master's  teaching 
are  sometimes  found  even  in  the  pursuit  of  the  other 
sciences,  and  are  no  proof  that  the  science  in  question  is 
not  ultimately  grounded  on  reasoning  ;  for  this  assent 
in  Moral  or  other  Science  is  given  on  the  understanding 
that  somebody  has  been  able  b}'  valid  reasoning  to 
establish  the  truths  so  believed.  Could  a  child  suspect 
that  nobody  had  ever  proved  the  truths  of  Mathematics 
he  would  not  accept  them.  And  in  the  same  way  did  he 
suspect  that  nobod}'  had  ever  proved  the  truths  of 
morals  he  would  not  accept  them.     The  existence,  then 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  429 

of  authority  in  the  teaching  of  n:  orals  is  no  proof  that 
our  moral  beliefs  are  not  grounded  on  reasoning. 

The  argument  from  consciousness  becomes  stronger 
when  we  consider  that  a  man  is  able  to  reflect  upon  his 
o-vn  moral  beliefs — beliefs  that  he  has  accepted  from 
childhood,  and  that  he  can  and  often  does  subject  these 
beliefs  to  examination,  and  sometimes  questions  their 
validity,  and  sometimes  even  rejects  them  as  invalid 
because  the  grounds  which  once  he  believed  to  exist  in 
support  of  them  he  now  finds  not  to  exist.  Now,  the 
fact  that  we  are  able  to  examine  and  criticise  our  own 
beliefs,  and  that  when  we  realise  that  they  are  not 
capable  of  being  supported  by  logical  reasons  we  reject 
them,  is  strong  evidence  that  moral  behefs  generally  do 
not  arise  by  association  but  on  the  grounds  of  reason, 
which  we  either  apprehend  ourselves,  or  believe  to  be 
apprehended  by  others. 

Sometimes,  perhaps,  we  do  not  question  these  moral 
beliefs  of  our  youth  ;  but  the  reason  why  we  do  not 
question  them  is  that  our  intellect  is  satisfied  with  them 
and  with  the  evidence  for  them.  Our  unquestioning 
acquiescence  in  them  is  not  due  to  heredity,  as  the 
Psychological  Evolutionist  would  have  us  believe.  The 
Psychological  Evolutionist  says  that  the  man  who 
inherits  beliefs  sees  no  reason  for  questioning  their 
validity,  because  inherited  beliefs  seem  always,  and 
must  seem  always,  to,  be  intuitive  or  self-evident  truths. 
To  this  we  reply  that  no  truth  could  seem  self-evident 
to  the  human  intellect  simply  because  it  is  inherited. 
Even  if  we  could  inherit  beliefs  still  there  is  no  pro- 
position which  we  are  not  able  to  examine  later  and 
put  to  the  test  and  reject  if  its  credentials  cannot  be 
shown.  The  human  intellect  regards  no  proposition  as 
self-evident  unless  it  sees  that  the  predicate  of  the  pro- 
position is  contained  in  the  subject.  If  the  predicate 
is  not  seen  to  be  contained  in  the  subject  then  the  in- 
tellect has  power  to  reject  the  proposition  until  such 
time  as  it  is  -proved  by  reasoning.     It  is  not  true,  there- 


^30  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

fore,  that  the  intellect  is  forced  to  regard  any  pro- 
position as  self-evident  merely  because  that  proposition 
is  inherited.* 

(6)  We  appeal,  secondly,  to  history,  which  supports 
our  theory  that  moral  beliefs  are  derived  by  reasoning. 
We  can  infer  from  history  that  men  have  always  formed 
their  moral  judgments,  or  at  least  adhered  to  their  judg- 
ments in  their  maturer  years,  on  the  basis  of  intrinsic 
reasons.  Any  records  of  the  past  that  have  a  bearing  on 
these  subjects  show  that  men  do  reason  and  accept  their 
beliefs  on  Reason.  And  even  with  regard  to  prehistoric 
man  we  have  no  reason  to  think  that  man  ever  acted 
otherwise.  At  no  age  in  the  history  of  the  human  race 
was  the  spirit  of  inquiry  wholly  absent,  and  at  no  age 
consequently  were  moral  beliefs  accepted  by  a  kind  of 
blind  instinct.  There  certainly  is  no  evidence  of  such 
beliefs.  We  must  suppose  that  in  all  ages  man  must 
have  engaged  sometimes  in  active  thought,  and  that 
he  must  have  tried  seriously  to  interpret  the  common 
facts  of  human  nature  and  to  deduce  from  them  the  laws 
that  obviously  befitted  human  conduct. 

(c)  Thirdly,  we  appeal  to  the  Science  of  Ethics  itself, 
in  which  are  given  the  jundamenial  scientific  reasons  for 
our  moral  beliefs.  Some  of  these  reasons  we  have  stated 
in  the  earlier  chapters  of  this  work,  and  some  will  be 
given  later,  when  we  come  to  treat  of  special  Ethics. 
And  our  argument  is  that  if  the  trained  scientist  is  able 
to  give  the  reasons  of  his  beliefs  we  should  assume  in 
Ethics,  as  in  every  other  science,  that  the  world  at  large 
also  accepts  these  beliefs  for  assignable  reasons,  and  not 
blindly  or  as  a  result  of  heredity  only. 

We  now  go  on  to  our  second  proposition  : — 

(2)  Our  present  moral  beliefs  could  not  have  been 
derived  by  inherited  associations  from  feelings  of  pleasure 
and  pain. 

(a)  Our  first  argument  is  that  no  mere  association  of 

•  A  fuller  proof  of  this  proposition  will  be  given  in  the  section  2. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  431 

feelings,  whether  of  pleasure  or  pain  or  of  any  other 
thing,  could  ever  develop  into  a  belief.  I  may,  for 
instance,  on  seeing  a  certain  house,  perceive  at  the 
same  time  a  certain  perfume,  and  this  combination 
may  be  repeated  so  often  that  the  very  thought  of  the 
house  awakens  in  me  the  feeling  or  thought  of  the  per- 
fume. Yet  we  are  not  aware  that  this  association  will 
ever  of  itself  and  without  further  reasoning  develop  into 
the  belief  that  the  house  is  either  the  perfume  itself  or  is 
the  cause  of  the  perfume.  Mere  associations  may, 
indeed,  make  the  thinking  of  a  certain  object  necessary, 
and  the  fact  that  two  things  occur  together  may  make 
us  suspect  they  are  causally  connected.  But  mere  asso- 
ciation cannot  of  itsclj  become  a  belief  that  one  thing  is 
another  or  is  its  cause.  This  is  not  the  function  of  asso- 
ciation— to  generate  beliefs.  The  function  of  associa- 
tion is  determined  empirically  by  its  effects ;  and  its 
only  effect,  so  far  as  our  experience  goes,  is  found  in  the 
fact  that  when  any  idea  arises  in  our  minds  other  related 
ideas  tend  sympathetically  to  spring  into  our  conscious- 
ness at  the  same  time.  Mere  association  then  could 
never  develop  into  an  intellectual  assent. 

(6)  Secondly,  beliefs  cannot  be  transmitted.  A  child 
never  seems  to  be  possessed  of  ready-made  moral  beliefs. 
No  doubt,  even  without  instruction,  people  must  at  some 
time  come  to  a  knowledge  of  certain  self-evident  prin- 
ciples. But  of  these  principles  there  is  at  first  no  trace 
in  the  child's  thought  or  expression.  And  even  later, 
when  these  self-evident  principles  come  to  be  understood, 
there  still  appears  no  trace  of  other  beliefs  (beliefs  as 
necessary  as  the  former,  but  conclusions  of  Reason), 
which  yet  our  ancestors  have  understood  from  the  most 
distant  ages.  The  appearance  of  these  beliefs  in  the 
mind  either  of  child  or  man  is  undoubtedly  due  either 
to  the  exercise  of  the  reasoning  power  or  to  instruc- 
tion. On  the  theory  of  Psychological  Evolution  these 
beliefs  should  be  all  inherited,  and  children,  instead  of 
being  without  beliefs  of  any  kind,  should  all  be  born 


432  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

with  a  consciousness  not  only  of  the  principles  of 
morals  but  of  many  of  the  universally  admitted  con- 
clusions. 

(c)  Again,  is  it  possible  that  the  present  moral  beliefs 
of  the  fully-developed  consciousness  of  the  adult  are 
only  the  accumulated  and  consolidated  feelings  of  past 
pleasures  and  pains  ?  Could  the  influence  and  the 
sanctions  of  parents  and  of  society  cause  the  accumula- 
tion of  remembered  pleasure  and  pain  to  develop  into 
a  consciousness  of  our  present  moral  code  ?  These 
questions  must  be  answered  in  the  negative.  Such 
vices  as  sexual  immorality  have  not  in  past  ages  gathered 
around  them  a  surplusage  of  pain  so  great  as  to  cause  a 
hereditary  belief  that  they  are  intrinsically  bad.  In 
fact,  it  is  doubtful  whether  such  acts  would  not  have 
created  an  associated  feeling  of  pleasure.  Again,  truth- 
fulness is  the  virtue  of  a  courageous  man,  because  it 
needs  a  courageous  man  to  be  always  truthful.  From 
this  it  is  evident  that  the  consequences  of  truthfulness 
are  not  exclusively  pleasurable  consequences.  How, 
then,  could  mere  associations  of  feeling,  however  they 
may  accumulate,  and  however  much  they  may  have 
been  enforced  by  the  sanctions  of  society  and  of  parents, 
develop  into  a  moral  belief  that  truthfulness  is  morally 
good  and  not  morally  bad  ?  If  our  moral  beliefs  be 
derived  from  associations  of  pleasure  and  pain,  then, 
since  the  effects  of  actions  like  sexual  immorality  and 
truthfulness  are  mixed,  our  convictions  should  be  that 
such  acts  are  morally  good  in  part  and  morally  bad  in 
part.  It  is  possible,  indeed,  that  society  early  in  the 
history  of  the  race  may  have  condemned  or  approved 
of  these  acts  for  purposes  of  the  general  good,  and  thus 
by  its  sanctions  given  to  sexual  immorality  and  truth- 
fulness the  associations  of  pain  and  pleasure  which  have 
caused  men  to  regard  one  us  a  vice  and  the  other  as  a 
virtue.  But  to  suppose  such  positive  legislation  takes 
us  quite  outside  the  theory  that  our  moral  beliefs  are 
due   to   inherited    feelings.     Such   primitive   legislation 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  433 

would  need,  and  would  be  prompted  by  an  intellectual 
appreciation  of  the  consequences  of  those  acts,  and  any 
such  intellectual  appreciation  is  incompatible  with  the 
Psychological  Evolutionist  theory  of  feelings  and  associa- 
tions as  the  essential  element  in  the  building  up  of 
moral  beliefs.  It  would  also  need  an  intellectual  appre- 
ciation of  the  moral  character  of  those  acts  based  on  the 
consideration  of  consequences.  If,  then,  past  legis- 
lators forbade  certain  acts  they  must  have  done  so 
because  they  perceived  that  these  acts  were  bad.  And 
the  question  remains  in  their  case  as  in  ours — how  could 
mere  associations  of  pleasure  and  pain  generate  a  belief  in 
the  '  good  '  and  '  evil '  of  the  courses  we  have  described  ? 
Again,  let  us  suppose  that  early  legislators  forbade 
the  acts  just  mentioned  :  it  is  certain  that  even  such 
prohibition  could  not  blot  out  the  associations  of  pleasure 
attaching  to  such  acts.  So  that  we  find  ourselves  con- 
fronted again  with  the  difficulty  of  the  mixed  associa- 
tions, a  difficulty  which  it  is  important  we  should  duly 
emphasise,  since  it  touches  what  is  central  in  this  most 
important  of  all  evolutionist  theories.  We  shall,  there- 
fore, before  bringing  the  present  argument  to  a  close 
re-state  the  difficulty.  Each  act  has  many  and  varied 
associations,  some  agreeable,  some  painful ;  whilst,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  theory  that  our  moral  beliefs  arose 
solely  from  these  associations  requires  that  the  associa- 
tions of  what  we  now  recognise  as  a  good  act  should  be 
altogether  on  the  side  of  pleasure,  and  the  associations 
of  what  we  now  recognise  as  a  bad  act  should  be  alto- 
gether on  the  side  of  pain,  or  at  least  that  the  former 
should  be  so  much  on  the  side  of  pleasure  and  the  latter 
so  much  on  the  side  of  pain  that  the  opposite  feelings 
in  each  case  may  be  regarded  as  of  no  account.  This 
latter,  we  should  sa}',  is  the  more  usual  contention  of 
the  Psychological  Evolutionists — namely,  that  in  the 
case  of  what  we  now  recognise  as  bad  acts  the  associa- 
tions of  pain  have  become  enormously  developed,  and 
have  excluded  the  agreeable  associations  from  the  con- 

Vol.  1—28. 


4M  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

sciousness  of  men,  and  that  in  the  case  of  good  acts 
the  opposite  has  taken  place.  Now  it  will  be  quite 
obvious  that  in  such  acts  as  stealing  and  lying  the 
pleasure-giving  element  (the  element  of  profit)  is  quite 
as  persistent  as  the  evil-bringing  element,  which  latter 
the  Psychological  Evolutionists  suppose  to  have  evolved 
into  man's  concept  of  dishonesty.  Nay,  more,  in  steal- 
ing and  lying  the  pleasure  or  profit  element  is  intrinsic — 
that  is,  it  is  a  natural  effect,  whereas  the  pain  and  the 
loss  are  extrinsic  to  the  act — that  is,  the  pain  is  that  of 
social  punishment  only.  It  is  the  pleasure  element, 
therefore,  and  not  the  pain  element  that  sHould  the 
more  easily  have  become  associated  in  consciousness 
with  the  idea  of  these  actions.  The  difficulty  remains, 
therefore,  of  explaining  as  the  resultant  of  these  two 
opposing  forces — namely,  those  of  pleasure  and  of  pain 
— such  a  definite  and  universal  belief  amongst  men  as 
the  idea  that  we  are  bound  not  to  steal  and  lie.  We 
cannot,  in  the  light  of  our  daily  experience,  suppose 
that  resultant  to  be  on  the  side  of  painful  associations 
with  such  a  huge  preponderance  as  to  cause  men  in 
their  moral  ideas  to  disregard  completely  the  associations 
of  an  opposite  kind. 

{3)   Theory  of  natural  selection  as  applied  to  the  psycho- 
logical question  of  the  origin  of  moral  beliefs. 

The  theory  which  we  have  just  criticised  supposes 
that  association  is  the  principal  factor  in  the  evolution 
of  moral  ideas.  We  now  pass  to  another  theory  of 
Psychological  Evolution,  having  as  its  groundwork  the 
law  of  "  natural  selection "  and  of  "  survival."  The 
origin  of  our  moral  beliefs  is  explained  by  some  as  a 
special  case  of  the  law  of  "  natural  selection  "  and  the 
"  survival  of  the  fittest."  Certain  moral  beliefs,  it  is 
explained,  tend  to  survive  more  than  others  because 
they  are  more  suitable  to  their  human  environment, 
and  those  beliefs  that  survive  we  naturally  regard  as 
certain,  and  as  the  only  true  beliefs,  since  none  others 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  435 

are  left  in  liuman  consciousness  to  compete  with 
them. 

Now,  before  going  on  to  estimate  the  truth  or  falsit}' 
of  this  particular  form  of  the  theory  of  Psychological 
Evolution,  we  may  be  allowed  to  remark  that  in  one 
modified  sense  it  is  possible  to  explain  our  moral  beliefs 
as  a  result  of  this  law  of  survival  in  the  struggle  for 
existence  ;  for,  as  we  have  already  pointed  out,  it  is 
quite  possible  for  men  to  ground  their  moral  judgments 
on  experience — that  is,  upon  the  pleasurable  or  painful 
consequences  of  actions  in  a  sense  already  explained. 
Pleasure  and  pain  are,  aS  we  formerly  showed,  a 
criterion,  though  they  are  not  the  primary  criterion,  of 
good  conduct.  It  is  quite  possible,  therefore,  that  our 
present  moral  judgments  may  be  to  a  large  extent  the 
result  of  such  experiences,  that,  many  courses  of  con- 
duct having  been  tried,  it  was  found  that  some  could 
not  be  made  to  work  on  account  of  the  consequences 
that  they  necessarily  entailed,  that  these  courses  were 
then  regarded  as  bad,  and  that  thus  our  present  moral 
beliefs  are  to  be  explained  as  a  survival — a  survival, 
namely,  from  many  rival  theories,  some  of  which  have 
been  discarded  as  unpracticable  and  untrue,  and  others 
retained  as  workable,  and,  therefore,  as  natural  and  true.* 

But  this  is  not  the  view  defended  by  the  psychological 
evolutionists  now  under  consideration.  For  in  the 
theory  just  explained,  and  which  we  do  not  altogether 
oppose,  our  moral  views  are  regarded  as  rational  deduc- 
tions from  "  experience,"  and  as  replacing  one  another, 
not  in  the  sense  contemplated  by  the  Darwinian 
Ethicians,  whose  claim  is  that  ideas  may  crush  one 
another  out  of  existence,  just  as  plants  or  animals 
crush  one  another  out  of  life,  some  of  them  being 
stronger  in  their  fibre  and  more  suited  to  their  environ- 
ment, others  weaker  and  less  suited,  but  in  the  sense 

*  This  is  to  be  understood  in  the  sense  already  given.  Conduct 
that  leads  to  evil  consequences  necessarily  and  in  all  sets  of  circum- 
stances is  unnatural,  and  the  belief  that  such  a  course  of  conduct  is 
the  good  or  the  right  course  is  an  untrue  belief. 


436  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

that  in  the  sphere  of  morals  a  ripened  and  well-founded 
view  may  replace  a  crude  and  hasty  one,  or  a  true  view 
may  replace  a  false  one,  just  as  they  replace  one  another 
in  Physiology  or  Botany  or  any  other  science.  The 
following,  which  we  take  from  Professor  Sorley's 
"  Ethics  of  Naturalism,"  will,  we  believe,  be  found  to 
represent  the  survival  theory  of  Psychological  Evolution 
with  sufficient  accuracy — in  spite  of  a  certain  ambiguity 
which  shall  be  noted  presently.*  Having  explained  that 
Natural  Selection  may  have  reference  to  three  things — 
competition  between  individuals,  between  groups  of 
individuals,  and  between  ideas — he  then  goes  on  to  say — 
"  Now,  when  the  phrase  '  natural  selection  of  Morals  ' 
is  used,  the  reference  is  commonly  to  a  conflict  of  this 
last  kind.  The  supposition  is  that  different  ideas  and 
also  different  standards  of  action  are  manifested  at  the 
same  time  in  the  same  community,  that  the}^  compete 
with  one  another  for  existence,  and  that  those  which 
are  better  adapted  to  the  life  of  the  community  survive 
while  the  others  grow  weaker  and  in  the  end  disappear. 
In  this  way  the  law  of  natural  selection  is  supposed  to 
apply  to  moral  ideas  and  moral  standards."  In  this 
theory,  therefore,  certain  ideas  and  beliefs  are  regarded 
as  surviving  in  the  same  way  as  plants  or  animals  sur- 
vive— namely,  as  a  result  of  a  certain  struggle  for 
existence,  a  struggle  in  which  some  principles  and  beliefs 
are  gradually  discarded  by  the  human  mind,  whilst 
others  that  are  more  suitable  to  their  environment  gain 
prominence  and  live. 

Now,  though  this  explanation  seems  simple  enough, 
■we  think  that,  as  stated  by  Professor  Sorley,  the  theory 
is  somewhat  ambiguous  because  it  does  not  explain 
whether  particular  ideas  survive  or  disappear  because 
the  individual  or  the  race  who  maintains  them  survives 
or  disappears  ;  or  whether  the  battle  is  a  purely  psycho- 
logical one,  a  struggle  between  the  ideas  themselves,  a 
struggle  which  would  take  place  even  if  the  mind  that 

•  This  theory  is  merely  explained  by,  it  is  not  defended  by,  Sorley. 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  437 

harboured  these  ideas  were  one  and  permanent,  or  even 
though  individual  persons  remained  ahvays  in  hfe. 
These  t(vo  possible  forms  of  the  present  theory  are 
really  distinct  in  principle,  and  we  think  that  they 
should  be  kept  separate  in  our  minds,  even  though  the 
results  to  which  they  lead  be  the  same  in  each.  We 
repeat,  therefore,  this  distinction  as  follows  :  (a)  In  the 
first  theory  beliefs  are  represented  as  surviving  and  dis- 
appearing because  some  beliefs  and  principles  are  so 
adapted  to  their  environment  as  to  aid  the  individuals 
who  maintain  them  to  live  and  be  strong,  whilst  others 
tend  to  the  extermination  of  the  individuals  who  main- 
tain them.  Thus,  races  that  believe  in  the  rights  of 
parents  to  rule  and  direct  their  children  have  a  better 
chance  of  survival  than  those  who  maintain  the  opposite 
view,  and,  therefore,  the  views  of  the  former  have 
naturally  a  better  chance  of  surviving  than  those  of 
the  latter.  In  other  words,  the  content  of  men's  minds 
will  naturally  survive  or  disappear  according  as  the 
mind  or  the  person  that  contains  or  maintains  that  con- 
tent survives  or  disappears,  (b)  In  the  second  form  of 
the  theory  ideas  are  represented  as  contending  with 
one  another,  as  crushing  one  another  out  of  existence  in 
the  psychological  sphere,  in  the  same  way  that  plants 
and  animals  contend  with  and  kill  one  another  in  the 
physical  universe.  In  both  forms  of  the  theory,  we 
admit,  it  is  the  idea  or  the  belief  that  is  to  be  regarded 
as  the  principal  factor,  as  the  instigator  in  the  struggle, 
and  as  the  cause  of  survival  or  of  decay,  since,  even  in 
the  first  form,  it  is  the  idea  or  the  belief  that  determines 
the  staying-power  of  the  individual  in  the  struggle,  and 
therefore  it  is  the  idea  that  decides  on  what  side  the 
victory  shall  be.  Still,  as  we  have  said,  for  clearness 
sake  it  will  be  well  to  keep  the  systems  apart,  and  also 
to  criticise  them  separately. 

Criticism  of  the  psychological  "  survival  "  theories. 
(a)  In  the  first  form — the  form,  namely,  which  repre- 


438  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

sents  moral  ideas  and  beliefs  as  surviving  or  vanishing 
according  as  the  individuals  who  possess  them  survive 
or  vanish — there  is  involved  an  assumption  that  has 
already  been  examined  and  rejected  by  us  in  various 
parts  of  the  present  work — the  assumption,  namely,  that 
moral  ideas  and  beliefs  are  transmitted  by  inheritance, 
that  the  beliefs  of  a  father  are,  even  apart  from  instruc- 
tion, a  determining  factor  in  the  beliefs  of  his  children, 
if  they  are  not  the  whole  determining  cause  of  their 
beliefs.  This  assumption  we  have  denied  outright,  and 
it  will  not  be  necessary  now  to  repeat  our  arguments 
against  it. 

Another  point  on  which  we  would  insist  in  connection 
with  the  first  form  of  the  theory — a  point  which  has 
already  been  explained  and  established  in  our  present 
chapter — is  the  following  :  our  moral  beliefs,  even  if 
they  have  been  transmitted  to  us  by  inheritance,  are 
always  revisable  by  our  intellects — that  is,  it  is  always 
possible  to  reconsider  them  and  to  retain  or  reject  them 
according  as  they  admit  or  do  not  admit  of  rational 
explanation  or  proof.  Hence,  it  is  absurd  to  contend 
that  our  sole  reason  for  retaining  our  present  moral 
beliefs  is  that  they  have  come  down  to  us,  the  rest 
having  been  lost  with  their  owners  in  their  struggle  for 
existence.  Is  it  not  evident  from  experience,  and 
especially  from  introspection,  that  it  is  in  our  power  at 
any  moment  to  question  our  present  moral  beliefs,  to 
conceive  their  opposites,  and  to  reject  or  to  accept 
either  of  these  according  as  the  proofs  available  for  one 
side  or  the  other  are  stronger  or  weaker  ?  If  moral 
beliefs  could  appear  and  disappear  with  their  possessors 
as  languages  and  racial  features  disappear  with  certain 
peoples,  then  it  would  be  impossible  for  us  to  revise  our 
present  beliefs  in  this  way,  to  ask  whether  they  are 
more  true  than  their  opposites,  and  more  especially  to 
alter  a  moral  belief  on  revision,  a  thing  which  often 
happens  in  matter  of  fact. 

(b)  This  same  argument  may,  we  believe,  be  reason- 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  439 

ably  urged  against  the  second  form  of  the  theory  as 
against  the  first.  If  moral  beliefs  could  struggle  with 
and  destroy  one  another  in  the  psychological  arena, 
say,  if  possible,  in  the  racial  or  tribal  mind,  as  trees 
destroy  one  another  in  the  forest,  then  it  would  not  be 
in  man's  power  to  question  or  to  revise,  to  seek  proofs 
for  or  to  alter  his  moral  beliefs  at  any  moment.  And 
the  fact  that  we  are  possessed  of  such  a  power  is  proof 
unquestionable  that  the  full  and  final  explanation  of 
the  presence  in  man  of  moral  beliefs  is  not  to  be  found 
in  the  theory  of  struggle  and  survival,  nor,  indeed,  in 
any  other  theory  of  Psychological  Evolution. 

Beliefs,  then,  we  repeat,  are  not  formed  and  discarded 
mechanically — that  is,  as  a  result  of  mechanical  or  quasi- 
mechanical  laws  of  reaction  between  mind  and  environ- 
ment, as  plants  and  animals  crush  one  another  out  of 
life  in  the  struggle  for  existence.  Our  moral  beliefs  are 
built  up  by  a  slow  process  of  reasoning,  helped  on  by 
instruction  and  tradition.  But,  let  it  at  any  moment  be 
understood  that  a  particular  belief  has  not  been  proved, 
that  it  is  merely  a  tradition,  or  that  it  rests  on  premisses 
which  there  is  good  reason  for  regarding  as  untrue, 
then,  no  matter  how  long  the  tradition  and  how  suit- 
able the  judgment  for  success  and  survival  in  the  given 
environment,  such  a  judgment  or  belief  will  be  discarded 
with  the  same  ease,  and  perhaps  also  with  the  same 
necessity,  as  any  other  judgment  which  our  Reason 
shows  us  to  be  false  and  unfounded. 

We  would  also,  before  taking  leave  of  our  present 
subject,  point  to  two  assumptions  made  by  this  theory 
in  both  its  forms.  One  is  that  in  the  beginning  there 
were  no  definite  moral  beliefs,  that  at  some  period  of 
our  history,  while  some  men  believed  that  wholesale 
murder  and  lying  and  cruelty  and  the  neglect  of  children 
were  bad,  others  regarded  them  as  good,  others,  again, 
as  at  least  as  good  as  their  opposites — that  is,  as  in- 
different— and  that,  finally,  one  set  of  ideas  crushed  the 
others  out  of  existence.    Now,  to  entertain  such  beliefs 


440  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

as  these  is  opposed  to  all  that  we  know  of  human  nature. 
We  cannot  believe  that  any  rational  being  ever  believed 
that  lying,  and  pitilessness,  and  wholesale  murder  were 
either  good  or  indifferent.  They  are  too  evidently 
opposed  to  human  life  and  progress  to  be  considered 
anything  but  bad.  Our  main  beliefs  then  cannot  be 
explained  by  selection  and  survival.  Secondly,  in  both 
forms  of  the  theory  it  is  supposed  that  the  true  concep- 
tion of  morals  is  always  the  surviving  conception,  a  sup- 
position which  we  cannot  grant,  since,  as  Professor 
Sorley  points  out,  it  happens  that  "  in  the  majority  of 
instances  the  holding  of  false  or  inadequate  conceptions 
does  not  tend  to  weaken  vitality."  Hence,  a  belief  need 
not  be  regarded  as  true  simply  because  it  makes  for 
survival,  for  there  are  a  great  many  false  ideas  which  if 
accepted  would  not  tend  in  the  least  to  weaken  vitality, 
and  consequently  they  might  survive  for  generations. 
Vitality  and  survival,  therefore,  are  not  the  sole  deter- 
minants of  our  moral  beliefs. 

For  these  reasons  we  reject  the  theory  of  Natural 
Selection  and  of  Survival  as  an  explanation  of  the 
origin  of  our  present  moral  ideas. 


QUESTION    OF   ORIGIN    IN    ITS    RELATION    TO    QUESTION   OF 

VALIDITY 

In  concluding  this  treatment  of  Psychological  Evolu- 
tion we  must  consider  Professor  Sidgwick's  view  that 
the  question  of  the  validity  of  our  moral  beliefs  is  quite 
independent  of  the  question  of  their  origin.  According 
to  Sidgwick,  questions  concerning  the  origin  of  our  idea 
of  space  cannot  possibly  affect  the  problem  of  the 
validity  of  our  mathematical  beliefs.  A  pari,  he  con- 
tends, there  is  no  reason  why  any  theory  of  the  origin 
of  our  moral  beliefs  should  determine  the  problem  of 
the  validity  of  these  moral  beliefs. 

Now,  if  Professor  Sidgwick  were  right  in  making  this 
inference  hy  would  show  that   the  theory  of  Psycho- 


EVOLUTION  AND  ETHICS  441 

logical  Evolution  is  irrelevant  to  the  Science  of  Ethics, 
and  it  would  be  unnecessary  to  discuss  it  in  this  book. 
But  we  differ  from  Professor  Sidgwick  on  this  point. 
We  do  not  deny  the  importance  of  investigating  origins 
for  the  purpose  of  understanding  validity.  We  contend 
that  if  the  moral  beliefs  of  men  in  general  be  the  result 
of  association  only,  if  it  be  understood  that  no  man  can 
prove  the  truth  of  these  beliefs,  then  we  have  no  guar- 
antee that  there  is  anything  in  the  objective  world  that 
corresponds  to  these  beliefs— that  is,  we  have  no  guar- 
antee of  their  validity — they  may  be  purely  subjective. 
In  Ethics,  therefore,  as  in  other  Sciences,  we  regard 
our  beliefs  as  valid,  either  because  we  ourselves  or 
somebody  else  has  proved  them  true.  Else  we  should 
not  accept  them. 

Professor  Sidgwick's  argument  from  our  beliefs  in 
Geometry  we  regard  as  fallacious.  Questions  in  regard 
to  the  origin  of  our  idea  of  space  may  not,  indeed,  affect 
our  beliefs  in  Geometrical  propositions,  but  questions 
as  regards  the  origin  of  our  belief  in  the  principles  of 
Geometry  may  and  do  affect  the  question  of  validity. 
If,  as  Mill  asserted,  our  belief  in  the  axioms  of  Euclid  is 
merely  due  to  association  of  ideas,  if  these  axioms  are 
not  self-evident  in  the  sense  of  the  predicate  being  con- 
tained in  the  subject,  then  we  have  no  guarantee  that 
these  axioms  are  true,  or  that  the  propositions  that 
depend  on  these  axioms  are  true.  Again,  if  our  beliefs 
in  the  propositions  of  Euclid  be  due  to  association 
merely,  if  it  be  understood  that  no  man  had  established 
their  truth  by  reasoning,  then,  again,  our  belief  in  these 
propositions  might  not  be  valid — they  might  be  purely 
subjective.  In  the  same  way,  if  our  moral  beliefs  be 
due  to  association  merely,  if  we  cannot  prove  them  to 
be  true  or  show  them  to  be  self-evident,  then  their 
validity  at  once  becomes  doubtful — they  may  be  purely 
subjective.  Hence,  the  question  of  the  validity  of  our 
moral  beliefs  is  not  independent  of  the  question  of  their 
origin. 


CHAPTER   XIII 
ETHICS    OF   TRANSCENDENTAL   EVOLUTION 

{a)    STATEMENT   OF  THEORY 

To  describe  the  various  forms  of  the  theories  known  as 
theories  of  Transcendental  Evolution  would  be  out  of 
the  question  in  a  w^ork  like  the  present.  On  the  other 
hand,  to  give  a  combined  account  of  them,  an  account 
that  would  embrace  the  features  common  to  them  all, 
W'Ould  be  a  very  difficult,  if  not  an  impossible  task. 
Still  w^e  feel  that  it  would  be  a  great  help  to  the  student 
if,  before  attempting  the  study  of  these  theories,  he  had 
some  general  conception  of  their  character  and  purpose, 
even  though  this  general  conception  were  inadequate 
and  required  to  be  modified  afterwards  in  order  to  fit  in 
with  any  one  particular  theory.  It  is  with  this  end  in 
view  that  we  offer  the  reader  the  following  brief  account 
of  the  Ethics  of  Transcendental  Evolution,  an  account, 
we  confess,  which  is  meant  to  correspond  more  with  the 
Hegelian  than  with  any  other  system,  since  it  is  in  this 
system  that  all  transcendental  theories  are  supposed  to 
culminate. 

A  definition  will  be  more  easily  framed  when  we  have 
compared  the  theory  of  Transcendental  Evolution  with 
the  theory  of  Biological  Evolution.  The  theory  of  Bio- 
logical Evolution  is  an  empirical  or  a  posteriori  theory. 
It  is  built  upon  a  supposed  phenomenon  of  the  world  of 
sense,  a  phenomenon  which  is  discovered  by  sense — 
namely,  that  of  the  physical  universe,  as  evolving,  as 
passing  from  a  less  perfect  to  a  more  perfect  state.  The 
whole  orderly  system  of  the  firmament  is,  we  are  told, 
an  evolution.  The  stars  and  planets,  the  sun  and  the 
earth  are  all  evolutions  from  the  one  original  primal 

442 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  443 

substance.  On  earth  higher  species  evolve  from  lower. 
Conduct  also  evolves  according  to  certain  laws,  as  is 
evident  from  comparing  the  structure  and  habits  of  one 
animal  species  with  another,  and  also  the  habits  of  one 
grade  of  human  civilisation  with  another.  And  the 
laws  which  we  thus  find  to  govern  the  evolution  of 
conduct  can,  according  to  Spencer,  be  made  to  serve  as 
a  ground  of  morals,  since  morally  perfect  conduct  is 
nothing  more  than  highly  evolved  conduct.  The 
method,  therefore,  of  the  Ethics  of  Biological  Evolu- 
tion is  in  the  main  empirical  and  inductive  or  a  posteriori 
— it  is  founded  on  experience. 

The  theor}^  of  Transcendental  Evolution  is  the  very 
reverse  of  all  this.  In  the  working  out  of  this  theory 
Reason  may  be  guided  to  some  extent  by  analogies  from 
the  senses  ;  it  may  even  depend  to  a  very  large  extent 
on  experience  and  on  the  use  of  the  historical  method  ; 
but  the  method  of  the  theory  of  Transcendental  Evolu- 
tion is  primarily  a  priori.  It  is  based  not  on  an  ex- 
amination of  particular  objects,  but  on  the  highest  and 
most  universal  of  conceptions — that,  namely,  of  the 
Absolute.*  The  Absolute  (whether  regarded  as  sub- 
jective or  objective  or  the  ground  of  both)  is  that 
ultimate  Being,  from  which  all  things  are  derived,  in 
which  all  things  subsist,  and  of  which  they  are  merely 
parts  or  phases — it  is  the  ground  reality  of  the  Universe, 
and  from  it  and  out  of  it,  are  evolved  all  laws  and 
relations. 

This  Absolute  is  described  as  first  unfolding  itself, 
differentiating  itself  (according  to  laws  which  our  Reason 
discovers  a  priori  in  the  very  conception  of  the  Abso- 
lute) into  the  various  particular  objects  of  the  universe, 


*  Philosophers  vary  in  the  account  they  give  of  this  ground-Being 
of  the  Universe.  With  Fichte  it  is  purely  subjective.  It  is  the  Ego. 
With  Schelling  it  is  absolute  indifference  of  subjective  and  objective. 
With  Hegel  it  is  more  fundamental  than  either  subjective  or  objective, 
and  the  ground  of  both.  The  method  of  Hegel's  system  is  usually 
known  as  "  dialectic,"  but  as  dialectic  this  method  is  a  priori  or  de- 
ductive, not  a  posteriori. 


444  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

both  mental  and  phj'sical,  and  then,  secondly,  moving 
on  towards  its  own  fuller  and  fuller  realisation  through 
the  re-identification  of  these  same  particulars  with  itself, 
until  in  the  end  they  become  absolutely  one  with  it. 
This  whole  process  may  be  described,  following  some 
defenders  of  this  theory,  as  first  a  movement  from 
negative  (or  abstract)  to  positive  infinity — that  is,  from 
undifferentiated  or  potential  infinity  to  differentiated  or 
actual  infinity,  and  then  a  movement  back  into  the  real 
infinity  which  embraces  the  undifferentiated  and  differ- 
entiated Absolute  in  one  complete  reality. 

Now,  morals,  we  are  told,  form  one  portion  of  this 
process — one  phase  in  the  development  of  the  Absolute — ■ 
and  under  "  morals  "  we  are  to  understand  not  merely 
the  laws  of  conduct  but  our  views  of  those  laws,  also  the 
moral  customs  and  institutions  in  which  those  views  are 
enshrined,  and  which  are  themselves  the  objective  ex- 
pression of  the  moral  law.  The  Ethics,  therefore,  of 
Transcendental  Evolution  we  may  define  as  the  theory 
that  moral  laws  and  moral  opinions  and  customs  are  a 
gradual  development  out  of  the  Absolute,  that  the'  good 
is  any  act  (or  rather  any  state)  which  realises  or  repro- 
duces the  Absolute  in  things — which  fits  in  with  the 
process  whereby  the  Absolute  principle  of  the  universe 
brings  into  closer  and  closer  identity  with  itself  the  par- 
ticular objects  and  ends  of  the  universe,  into  which  it 
has  differentiated  itself. 

But,  besides  the  theories  of  pure  transcendentalism, 
theories  which  deduce  the  moral  law  from  the  mere 
conception  of  the  Absolute  (for  instance,  the  theory  of 
Hegel  and  Bradley),  there  are  other  modified  theories, 
which,  though  based  on  metaphysical  conceptions 
similar  to  those  of  Hegel's,  still  make  positive  and 
express  use  of  experience  in  the  formulation  of  the  laws 
of  morals,  and  even  follow  the  historical  method  not  as 
a  secondary  method,  as  is  the  case  with  Hegel  and 
Bradley,  but  as  the  primary  and  essential  method  of 
Ethics.     Such  a  modified  form  of  Transcendentalism  is 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  445 

that  of  Green.*  Like  Hegel,  Green  regards  the  Abso- 
lute as  slowly  unfolding  or  differentiating  itself  into  the 
manifold  of  particular  objects,  and  through  this  process 
of  differentiation  approaching  gradually  the  final  end, 
which  is  complete  Self-Realisation  or  the  state  of  com- 
plete positive  unity  of  the  Absolute  consciousness  with 
finite  things.  What  that  self-realisation  consists  in,  or 
how  we  may  directly  promote  it  in  ourselves.  Green  does 
not  claim  to  know.  But  he  believes  that  we  can  know 
the  direction  in  which  this  supreme  end  lies  by  examin- 
ing the  line  along  which  humanity  has  been  developing 
up  to  the  present  moment,  since,  according  to  Green,  in 
continuing  to  follow  that  line  of  development  which  has 
brought  man  to  his  present  elevated  condition  we  must 
necessarily  approach  to  the  true  and  final  ideal  of  human 
conduct,  and  thus  we  shall  indirectly,  if  not  directly 
and  consciously,  be  moving  to  our  final  end.  Green's 
theory,  therefore,  is  in  great  measure,  if  not  principally, 
an  empirical  theory. 

NoTE.f — This  brief  description  of  the  Transcendental 
theories  we  must  now  fill  in  by  describing  in  some  detail  one 
or  two  of  the  best  known  of  these  systems.  We  select  for 
special  mention  the  theories  of  Hegel  and  Green,  of  whose 
systems  we  shall  give  a  very  brief  account. 

Kegel's  ethical  system 

Like  most  Ethical  systems  Hegel's  begins  with  an  analysis 
of  will.  Will  is  the  faculty  in  which  morality  resides.  It  is 
not  a  distinct  faculty  from  thought.  Will  and  thought  are 
but  two  functions,  the  one  conative,  the  other  cognitive,  of 

*  Prologomena  to  Ethics.  In  his  admirable  little  work  on  "  The 
Philosophy  of  Green,"  Professor  Fairbrother  expresses  the  same  view 
of  the  method  of  Green  which  we  give  in  the  text  above — namely, 
that  it  is  essentially  a  historical  method.  From  self- reflection  we 
get  the  idea  of  the  good — we  fill  in  the  content  of  this  idea  by  an 
examination  of  history. 

f  Since  the  text -note  above  is  not  necessary  for  the  understanding 
of  the  argument  that  is  to  follow,  and  since  the  matter  of  the  note  is 
from  the  nature  of  the  theories  described  in  it  obscure  and  difficult, 
we  should  advise  the  reader  who  has  not  previously  gained  some 
knowledge  of  the  Transcendentalist  systems  from  works  on  the  History 
of  Philosophy  to  pass  over  the  note  and  proceed  to  the  argument, 
page  451. 


446  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

mind.  Will  is  "  thought  translating  itself  into  reality  "  (that 
is,  tending  to  an  end  outside  thought).  Now,  Ethics  is  the 
science  of  the  freedom  of  the  will,  for  goodness  is  freedom,* 
and  therefore  the  "  account  "  of  moral  goodness  is  the 
"  account  "  of  freedom.  What,  therefore,  is  freedom  ? 
Freedom  means  self-determination.  "  It  is  will  which 
through  thinking  gives  itself  direction  and  end,  whose  object 
is  itself,  which  therefore  is  independent  of  everything  and 
every  person  outside  itself.  Will  is  free  intelligence."  f  But 
the  self  is,  in  Hegel's  philosophy,  not  what  Kant  represented 
it  to  be — mere  Reason  or  pure  will — the  self  is  made  up  of 
Reason  and  Sense,  will  and  desire.  And  since  pure  Will  is 
the  universal  will,  and  desire  {i.e.,  the  wish  for  pleasure  or 
for  sense-objects)  the  particular  will,  or  the  will  of  the  indi- 
vidual, so  self-determination  means  the  identification  through 
conduct  of  the  individual  desire  and  the  Universal  Will. 
The  individual  can  realise  his  full  self,  Hegel  maintains,  and 
thereby  fulfil  his  duty  by  furthering  this  identification,  by 
realising  the  Universal  in  his  own  partiulcar  will.  Not, 
indeed,  that  nature  is  waiting  on  individual  caprice  for  its 
realisation  of  particular  and  Universal.  For  already  par- 
ticular and  Universal  are  identified  in  Society  or  the  State, 
and  all  that  the  individual  does  in  fulfilling  the  moral  law 
in  his  own  case  is  to  participate  in  this  process  of  identifica- 
tion of  particular  and  Universal,  the  identification  of  par- 
ticular and  Universal  being  not  only  the  end  of  all  but  the 
underlying  principle  and  the  very  Being  of  all  reality.  In 
the  moral  sphere  the  State  is  itself  this  process  of  identifica- 
tion— not  the  result  of  the  process  but  the  process  itself — 
for  in  the  State  is  realised  the  identification  of  the  many  and 
the  one,  and  the  form  of  their  unity  is  Universal  Law.  The 
State  is  the  realisation  of  the  whole  self  of  man,  particular 
and  Universal,  Will  (that  is,  pure  or  Universal  Will)  and 
Desire,  J  Reason  and  Sense.  "  The  State,"  writes  Hegel,§ 
"  which  is  the  realised  substantive  will  having  its  reality  in 


•  This  doctrine,  it  will  be  remembered,  Hegel  borrowed  from  Kant. 
See  chapter  on  Freedom,  page  209. 

t  Jodl,  "  Geschichtc  der  Ethik,"  II.,  page  108.  This  unification 
of  Reason  and  will  which  is  so  opposed  to  the  philosophy  of  Schopen- 
hauer is  also  to  be  found  in  other  philosophers — for  instance,  in 
Herbart.  According  to  this  latter  philosopher,  the  law  of  the  will — 
the  moral  law — is  grounded  not  in  will  itself,  but  in  the  judgment. 

J  The    particular    will    with    Hegel    means    "  particular    wish    for 

f>articular  object,"  and  as  object  and  subject  are  one  in  his  system, 
t  also  means  particular  subject. 

§  "  Philosophy  of  Kight  "  (translated  by  Dyde),  page  240. 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION     447 

the  particular  self-consciousness  raised  to  the  plane  of  the 
Universal,  is  absolutely  rational.  This  substantive  unity  is 
its  own  motive  and  absolute  end.  .  .  .  This  end  has  the 
highest  right  over  the  individual  whose  highest  duty  in 
turn  is  to  be  a  member  of  the  State," 

Following  then  these  three  headings  of  the  Universal  Will 
or  Universal  Self,  the  particular  Will  or  particular  Self,  and 
the  Absolute  Self  *  or  the  State,  Hegel,  in  the  "  Philosophy  of 
Right,"  divides  his  Ethical  system  into  three  parts.  In  the 
first  he  treats  of  Universal  Will  or  abstract  Will,  "  Will  with- 
out individual  interests  or  responsibilities."  This  is  the 
sphere  of  abstract  right,  for  '  theory  of  right  '  or  '  justice  ' 
is  that  domain  of  Ethics  in  which  no  account  is  taken  of 
individual  conscience  or  individual  responsibility.  The  man 
who  discharges  his  debt,  discharges  it  whether  he  intended 
to  discharge  it  or  did  not  ;  and  he  who  has  not  paid  what 
he  owes  is  still  a  debtor  even  though  he  may  not  be  blamed 
for  not  discharging  his  debt.  In  the  second  part  Hegel 
treats  of  responsibility,  sin,  conscience,  moral  good  and  evil, 
and  everything  in  the  sphere  of  Ethics  that  characterises 
the  individual  will  as  opposed  to  mere  abstract  Right.  The 
Good  Hegel  here  defines  as  the  "  idea  of  the  unity  of  the  con- 
ception of  the  Will  (i.e.,  the  universal  will)  with  the  particular 
will."  It  is  therefore  the  realisation  in  man  of  the  Absolute 
Self.  In  the  third  part  he  treats  of  "  Absolute  Will,"  of 
that,  namely,  in  which  the  identification  of  particular  wills 
with  the  Universal  Will,  of  nature  with  freedom  is  actualised. 
This  Absolute  Will  he  calls  "  Ethical  system,"  "  Ethical  ob- 
servance," "  Ethical  Custom " — i.e.,  that  outer  system, 
observance,  or  custom  which  at  once  enshrines  the  moral 
beliefs  and  principles  of  the  human  race,  and  has  actually 
become  a  law  to  the  world.  In  the  common  system  of  law 
and  custom,  particular  and  universal  are  made  one.  This 
Ethical  system  is  the  Absolute.  Ethical  observance  or 
system  has  three  forms  into  which  it  develops  in  order — viz., 
the  family,  the  civic  community,  and  the  State.  The  perfect 
form  is  the  State  ;  it  is  the  end  of  all  and  the  beginning  and 
ground  of  all.  The  State  is  even  the  underlying  principle  of 
matter  and  movement,  for  it  includes  all  things  ;  but  as 
underlying  principle  of  the  evolutionary  process  of  all  things, 
including  matter  and  movement,  the  State  does  not  manifest 
itself  to  us  as  a  State.     As  the  underlying  principle  of  all  we 

*  Hegel  calls  the  State  the  Ethical  Idea.  "  Idea  "  with  Hegel 
sic^nifies  the  concept  made  real,  or  the  universal  made  real  by  iis 
identification  with  particulars. 


44S  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

should  call  it  not  "  State  "  but  the  "  Absolute  "  simply.  As 
"  conscious  of  itself  "  as  "  will  which  thinks  and  knows  itself, 
and  carries  out  what  it  knows  in  so  far  as  it  knows,"  it  is 
called  State.  Yet  these  two — the  State  and  the  Absolute — 
are  one.  The  State  is  Absolute  Spirit.  "  The  State,"  writes 
Hegel,  "  is  the  spirit  which  abides  in  the  world,  and  there 
realises  itself  consciously  ;  while  in  nature  it  is  realised  only 
as  the  other  self  or  the  sleeping  spirit.  Only  when  it  is 
present  in  consciousness  knowing  itself  as  an  existing  object, 
is  it  State."  The  rule  of  conduct,  therefore,  is  to  obey  the 
State,  not  this  or  that  particular  State,  but  State  in  the 
abstract,  or  what  Hegel  calls  the  essential  moments  of  the 
State. 

green's  theory 

Of  Green's  theory  we  can  only  give  the  barest  outline : 
Nature,  according  to  Green,  is  unity  in  plurality.  It  is 
primarily  and  essentially  plurality,  because  its  elements  are 
distinct.  It  is  secondarily  unity,  because  nature  implies 
unity.  All  plurality  implies  relation  of  some  sort,  and  all  re- 
lation implies  unity  of  related  elements.  Nature  itself  being 
primarily  plurality,  and  there  being  nothing  in  plurality  itself 
to  make  it  one,  so  the  principle  of  unity  cannot  lie  in  nature. 
That  which  unites  two  things  in  one  must  be  distinct  from. 
the  two.  It  must,  therefore,  lie  in  Mind.  Now,  feeling 
cannot  be  the  unifying  principle,  for  feelings  are  many,  and 
they  exist  themselves  in  relation  to  one  another,  and  there- 
fore they  themselves  require  to  be  unified  by  something 
higher.  Neither  can  states  of  consciousness  be  the  unifying 
principle,  for  they,  too,  stand  in  relation  to  feeling  being 
distinguished  from  it,  and  besides  they  are  changeable  and 
are  many  themselves.  Consciousness  itself,  therefore,  is  the 
principle  of  unity,  not  the  passing  consciousness  that 
exists  and  thinks  in  time,  but  the  Eternal  Unchanging 
Consciousness,  the  timeless  Self,  which  is  one  and  whole  in 
all  things.  States  of  consciousness  may  change,  but  con- 
sciousness itself  does  not.  Pure  consciousness  then  is  the 
only  unconditioned  thing  in  nature.  It  exists  before  all 
things  else,  and  constitutes  them  all.  It  is  the  root  principle 
of  the  world,  and,  being  the  only  thing  unconditioned  by 
anything  extrinsic  to  itself,  is  the  only  originally  free  tiling 
and  the  principle  of  all  derived  freedom.  Just  so  far  then 
as  the  Eternal  Consciousness  exists  in  any  object,  so  far  is 
that  thing  free  and  good.*    As  phenomenon  man  can  never 

*  Again,  the  Kantian  principle  that  freedom  is  goodness. 


I 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  449 

be  free,  because  as  plienomenon  he  is  merely  part  of  the 
world,  and  is  therefore  conditioned.  But  he  is  free  in  so 
far  as  this  eternal  princij)le  is  in  him  working  throughout  his 
empirically  conditioned  knowledge,  and  yet  itself  not  em- 
pirical but  intelhgible.  Such  realisation  of  the  Eternal 
Consciousness  is  plainly  possible  in  thinking  subjects  ;  but 
in  bodies  it  is  realisable  only  in  so  far  as  they  approach  the 
state  of  thinking  subject — i.e.,  in  so  far  as  they  are  organised. 
Man,  in  so  far  as  he  is  thinking  subject,  can  participate 
internally  in  the  Eternal  Consciousness,  but  as  phenomenon 
he  exists,  like  everything  else,  only  as  object  of  self -conscious- 
ness. As  phenomenon  he  is  not  one  with  absolute  self- 
consciousness,  yet  exists  by  it.  Man,  therefore,  can  be  free 
in  so  far  as  he  is  one  with  the  Eternal  Consciousness — as 
noumenon  and  subject.  But  how,  it  may  be  asked,  can 
man  be  free  even  as  subject  or  noumenon  ?  Does  not  the 
will  determine  itself  by  objects  outside,  and  is  not  determina- 
tion from  without  the  very  opposite  of  self-determination  or 
freedom  ?  Green  answers  this  question  in  the  negative. 
The  will,  no  doubt,  must  in  every  act  present  to  itself  an 
object  outside  itself  to  be  desired.  But  the  will  is  neverthe- 
less not  determined  or  moved  by  such  object  but  by  the  idea 
of  the  object,  which  idea  lies  within  the  mind  and  will. 
Even  then,  in  his  desires  for  outward  things,  the  free  being 
is  self-determined. 

Now,  in  this  Eternal  Consciousness  and  its  extension  to 
man,  there  are  three  grades  or  stages — viz.,  knowledge,  will, 
and  desire.  Knowledge  requires  no  explanation.  "  Desire  " 
is  mere  solicitation  to  an  object  known  as  distinct  from  the 
"  ego."  "  Will  "  is  the  actual  choice  of  such  object.  The 
"  good  "  in  general  is  that  which  satisfies  desire  ;  the  moral 
"  good  "  in  particular  is  that  which  satisfies  the  moral  agent 
as  such,  and  the  moral  needs  are  satisfied  and  the  good 
realised  so  far  as  the  agent  approaches  the  state  of  the  think- 
ing subject — that  is,  so  far  as  he  participates  in  the  Eternal 
Self-consciousness.  And  as  this  Eternal  Self-consciousness 
is  the  constitutive  principle  of  all  things,  moral  good  is  the 
same  thing  as  self-realisation,  the  self-unfolding  of  the  eternal 
consciousness  in  our  empirical  finite  consciousness,  and  the 
consequent  identification  of  our  own  personal  consciousness 
with  the  Absolute. 

From  "  the  good  "  Green  passes  to  the  idea  of  duty.  The 
reflecting  subject  is  conscious  of  wants,  and  from  this  it 
easily  proceeds  to  the  consciousness  of  its  intended  objects. 
Traversing  therefore  the  series  of  wants  which  the  self  dis- 
tinguishes from  itself,  "  there  arises  the  idea  of  satisfaction 
Vol.  I — 29 


450  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

on  the  whole,"  an  idea  never  reahsable,  but  ever  striving  to 
reahse  itself  in  the  attainment  of  a  greater  command  over 
means  to  the  final  end,  or  to  the  full  satisfaction  of  particular 
wants.  This  idea  of  satisfaction  is  equivalent  to  "  our  good 
on  the  whole,"  and  as  it  represents  nothing  real  but  only  an 
ever  unrealisable  ideal,  it  presents  us  with  the  idea  of  what 
"  should  be  "  as  distinguished  from  "  what  is."  This  idea 
of  "  should  be  "  is  "  obligation."  The  moral  good  then  being 
that  which  will  satisfy  the  whole  of  desire,  and  not  any  mere 
particular  desire,  is  that  which  will  satisfy  the  Eternal 
principle  of  Consciousness  within  us,  that  principle  through 
which  all  finite  things  are  parts  of  the  one  timeless  unity  ; 
and  as  this  eternal  principle  of  Consciousness  is  alone  capable 
of  representing  to  itself  the  totality  of  all  desire,  the  good 
must  finally  consist  in  our  identifying  ourselves  with  the 
Eternal  Consciousness,  and  the  consequent  promotion  of  its 
final  end.  What  the  final  good  is  we  can  never  know  in 
itself ;  yet  we  know  that  it  is  the  end  of  all  motion,  all  desire, 
and  all  progress.  We  can  therefore  come  to  know  it  practically, 
if  not  theoretically — that  is,  we  can  know  the  direction  in 
which  it  lies  and  the  means  by  which  it  is  to  be  attained  by 
discovering  the  direction  in  which  the  Eternal  Consciousness 
has  already  been  progressing,  just  as  we  should  discover  the 
whole  structure  of  a  thing  by  examining  a  cross-section  of 
it.  Following  out  the  line  of  progress  that  has  brought  man- 
kind to  his  present  elevated  position  in  the  finite  world  we 
are  sure  to  be  travelling  towards  the  final  end  of  all,  and  of 
promoting  that  end,  even  though  we  do  not  ourselves 
personally  reach  it. 

The  final  end  is  the  unconditioned  good.  What  the  un- 
conditioned good  is  Green  cannot  say.  If  you  ask  me,  says 
Green,  what  this  unconditioned  good  is,  I  can  only  tell  you 
it  is  what  the  good  will  seeks,  and  if  you  ask  me  what  the 
good  will  seeks,  I  can  only  tell  you  it  is  the  unconditioned 
good.  This  argument  is  a  vicious  circle,  as  Green  admits, 
but  it  is  one  that  arises  necessarily  out  of  the  case.  It  is  a 
fallacy,  he  maintains,  but  a  justifiable  fallacy,  since  in  the 
system  which  he  inculcates,  the  same  thing  is  both  means 
and  end — and  we  can  only  define  the  end  in  terms  of  its 
imperfect  realisation  in  the  means. 

The  end,  therefore,  though  unknown,  may  still  be  furthered 
by  the  adoption  of  tlie  means  that  lead  to  it.  Tlicse  means 
are  our  existing  laws  and  institutions  and  the  line  of  develop- 
ment that  has  led  to  them.  Following  this  line  of  develop- 
ment we  shall  keep  ever  approaching  to  the  end  more  and 
more  closely — but  wc  can  never  reach  it. 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  451 

(b)    CRITICISM      OF      THE      ETHICS      OF      TRANSCENDENTAL 
EVOLUTION  * 

(i)  Our  first  point  of  criticism  will  concern  the  general 
theory  of  Transcendental  Evolution  that  all  things  are 
an  evolution  from  a  single  Unity,  named  by  the  Tran- 
scendentalists  the  Absolute.  (2)  Our  second  point  con- 
cerns the  theory  that  morality. is  only  a  phase  in  this 
supposed  universal  process  of  evolution.  (3)  Thirdly, 
we  shall  briefly  refer  to  some  of  the  main  points  in  the 
two  systems  described  in  our  text  note. 

(i)  Evolution,  if  it  exists,  and  so  far  as  it  exists,  is  a 
fact  of  nature,  a  movement  of  things  from  a  lower  con- 
dition to  a  higher,  and,  Hke  any  other  movement,  it, 
and  the  laws  which  direct  it,  if  such  laws  exist,  should 
be  capable  of  being  seen  or  discovered  by  our  ordinary 
faculties  of  apprehension  and  of  Reason.  We  have  no 
more  right  to  postulate  the  existence  of  an  evolutionary 
law  in  nature  which  we  have  not  seen  or  proved  than  we 
have  to  postulate  the  existence  of  fruit  or  leaves  in  iron, 
or  a  faculty  of  thought  in  stones,  or  any  other  such 
unexperienced  phenomenon.  Also  the  extent  of  evolu- 
tion, if  a  law  of  evolution  should  be  shown  to  exist,  is 
to  be  determined  not  by  a  priori  reasoning  nor  by 
arbitrary  imagination,  but  by  actual  empirical  investi- 
gation and  reasoning  upon  observed  phenomena.  We 
must  not  extend  the  law  of  evolution  to  stones  since  we 
do  not  see  them  evolving,  nor  assume  that  a  dead  plant 
still  grows  and  evolves  when  it  is  too  plain  that  it 
cannot  now  do  so.  Evolution,  if  it  be  true,  is  a  fact, 
and  facts  must  be  either  seen  or  proved  before  we  can 
assume   their   existence   or   build   our   reasonings   upon 

*  We  warn  the  reader  that  he  ought  not  to  expect  too  much  in 
the  way  of  positive  refutation  here.  It  is  easy  to  formulate  theories 
that  are  not  grounded  on  any  fact  of  experience  or  principle  of  Reason. 
But  often  it  is  not  easy  by  positive  argument  to  refute  such  theories. 
Nor  is  it  necessary  to  do  so.  Sensible  men  will  always  be  content 
if  it  is  shown  that  a  theory  is  not  supported  by  satisfying  proofs 
either  deductive  or  inductive — in  other  words  that  it  is  merely  assumed 
and  imaginary. 


452  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

them  or  explain  anything  by  means  of  them.  These 
are  only  the  plain  requirements  of  Reason  and  common 
sense,  and  they  are  necessary  presuppositions  of  any 
science,  whether  physical  or  moral. 

Now,  these  presuppositions  are  flatly  contradicted  by 
the  system  of  Philosophy  which  we  are  at  present  con- 
sidering. For,  in  the  first  place,  the  Absolute  itself, 
which  is  supposed  to  be  the  ground  unity  of  all  exist- 
ence, in  which  all  things  subsist  as  parts  or  moments  or 
phases — whatever  be  the  name  we  give  to  the  individual 
things  within  it — is  a  gratuitous  hypothesis.  It  is 
neither  seen,  nor  felt,  nor  is  its  existence  proved  by 
reasoning  upon  observed  phenomena.  It  is  not  neces- 
sary as  an  explanation  of  any  admitted  facts.  It  is 
itself  not  only  a  contradiction,  but  a  sum  of  contradic- 
tions. For  instance,  it  issues  particular  judgments  and 
the  opposite  of  these  judgments  at  one  and  the  same 
moment  in  different  people.  It  not  merely  exists  in  one 
man  and  m  another,  but  it  is  one  and  the  other.*  It  is 
also  the  unity  of  both  and  at  the  same  time  their 
diversity,  for  unless  it  is  everything  that  is,  it  is  not 
the  Absolute.  It  is  one  and  simple,  for  through  it  all 
things  are  reduced  to  unity,  and  yet  all  things  are  parts 
of  it  and  subsist  through  it — subsist  through  it  and  com- 
pose it  even  in  their  diversity.  It  is,  therefore,  one 
and  many  secundum  idem.  On  this  impossible  concep- 
tion is  grounded  the  theory  of  Transcendental  Evolu- 
tion. 

Again,  as  the  Absolute  itself  is  something  merely 
imagined,  so  also  is  the  evolutionary  process  by  which 
it  develops  into  the  manifold  objects  of  the  universe 
merely  imagined.  But  imagination  is  not  the  proper 
instrument  of  empirical  science,  nor,  indeed,  of  any 
science,  and  we  have  no  right  to  postulate  the  existence 
of  an  evolutionary  process  in  the  world  unless  we  can 
see  it  definitely  at  work  or  can  prove  its  presence  by 

•  "  A  separation  between  tlie  Absolute  and  finite  Beings  is  meaning- 
less "  (Bradley,  "  Appearance  and  Reality,"  page  418). 


I 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  453 

our  Reason.  Everything  in  this  world  is  either  a 
development  from  some  perfectly  definable  thing  not 
the  Absolute,  or  it  has  not  developed  at  all.  The  plant 
grows  from  the  seed,  the  seed  is  shed  by  the  living 
plant.  There  the  process  of  evolution  is  complete  and 
circumscribed.  There  is  no  doubt  about  where  it  begins 
and  ends.  The  plant  can  only  develop  out  of  the  seed, 
the  seed  is  a  development  of  the  plant  alone.  Neither 
develops  out  of  any  other  thing.  If  the  process  of 
development  began  at  all  it  began  with  the  making  of 
one  of  these  two  things,  not  with  something  which  is 
neither  plant  nor  seed.  Nature  presents  many  such 
circumscribed  evolutionary  processes  in  living  things. 
We  may  even,  for  the  sake  of  argument,  allow  that  one 
species  develops  out  of  another.  But  every  such 
evolved  thing  develops  out  of  some  definable  thing 
upon  this  earth,  and  not  out  of  any  other  thing,  it 
develops  from  something  which  we  can  see  or  know 
and  that  from  which  the  known  objects  of  this  world 
develop  is  certainly  not  the  Absolute.  But  thousands  of 
things  never  develop,  and  could  not  have  developed 
out  of  any  other  thing.  There  is  nothing  in  the  Uni- 
verse, then,  that  offers  the  slightest  ground  for  believing 
either  that  all  things  evolve  or  that  all  things  have  come 
from  one  thing,  particularly  from  one  absolute  thing 
which  we  do  not  know,  and  which  is  full  of  contradic- 
tions, a  thing  which  still  maintains  its  unity  whilst  it 
is  the  ground  and  inner  Being  of  the  manifold  things 
into  which  it  has  evolved. 

We  should  remark,  however,  that  the  transcendental 
evolutionists  not  only  suppose  the  existence  of  such  a 
universal  process  of  evolution  as  is  here  described,  but 
actually  describe  the  laws  according  to  wliich  it  takes 
place,  which  laws  they  deduce  not  from  observation,  but 
from  the  conception  of  the  unknown  and  unintelligible 
Absolute  itself,  such  as  the  law  formulated  by  Hegel 
that  each  thing  passes  into  its  opposite,  only  to  return 
upon  itself  again  in  its  higher  form  of  the  unity  of  its 


454  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

former  self  and  the  opposite  of  its  former  self.  These 
laws  do  not  require  further  discussion.  An  imagined 
Absolute  evolving  according  to  imagined  laws  cannot, 
we  venture  to  suggest,  be  accepted  as  the  ground  and 
principle  of  any  science,  much  less  the  natural  science 
of  Ethics. 

(2)  This  brings  us  to  our  second  point.  Morality,  we 
claim,  is  not  a  phase  in  the  supposed  e\'olutionary 
process  of  the  Absolute  unfolding  itself  into  the  mani- 
fold objects  of  the  Universe.  This  proposition  we 
might  establish  according  to  a  variety  of  considerations. 
The  following  two  will  suffice :  {a)  Morality  is  an 
attribute  of  the  individual  person.  It  is  the  individual 
person  that  is  under  obligation  to  do  certain  things. 
It  is  the  acts  of  the  individual  that  are  good  or  bad. 
The  individual  alone  is  morally  responsible  for  his 
acts.  There  is  no  common  receptacle  for  the  moral 
responsibilities  of  the  acts  of  different  men.  Our 
responsibilities  are  not  interchangeable  nor  continuous 
with  one  another.  My  responsibilities  are  my  own, 
as  my  wishes  and  actions  are  my  own.  Now,  if  the 
ground  reality  of  all  men  be  one,  and  if  the  "  good  " 
means  identification  with  this  ground  reality,  then  my 
responsibilities  are  not  my  own,  for,  a  common  sub- 
stance can  originate  only  common  responsibilities.  (6) 
Again,  a  moral  being  directs  and  controls  his  individual 
acts.  But  if  all  men  and  all  actions  are  but  necessaril}/ 
evolved  phases  of  one  original  object  or  condition,  then 
I  no  more  control  my  individual  actions  than  I  control 
my  own  existence  or  my  entry  into  this  world,  and 
hence  I  am  not  more  moral  than  animal  or  tree  or  stone. 

Morality,  then,  is  not  a  phase  in  the  evolution  of  the 
Absolute  into  the  manifold  objects  of  the  Universe. 

(3)  We  shall  now  briefly  criticise  the  chief  point  of 
the  two  Transcendental  systems  given  above,  as  to  the 
nature  of  the  good — namely,  Hegel's  view  that  the  good 
is  the  identification  of  the  particular  with  the  universal 
will  or  the  State  ;  and  Green's  view  that  the  good  means 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  455 

the  reproduction  of  the  Eternal  Self-Consciousness  in 
us  through  approach  to  the  final  end  of  the  Eternal  Self- 
Consciousness,  or  to  that  end  which  will  supply  the 
totality  of  wants.  Our  criticism  of  Green  will  also 
include  other  references  to  his  theory  of  man's  final 
end. 

Hegel's  View — (a)  We  have  already  clearly  shown 
that  the  good  is  not  and  cannot  be  identity  of  or  rela- 
tion of  any  kind  between  the  particular  and  the  uni- 
versal will  or  the  State.*  The  good  individual  will  is 
the  will  that  tends  to  the  final  natural  end  of  the  indi- 
vidual, not  the  will  that  identifies  itself  with  any  other 
will,  even  though  that  other  includes  the  individual 
will.  Even  then,  if  it  were  certain  that  what  is  called 
the  universal  will  was  good  in  itself,  an  individual  will 
would  still  be  good  only  in  so  far  as  it  sought  the  natural 
ends  of  its  own  individual  natural  capacities.  Hence, 
goodness  cannot  consist  in  fulfilment  of  the  end  of  the 
universal  will. 

(6)  The  good  will  of  an  individual  man  is  individual 
and  particular.  For  it  is  the  same  will  which  is 
responsible  for  evil  and  which  merits  by  the  doing  of 
the  good.  Now,  the  evil  will  is,  on  the  theory  of  the 
transcendentalists,  essentially  particular,  essentially  un- 
identified with  the  Universal  (the  Universal  cannot  be 
evil),  therefore,  the  good  will  is  particular  also,  and  is 
not  identified  with  the  universal  will. 

(c)  There  is  no  such  thing  as  a  universal  will.  There 
is  no  abstract  State  comprising  in  itself  all  individual 
States  and  the  ground  of  all.  All  existing  States  and 
all  existing  wills  are  particular.  This  we  have  had 
occasion  to  remark  more  than  once  before  in  this  work. 
To  prove  this  proposition  would,  of  course,  be  quite 
outside  the  scope  of  a  work  like  the  present.  But  the 
reader  will,  we  think,  not  need  proof  to  understand  this 
at  least,  that  the  existence  of  a  universal  will  such  as  is 
supposed  by  Hegel  is  a  pure  hypothesis,  that  it  could 

♦  See  previous  chapter,  page  32  j 


456  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

not  be  established  by  reasoning,  and  that  consequently 
an  Ethics  built  upon  such  a  theory  can  never  have  more 
than  a  suppositional  value. 

(d)  But  whether  a  universal  will  exists  or  not,  an 
identification  of  particular  and  universal  wills,  of  my 
own  with  the  eternal  will  by  individual  effort,  is  a  sheer 
impossibility.  Identity  of  end  might,  indeed,  be  theo- 
retically possible — that  is,  their  ends  might  be  made  con- 
formable to  one  another,  but  identity  of  being  would  not 
be  possible  even  theoretically.  For  the  Absolute  Will 
and  the  will  of  the  individual  are  not  only  different 
entities,  they  are  the  very  contrary  of  each  other.  One 
particular  will  could  not  become  identical  with  another 
particular  will,  a  fortiori  it  could  not  become  identical 
with  the  universal  will.  There  is  a  sense,  indeed,  in 
which  a  universal  is  recognised  in  the  singular  even 
according  to  the  teaching  of  Aristotle — namely,  by 
participation.  In  this  sense  a  universal  is  realised  in 
all  the  singulars  that  participate  in  it,  as  whiteness  is 
realised  to  some  extent  in  each  white  object.  But  it 
never  does  and  never  could  become  identical  with  the 
particular.  Nothing  can  be  identical  with  its  contrary. 
This  latter  principle,  that  "  nothing  can  be  its  contrary," 
Hegel  would,  of  course,  deny  ;  but  we  think  we  are  safe 
in  assuming  it,  and  if  we  are  not  allowed  to  do  so  then 
argument  becomes  impossible,  since  otherwise  no  term, 
and  no  proposition,  could  have  any  meaning. 

Hegel's  theory,  therefore,  of  identification  of  universal 
and  particular  is  quite  different  from  Aristotle's  theory 
of  participation,  and  whereas  the  latter  represents  a 
truth  of  common  sense,  the  former  is  a  contradiction 
and  impossible.  There  is  no  conceivable  sense,  then,  in 
which  Hegel's  theory  of  the  individual  effort  to  make 
the  individual  will  identical  with  the  universal  could 
represent  anything  even  theoretically  possible.  Much 
less  could  it  be  made  a  practical  rule  of  morals. 

Green's  View. — Green's  theory  contains  the  following 
assumptions :     {a)   That    the   "  good "    consists   in   the 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  457 

reproduction  of  the  Absolute  or  Divine  Consciousness  in 
ourselves  :  (b)  that  we  can  reproduce  this  consciousness, 
and  therefore  be  morally  good,  by  the  realisation,  so 
far  as  lies  in  us,  of  the  end  of  the  Absolute  ;  (c)  that 
the  final  good  is  not  actually  attainable,  that  we  may 
always  continue  to  move  towards  it,  but  never  reach 
it ;  (d)  that  the  final  end  is  not  itself  knowable,  but 
(e)  that  it  is  possible  to  move  towards  this  end  by  con- 
tinuing to  follow  the  same  line  of  development  which 
human  law  and  human  institutions  have  followed  in 
the  past,  those  laws  and  institutions  which  have  brought 
man  and  society  to  their  present  perfection. 

{a)  To  the  fust  of  these  assumptions  we  reply — if  the 
Absolute  or  timeless  Self  *  is  the  principle  of  all  that  is, 
if  everything  is  but  a  phase  of  the  Absolute,  then  the 
Absolute  is  present  in  or  is  reproduced  in  every  desire 
and  in  every  object  ;  and  since,  according  to  Green, 
the  "  good  "  is  the  reproduction  of  the  Absolute  it 
follows  that  every  object  is  a  good  object  and  the  desire 
of  every  object  is  a  good  desire.  On  Green's  theory, 
therefore,  a  distinction  between  good  and  evil  acts  is 
quite  impossible. 

On  this  point — that  is,  on  the  relation  of  the  Absolute 
to  evil  (the  evil  under  consideration  being  certain  selfish 


*  The  metaphysical  question  of  the  existence  of  an  Eternal  Self 
immanent  in  the  world  cannot  be  fully  discussed  here.  Some  salient 
remarks  concerning  it  are  given  in  Prof.  Taylor's  "  Problems  of  Con- 
duct," page  70.  "  What  evidence  then,"  he  writes,  "  does  Green 
supply  which  leads  us  to  affirm  the  underived  character,  not  merely 
of  consciousness,  but  of  the  '  self  '  ?  As  far  as  I  comprehend  his 
reasonings  all  the  evidence  for  this  important  transition  is  afforded 
by  the  consideration  that  a  series  of  related  events  cannot  possibly 
become  aware  of  itself  as  a  related  series."  Taylor's  criticism  of  this 
argument  is,  taking  Green's  premisses  that  the  series  could  not  know 
itself  as  a  related  series  for  granted,  the  following  :  "  All  that  has 
really  been  proved  aboat  the  relation  of  the  knowing  self  to  the  time 
series  is  that  it  is  not  one  of  the  presentations  which  succeed  one 
another  in  the  course  of  our  experience — in  fact,  that  the  centre  of 
our  personal  identity  is,  relatively  to  the  changing  presentations  which 
I  make  up  the  series  of  our  perceptions  and  thoughts,  permanent  in 
time,  not  that  it  is  eternal  or  independent  of  duration."  As  it  stands 
no  argument  could  more  faithfully  reproduce  the  Scholastic  view  of 
the  soul  or  knowing  subject  than  Prof.  Taylor's  argument. 


458  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

tendencies  in  man) — Sorley  writes  *  :  "  Green  does  not 
even  ask  the  question  whether  these  "  (tendencies  to 
exalt  selfish  interest  over  common  welfare,  tendencies 
which,  as  we  say,  Sorley  considers  evil)  "  are  not  to 
be  considered  manifestations  or  reproductions  of  the 
Eternal  Self-Consciousness.  But  his  metaphysical  view 
does  not  exclude  them,  and,  if  they  are  included, 
morality  disappears  for  lack  of  a  criterion  between 
good  and  evil.  If  good  is  to  be  discriminated  from 
evil  it  must  be  by  some  other  means  than  by  describing 
the  whole  conscious  activity  of  man  as  a  reproduction 
of  the  divine." 

Professor  Sorley  points  out  that  Bradley  is  more 
consistent  on  this  point  than  Green,  since  Bradley, 
who,  like  Green,  regards  the  good  as  in  a  certain  sense 
the  realisation  of  the  absolute,  "  brings  out  the  conse- 
quences which  in  Green  is  more  or  less  concealed  that 
the  evil  equally  with  the  good  in  man  and  the  world 
are  appearances  of  the  absolute."   f 

Evil,  therefore,  is,  if  Green's  theory  be  consistent, 
quite  as  much  a  part  or  as  much  a  development  of  the 
Absolute  as  the  "  good  "  is,  and  hence  the  good  as 
opposed  to  evil  cannot  consist  in  the  reproduction  of  the 
Absolute.  We  can  also  urge,  in  opposition  to  Green's 
theory  of  the  good,  the  same  arguments  by  which  we 
have  already  disproved  Hegel's  theory  that  the  good 
consists  in  the  identification  of  the  individual  and 
Universal  or  Absolute  Will. 

{b)  To  Green's  second  assumption  we  reply  :  A  man's 
good  must  consist  in  the  attainment  of  his  own  end, 
not  in  the  end  of  something  other  than  himself — that 
is,  wc  determine  the  good  of  the  individual  by  a  con- 
sideration of  his  own  individual  capacities.  Now, 
whether  or  not  the  ends  of  our  individual  capacities 
are  identical  with  the  aims  of  the  universal  conscious- 
ness Green  does  not  determine,  and  consequently  it  is 

•  "  Recent  Tendencies  in  Ethics,"  page  99, 
f  Ibid.,  page  loi, 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  459 

not  lawful  for  him  to  assume  that  the  good  of  the  indi- 
vidual consists  in  the  promotion  of  the  aims  of  the 
universal  consciousness,  even  though  the  individual  be 
included  in  that  consciousness. 

(c)  To  the  third  we  reply  :  The  good  or  the  end  is 
the  fulfilment  of  a  natural  capacity — and  since  nature  * 
does  not  give  a  capacity  for  an  object  that  cannot  be 
attained,  it  follows  that  the  end  of  man  is  attainable. 

Again,  the  ends  of  all  inferior  beings — for  instance, 
of  trees  and  animals — are  attainable.  But  if  the  end  of 
a  tree  or  animal  is  attainable  can  we  hold  that  the  end 
of  man  is  unattainable — that  the  highest  thing  in 
nature  is  the  only  unfinished  thing  ?  If,  therefore,  on 
Green's  theory,  man's  good  is  unattainable,  then  the 
"  good,"  as  Green  conceives  it,  cannot  be  man's  good. 

(d)  The  final  end  of  anything  is  the  final  end  of  its 
highest  capacity.  Thus  the  final  end  of  a  tree  is  not 
growth  but  flowering  and  seeding.  So  also  the  highest 
end  of  an  animal  is  the  end  of  its  sensitive  powers,  since 
sense  is  the  highest  capacity  of  an  animal.  In  the  same 
way  the  final  end  of  man  must  be  the  end  of  his  rational 
will,  since  will  is  our  highest  appetite.  But  the  end  of 
the  rational  will  must  be  something  which  the  intellect 
is  capable  of  conceiving,  for  the  will  can  desire  and  tend 
to  that  only  which  the  intellect  can  conceive.  Hence, 
the  final  end  of  man  is  conceivable  by  man. 

(e)  We  move,  according  to  Green,  towards  our  final 
end  (even  though  we  can  never  reach  it)  when  in  our 
conduct  we  follow  the  line  of  development  which  marks 
the  history  of  conduct  in  the  past. 

Now,  the  difficulties  here  are  many — (a)  Has  there 
been  development  ?  We  claim  that  it  is  impossible,  so 
far  as  the  primary  laws  of  nature  are  concerned,  to  find 
any  line  of  development  in  the  history  of  past  human 
conduct  or  human  laws.  Even  M.  Levy-Bruhl  (an 
ardent  evolutionist)  admits  that  the  essential  laws  were 
the  same  in  the  days  of  Egyptian  greatness  that  they 

♦  For  explanation  of  this  principle  see  pages  72  and  86, 


46o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

are  to-day.  We  have,  however,  ah"eady  said  that  the 
derived  precepts  of  the  moral  law  may  change.  We 
know,  for  instance,  that  monogyny  is  more  universally 
practised  now  than  it  was  in  the  days  of  Aristotle.  But 
are  changes  in  the  secondary  laws  of  morals  due  to 
evolution  ?  We  believe  not.  It  seems  evident  from 
history  that  these  changes  have  been  effected  in  the 
main  not  by  evolution  but  from  the  two  following 
principal  causes :  First,  because  with  time  and  ex- 
perience we  have  learnt  to  think  more  truly  about 
human  needs,  and  how  they  are  to  be  satisfied,  than 
we  formerly  did  :  also  we  consult  the  higher  needs, 
those,  viz.,  of  the  civilised  life,  more  fully  than  was 
formerly  the  case  :  and,  secondly,  because  of  Christ's 
positive  teaching.  Of  these  two  reasons  the  latter  is 
perhaps  the  principal.  But  Christ's  teaching  was  not  a 
result  of  evolution.  There  was  nothing  in  previous 
history  that  could  logically  be  said  to  have  led  up  to 
it  ;  nothing,  for  instance,  that  led  up  to  Christ's  Sermon 
on  the  Mount,  or  to  His  teaching  on  marriage. 

Whatever  advancement,  therefore,  has  taken  place  in 
morals  and  moral  ideas  as  regards  the  secondary  laws 
or  the  laws  of  greater  human  perfection  is  not  to  be 
explained  by  evolution.  The  change  that  has  taken 
place  in  our  moral  ideals  is,  in  the  first  place,  a  change 
from  false  to  true,  from  inadequate  to  adequate  thinking 
on  good  and  evil,  and  second,  a  change  consequent  on 
the  introduction  of  Christ's  positive  teaching. 

{^)  The  necessity  for  a  moral  criterion  is  not  a  neces- 
sity of  to-day  only.  It  was  a  necessity  for  Aristotle 
and  for  ethicians  and  legislators  before  Aristotle.  Yet 
Aristotle  did  not  follow  Green's  criterion.  He  deter- 
mines what  is  good  for  man,  as  we  do,  by  an  analysis 
of  human  nature  and  its  needs,  not  by  an  appeal  to 
previous  history.  Nor  docs  he  refer  to  anyone  before 
him  who  appealed  to  history  for  the  determination  of 
the  moral  law.  Rules  of  conduct,  therefore,  have  been 
determined  not  from  previous  conduct,  but  from  Kcason. 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION     461 

In  other  words,  in  the  formulation  of  the  moral  law, 
Reason  does  not  follow  history,  but  makes  it. 

(7)  All  that  has  been  said  in  proof  of  our  view  already 
given,  that  in  framing  the  moral  law  we  must  follow 
certain  rational  criteria,  is  itself  proof  that  the  method 
of  Ethics  is  primarily  a  method  of  rational  deduction, 
and  not  the  historical  method — that  is,  that  the  moral 
law  cannot  be  determined  exclusively  by  any  reference 
to  past  human  conduct  as  such  or  to  past  development. 
But  Green's  theory  is  essentially  grounded  upon  the 
historical  method. 

These  are  only  a  few  of  our  reasons  for  rejecting 
Green's  evolutionary  theory.* 

NOTE    ON    THE   TRANSCENDENTAL-EVOLUTIONIST   VIEW   OF 
SELF-REALISATION 

"  Self-Realisation,"  in  the  works  of  transcendental 
Evolutionists,  is  used  to  signify  the  realisation  or 
development  of  the  "  Total  Self  "  of  the  individual — 
that  is,  the  attainment  of  the  ends  of  the  "  Total 
Self,"  and  (in  this  theory)  the  Total  Self  includes, 
besides  the  individual  selves,  the  "  Universal  Self," 
which,  we  are  told,  is  the  true  Being  of  the  individual. 

Our  view  of  this  theory,  as  we  have  already  said,  is 
that  common  sense  refuses  to  recognise  the  individual 
man  as  being  one  with  the  "  Universal  Consciousness  " 
or  "  Universal  Humanity."  The  Universal  Conscious- 
ness is  not  the  man's  "  self."  The  self  is  simply  the 
rational  individual.  Destroy  the  rational  individual — a 
thing  which  is  neither  inconceivable  nor  metaphysically 
impossible — and  you  destroy  a  complete  self.  The  self 
is  the  principle  of  thought  and  action.     It  is  that  which 

♦  At  the  conclusion  of  this  long  argument  on  Evolutionary  Ethics 
we  may  be  permitted  to  point  out  that  it  was  impossible  for  us  to 
notice  every  argument  for  and  against  the  Evolutionary  theory,  but 
we  have  tried  to  bring  out  the  main  points  on  each  side,  and  we  hope 
that  our  argument  will  be  suggestive  to  students  in  their  further 
readings  on  this  subject. 


462  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

thinks  and  acts.  But  only  the  individual  can  think  and 
act.  It  is  not  tree-in-gcneral  but  this  tree  that  grows 
and  decays.  It  is  not  self-in-general  or  a  universal  self 
but  this  particular  self  that  thinks,  desires,  and  moves. 
The  self,  then,  and  the  individual  man  are  one  ;  and 
self-realisation,  if  such  a  thing  is  possible,  will  be  the 
realisation,  in  some  way,  of  the  individual  rational 
man.* 

If  by  self-realisation  is  meant  the  attainment  of  a 
natural  end  outside  of  ourselves,  then  self-realisation  is 
not  only  a  possible  end  to  man  but  is  also  his  bounden 
duty.  But  to  transcendentalists  self-realisation  seems 
to  mean  something  more.  It  seems  to  include  the 
realisation  of  our  constitutive  substance.  But  this  is 
evidently  not  our  end,  as  we  saw  in  our  second  chapter. 
Our  bodies  may,  indeed,  grow  in  substance,  but  the 
body  is  not  our  highest  end.  Our  soul  does  not  grow  in 
substance.  Its  only  realisation  is  the  fulfilment  of  its 
natural  capacities,  and  the  end  of  our  highest  mental 
capacities  lies,  as  we  saw,  beyond  the  self.  Apart,  then, 
from  the  realisation  of — that  is,  the  attainment  of — 
ends  beyond  ourselves  it  is  absurd  to  speak  of  the 
realisation  of  the  self  as  our  final  end. 

There  are  senses,  then,  other  than  that  of  the  Trans- 
cendental Evolutionists  in  which  self-realisation  is  some- 

*  Other  Ethicians  also  besides  the  Transcendentalists  insist  that 
the  individual  as  such  is  never  a  self,  that  the  only  self  is  the  person. 
They  draw  two  distinctions  between  individual  and  person.  First, 
that  the  individual  is  as  such  purely  egoistic,  whereas  the  person  or 
rational  being  is  altruistic  also.  Secondly,  that  the  individual  is, 
as  such,  simply  a  number  of  unrelated  impulses,  whereas  the  person 
is  in  himself  an  organised  body  of  impulses,  and,  in  relation  to  others, 
is  a  part  of  the  larger  organisation  of  society.  With  these  writers 
self-realisation  means  realisation  of  the  person,  and,  therefore,  of  the 

Krson  as  altruistic.  (Prof.  Seth  is  one  of  this  school.  See  his  "  Ethical 
inciples,"  page  205.)  These  writers  also  claim  that,  as  individual, 
man  wishes  for  pleasure  only,  but  that,  as  person  or  rational  being, 
he  is  determined  by  the  conception  of  duty. 

Now  we  have  no  hesitation  in  saying  that  the  contrast  here  drawn 
between  the  individual  and  the  person  is  wholly  groundless.  The 
person  is  simply  a  rational  individual ;  but  Reason  is  an  individual 
faculty  in  cacli  man,  and  every  act  of  reason  is  individual.  The 
rational  self,  then,  is  essentially  individual. 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  463 

times  possible,  and  there  are  senses  in  which  it  may  be 
said  that  self-reaHsation  is  a  duty.  This  leads  us  out- 
side the  discussion  of  Transcendental  Evolution,  but  it 
will  be  useful  to  explain  what  precisely  is  implied  in 
"  self-realisation  "  in  so  far  as  it  is  really  our  end. 

Self-realisation  is  our  end  in  so  far  as  it  imphes  the 
attainment  by  man  of  his  end  as  a  rational  being.  When- 
ever we  attain  an  object  or  end  it  may  be  said  that  we 
"  realise  ourselves,"  inasmuch  as  we  realise  the  fulfil- 
ment of  a  capacity  of  ourselves.  Perfect  self-realisation 
means  the  perfect  fulfilment  of  our  natural  capacities 
by  the  attainment  of  the  ends  of  those  natural 
capacities.  Now,  what  precisely  is  implied  in  the 
realisation  of  our  natural  capacities  ?  It  includes  two 
things,  (i)  The  use  of  our  faculties  for  their  natural 
ends  only.  (2)  The  use  of  them  not  as  separate  and 
unrelated  faculties,  but  as  the  parts  of  an  organism. 
In  this  sense  to  realise  the  self  means  simply  to  act  up 
to  the  natural  laws  of  the  self.  This  sense  of  "  self- 
realisation  "  has  been  very  well  brought  out  in  a  note 
on  Aquinas'  "  Summa  Contra  Gentiles "  by  Father 
Rickaby.  Writing  of  the  actuality  of  the  Infinite,  he  says 
"  It  does  not  follow  from  this  "  (the  actuality  of  all 
God's  powers)  "  that  human  perfection  is  perfect  self- 
realisation  in  the  sense  of  every  power  being  realised 
to  the  utmost.  The  powers  of  man  are  many,  not  all 
of  equally  high  quality.  The  utmost  realisation  of  one 
might  and  would  interfere  with  the  realisation  of 
another  :  the  baser  might  be  brought  out  to  the  loss 
of  a  nobler  and  better  ;  the  perfection  of  man  is  a 
harmony  of  powers,  which  implies  both  use  and  re- 
straint of  them  severally  according  to  the  excellence 
of  their  several  functions.  In  man,  much  must  be 
left  in  potentiality  if  the  best  actuality  that  he  is  capable 
of  is  to  be  realised.  In  an  orchestra,  where  every  instru- 
ment is  played  (or  brayed)  continuously  at  its  loudest, 
the  result  would  be  din  indescribable,  a  maximum  of 
noise  with  a  minimum  of  music.     Perfection  is  actuality 


464  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

up  to  standard.  In  a  finite  nature  the  standard  imposes 
limitations  according  to  the  AristoteHan  canon  of  the 
golden  mean,  a  canon  not  framed  for  the  infinite."  * 

As  Rickaby  says,  in  realising  the  capabilities  of  any 
organism,  "  much  must  be  left  in  potentiality."  It  is 
plain  that  in  any  one  man  each  and  all  his  capacities 
cannot  be  exercised  in  their  fulness.  A  man  could  not 
exercise  his  capacity  for  knowledge  in  all  departments 
of  knowledge.  No  man  could  be  ph3^sicist,  mathe- 
matician, metaphysician,  historian,  &c.,  though  most 
men  have  capacities  for  all  or  many  of  these  things. 
But,  is  a  man  bound  to,  at  least,  a  partial  exercise  of 
every  natural  capacity  ?  This  question  is  answered  by 
Aquinas,  who  distinguishes  between  capacities  that 
appertain  to  the  good  of  the  individual  and  those  that 
appertain  to  the  good  of  the  race.  Not  every  individual 
is  bound  to  the  exercise  of  the  latter  kind  of  capacity, 
except  in  the  case  of  danger  to  the  race.  For  instance, 
ordinarily,  no  individual  man  is  bound  to  marry  ;  the 
good  of  the  race,  indeed,  requires  marriage,  but  the 
attainment  of  this  end  is  imposed  as  an  obligation  on 
the  human  race  as  a  whole,  not  on  each  individual.  But 
every  individual  is  bound  to  make  some  use  of  those 
capacities  which  appertain  to  his  own  good.f  The  law 
of  self-realisation  thus  outlined  by  the  scholastic  philo- 
sophy is  founded  not  on  any  mere  metaphysical  hypo- 
thesis like  that  of  the  Universal  Self  in  man,  but  on  the 
organic   nature   of   man   as   empirically   known   to   us. 


*  Rickaby — "  God  and  His  Creatures,"  page  22,  note. 

t  Many  of  our  capacities  are  only  a  means  to  other  capacities,  and 
provided  these  latter  capacities  are  duly  exercised  we  cannot  see  that 
the  capacity  which  is  only  means  must  necessarily  be  exercised. 
Eating  is  only  a  means  to  self-maintenance,  and  if  a  man  could  secure 
this  end  without  recourse  to  food  we  cannot  believe  that  he  is  strictly 
bound  to  cat.  In  one  sense  all  our  faculties  are  only  a  means  to  our 
highest  end,  and  provided  that  a  man  can  develop  personally  and 
can  also  fulfil  his  duties  to  the  race  without  exercising  a  particular 
faculty,  we  do  not  see  how  we  can  constrain  a  man  to  exercise  it, 
particularly  if  by  its  non-exercise  he  has  a  better  chance  of  doing 
some  other  greater  good  and  a  consequent  better  chance  of  attaining 
his  final  end.     See  Vol.  II.,  page  392,  nute^ 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  465 

Also,  unlike  the  theory  of  the  Universal  Self,  the 
scholastic  theory  affords  us  a  practical  criterion  of 
good. 

CONCLUSION 

We  have  now  passed  in  review  some  of  the  principal 
evolutionary  theories  of  Morals.  We  have  examined 
Spencer's  system  and  shown  that  moral  conduct  is  not 
highly  evolved  animal  conduct,  that  the  final  end  is 
not  increase  of  life,  and  that  the  "  good  "  is  not  the 
same  as  "  adaptation  to  environment."  In  our  ex- 
amination of  Psychological  Evolution  we  showed  that 
our  moral  opinions  are  not  evolved  from  associated 
feelings  of  pleasure  and  pain,  and  that  whatever  change 
may  have  taken  place  in  our  moral  opinions  that  change 
is  not  to  be  regarded  as  an  evolutionary  change  from 
mere  sensible  association  between  feelings  to  intellectual 
appreciation  of  principles,  but  simply  as  a  change  from 
false  to  true  thinking.  In  our  account  of  Transcendental 
Evolution  we  showed  that  moral  goodness  is  something 
that  belongs  to  man  as  individual,  and  not  to  man  as  a 
mere  phase  of  a  universal  consciousness  underlying  the 
whole  world.  We  showed  also  that  self-realisation  in 
the  transcendentalist  sense  is  not  the  end  of  man. 

One  remark  we  may  make  in  addition.  All  Evolu- 
tionists suppose  that  we  are  gradually  approaching  the 
final  end  of  man,  an  end  to  be  realised  (in  so  far  as  it 
ever  will  be  realised)  on  this  earth,  and  that  when  we 
shall  have  reached  it,  evil  shall  be  no  more.  That  any 
such  end  shall  ever  be  attained  in  this  world,  or  that  it 
shall  be  attained  here  or  elsewhere  by  any  system  of 
natural  evolutionary  forces,  is,  we  claim,  neither  proved 
nor  probable.  Our  final  end  lies  in  another  world,  as 
was  proved  in  the  second  chapter  of  this  work,  and  it 
can  only  be  attained  by  individual  moral  effort. 

Man  is,  indeed,  a  being  of  development  and  of  pro- 
gress, but  his  progress  is  not  to  be  secured  by  blind  and 
irresistible  laws  of  evolution  pressing  him  on  whether 

Vol.  1 — 30 


466  THE  SCIENCE   OF  ETHICS 

he  wishes  it  or  not  to  some  unknown  end.  Man  is  a 
self-directed  being,  and  development  consists  in  our 
freely  doing  the  good,  or  in  our  freely  moving  to  our 
final  end.  Our  final  natural  end  is  known  to  us.  It  is 
the  Infinite  Good,  and  this  end  can  only  be  obtained 
by  our  freely  observing  the  natural  law  both  in  the 
individual  and  in  the  public  life. 

APPENDIX   ON   THE   ETHICS   OF   SPINOZA   AND    OF   FICHTE 

Though  not  themselves  evolutionary  systems,  still  it  may 
not  be  out  of  place  at  this  point  to  give  a  brief  sketch  of  two 
very  different  yet  cognate  theories,  the  Ethics  of  Spinoza  and 
the  Ethics  of  Fichte,  so  closely  are  these  theories  related 
to  the  systems  we  have  just  criticised  under  the  name  of 
"  Transcendental  Evolution."  Our  accovmt  will  be  merely 
historical  and  not  accompanied  by  anything  in  the  nature  of 
philosophical  criticism. 

APPENDIX  A. — Spinoza's  *  system 

Spinoza's  theory  of  "  geometrical  Ethics  "  is  an  attempt  to 
deduce  the  laws  of  morality  from  the  single  conception  of 
"  substance  "  according  to  the  strictest  laws  of  reasoning.  It 
is  called  "  geometrical  "  because  of  its  analogy  with  the 
science  of  Geometry,  which  out  of  the  single  conception  of 
space  derives  the  whole  complexus  of  geometrical  laws  accord- 
ing to  the  strictest  reasoning.  What  space  is  to  Geometry, 
Substance  is  to  Ethics.  Substance  is  the  original  ground  of 
all  existence,  that  through  which  all  things  exist  and  of  which 
they  are  the  manifestation.  Human  acts  and  the  human 
character  are  but  "  modes  "  into  which  the  original  substance 
differentiates  itself  according  to  the  inner  necessary  laws  of 
nature.  The  Ethical  laws  therefore — the  laws  of  the  perfect 
human  character — are  necessary  laws,  and  the  human  act 
and  character  themselves  are  necessary  and  not  indifferent. 
What  "  ought  to  be  "  means  "  what  is."  The  "  moral  power 
of  right  "  means  "  actual  physical  power."  There  arc  no 
ideals  other  than  the  actual  facts  which  make  up  the  actual 
world. 


•  A  translation  of  the  Ethica  of  Benedict  de  Spinoza  is  to  be  found 
In  I3ohn's  Philosopliical  Library.  In  our  account  of  Spinoza's  system 
given  above  wc  have  made  frequent  use  of  Martincau's  work  "  Types 
of  Ethical  Theory." 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION  467 

Passing  by  his  purely  metaphysical  theory  of  Substance, 
Attributes,  and  Modes,  and  their  relation  to  one  another,  also 
his  account  of  knowledge  and  its  degrees,  we  come  to  his 
first  ethical  conception,  which  is  the  transition  from  knowing 
to  doing.  "  Doing  "  or  action  is  an  effect  of  that  inner  law 
of  conatus  in  things  whereby  every  thing  tends  to  persist  or 
maintain  itself  in  being.  This  conatus  or  tendency  to  self- 
maintenance  belongs  to  the  inner  essence  of  things.  It  is 
the  "  will  "  of  things,  and  since  will  and  intellect  are  not 
really  distinct,  so  conatus  is  not  really  distinct  from  logical 
affirmation  and  negation.  Will  or  conatus  is  the  dynamic 
causality  of  thought.  It  is  no  other  than  the  life  of  things, 
and  since  it  springs  from  the  being  itself  and  presupposes 
no  "  otherness  " — no  causality  from  without — it  is,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  put  forth  by  our  adequate  ideas,  our  freedom — 
freedom,  that  is,  not  in  the  Aristotelian  sense  of  power  to 
do  or  not  to  do,  but  in  the  Kantian  sense  of  self-determina- 
tion. In  so  far,  however  as  this  conatus  is  put  forth  by 
inadequate  ideas  or  imagination  it  is  feeling.  "  Freedom," 
"  pure  understanding  or  Reason,"  "  self -conservation,"  these, 
in  Spinoza's  system,  are  all  one  thing. 

"  Pleasure  is  the  feeling  in  which  the  mind  passes  to 
greater  perfection,  pain  that  in  which  it  passes  to  less." 
"  Pleasure  heightens  while  pain  lowers  the  self-conserving 
conatus."  "  Good  "  and  "  bad  "  mean  respectively  helps 
and  hindrances  to  self -conservation,  and  their  marks  or  tests 
are  respectively  pleasure  and  pain.  In  feeling  that  a  thing 
is  pleasurable,  we  know  it  is  good.  Pleasure  is  the  satisfac- 
tion of  desire,  and  desire  is  the  "  conatus  of  our  essence  to 
assert  "  and  maintain  itself.  And  since  the  central  element 
of  our  essence  is  "  understanding  "  the  perfect  life  will  con- 
sist in  bringing  "  all  the  proper  functions  of  our  nature,  as 
active,  to  one — viz.,  to  understand  or  know."  Love  of 
knowledge  is  the  "  sole  autonomous  affection  and  the  sole 
virtue."  And,  therefore,  the  special  virtues  which  this 
includes  may  all  be  reduced  to  one — namely,  to  "  act  from 
the  inward  essence  of  mind  alone  "  or  "to  stand  free  from 
the  sway  of  the  passive  affections,"  which  is  the  same  thing 
as  "  firmness  and  steadfastness  of  character  "  or  fortitude. 
But  the  highest  grade  of  perfection  is  gained  when  the  under- 
standing removes  itself  completely  from  outer  things,  and 
thus  having  rid  itself  of  the  element  of  "  inadequacy  "  in 
idea  which  comes  of  this  outemess,  it  contemplates  itself 
as  inner  essence,  and  also  that  which  is  its  inner  cause,  the 
underlying  basis  of  all  differentiation — that  is,  God.  In 
this  exercise  of  discovery  the  mind  is  aware  of  its  own  in- 


468  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

tclligent  power,  and  feels  glad  in  the  successful  action  of  its 
nature.  And  this  gladness  is  referred  to  its  cause — viz.,  to 
the  reality  or  truth  which  is  discovered — i.e.,  God,  who  com- 
prises in  Himself  all  reality  and  truth.  Now,  pleasure  re- 
ferred to  its  cause  is  love.  Therefore,  this  self-knowledge  is 
the  love  of  God.  Intellectual  love  of  God  is,  in  Spinoza's 
view,  the  culminating  point  of  human  excellence,  into  which 
Fortitude  "  becomes  sublimed,  and  where  it  reaches  its 
repose."  *  But,  for  this  "  love  of  God,"  which  is  our  highest 
activity,  we  are  not  to  expect  any  return,  since  God,  having 
no  affections,  neither  loves  nor  hates. 

APPENDIX    B. — FICHTE's   SYSTEM  f 

Fichte's  system  is  not  evolutionary.  But  since  in  the 
science  of  Ethics  he  attempts  to  deduce  the  whole  moral  law, 
without  the  mediation  of  any  presuppositions  whatever,  from 
the  mere  conception  of  an  "  Ego  "  or  self-consciousness,  it 
will  be  convenient  to  give  some  account  of  his  system  here 
since  there  is  so  much  that  is  common  to  it  and  the  tran- 
scendentalist  theories  just  considered.  The  moral  law  is,  in 
Fichte's  account,  the  law  that  arises  essentially  from  Ego. 
The  starting  point  of  Ethics  is,  according  to  Fichte,  that  the 
Ego  itself  is  given  to  itself — i.e.,  is  perceived  directly  by 
itself.  But  if  an  Ego  is  to  know  itself,  it  must  know  itself 
as  object,  and  since  as  knowing  Ego  it  is  only  subject,  there- 
fore it  is  not  in  its  capacity  as  subject — that  is,  as  perceiving 
— that  it  becomes  an  object,  or  is  known  to  itself,  but  only 
in  its  other  function  of  willing.  As  knowing  it  is  subject. 
As  willing  it  is  object.  This,  Fichte  expresses  in  the  phrase — 
"  I  find  myself  as  willing."  But  the  Ego  as  known  to  itself 
directly  and  immediately  as  ivilling  is  not  known  necessarily 
as  willing  anything  beyond  itself  but  only  as  ivilling ,  but  as 
it  must  will  something,  so  it  is  given  immediately  and  neces- 
sarily in  consciousness  as  willing  itself  and  as  willing  from 
itself,  as  self-determined — as  free.  The  idea  of  freedom, 
therefore,  is  contained  necessarily  in  the  very  idea  of  a  self- 
conscious  ego.    And  this  conceptual  necessity — the  necessity, 

•  Intellect  and  will  are  ascribed  by  Spinoza  to  God  not  as  Natura 
Naturans,  or,  .substance  as  eternal,  but  as  Natura  Naturata,  or,  what 
follows  from  the  eternal  necessity  of  the  Divine  Nature. 

I  l-'ichte's  system  is  known  as  the  system  of  Personal  Ethics,  be- 
cause in  his  theory  the  moral  law  is  founded  on  the  conception  that 
each  man  is  a  person.  Still  it  would  scarcely  be  right  to  call  his  system 
individualistic,  it  is  from  the  conception  of  Ego  in  general  and  not 
fxom  thia  or  that  Ego  that  he  derives  his  whole  philosophy. 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION     469 

namely,  with  which  the  idea  of  freedom  is  contained  in  that 
of  the  conscious  ego — is  the  ground  of  the  necessity  of  the 
law  to  be  free.  Freedom  is  our  first  essential  act,  the  first 
natural  impulse  of  the  Ego — the  impulse,  namely,  to  will 
itself  as  object. 

But  whatever  exists,  exists  for  thought  ;  or,  as  Fichte  puts 
it,  the  ground  for  everything  is  thinking.  Therefore  the  Ego 
as  willing  exists  only  as  a  thought  object.  The  Ego  as  think- 
ing or  perceiving  knows  the  Ego  as  willing ;  and  since  the 
Ego  as  object  or  willing  has  no  existence  except  through  the 
thinking  of  it  (nothing  has  existence  except  for  the  thinking 
Ego)  the  Ego  as  object  or  as  willing  would  seem  to  have  a 
ground,  a  dependence  on  something  distinct  from  itself — 
that  is,  it  would  seem  to  depend  on  the  Ego  as  thinking. 
It  would  seem,  therefore,  according  to  Fichte,  that  the  Ego 
as  willing  is  necessarily  a  conditioned  and  dependent  thing, 
and  that,  so,  it  cannot  be  altogether  self-directed  or  free — 
freedom  being  absolute  independence — absolute  uncon- 
ditionedness.  The  concept  of  freedom  therefore  must  go, 
on  account  of  this  dependence,  unless  we  insist  that  the  Ego 
as  thinking  and  the  Ego  as  willing  are  one — and  this  we 
must  insist  on.  For  freedom,  since  it  is  given  in  or  is  con- 
tained in  the  very  concept  of  thinking,  as  we  saw  at  the 
beginning,  must  be  maintained  at  any  cost  ;  and  since  a 
necessary  condition  of  freedom  is  the  unity  we  have  just 
referred  to  of  object  and  subject,  so  we  postulate  for  Ethics 
that  Ego  as  thinking  or  as  subject,  and  Ego  as  willing — i.e., 
as  object — are  one  principle,  and  that  freedom  is  an  act  of 
the  whole  unit.  But  subject  and  object  can  never  be  com- 
pletely identified — there  must  be,  in  Fichte's  words,  always 
disruption  of  subject  and  object.  Hence  the  inner  contra- 
diction of  freedom,  as  something  absolute  and  unanalysable 
in  thought,  something  which  is  never  realisable,  but  to  wiiich 
we  must  ever  keep  approaching,  something  we  must  keep 
ever  tending  to  without  ever  reaching,  like  those  lines  called 
asymptotes,  which,  as  Mathematicians  tell  us,  approach  ever 
another  line,  yet  never  reach  it.  Freedom  then  =  x,  which 
means  something  that  is  unanalysable. 

But  now,  merely  to  will  is  to  will  nothing.  To  will  we 
must  will  something  definite,  some  object  distinct  from  the 
will,  some  object  of  pleasure.  Hence  there  can  be  no  willing 
except  through  sense  feeling  and  desire,  for  it  is  through  feel- 
ing and  desire  that  we  become  related  to  particular  objects. 
This,  too,  is  given  in  the  very  idea  of  the  Ego.  Hence  in  the 
will  there  is  a  second  natural  impulse,  that  of  desire  for  the 
feeling  of  pleasure.     This  impulse  is  empirical,  but   as  all 


470  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

objects  that  exist  exist  for  thought  only,  so  these  objects  of 
desire  exist  only  for  thought — i.e.,  they  exist  for  the  Ego, 
and  have  all  their  existence  in  the  Ego.  The  consciousness 
of  the  necessity  of  freedom,  together  with  that  of  the  eternal 
opposition  between  it  and  the  natural  impulses,  gives  rise  to 
the  feeling  of  obligation. 

There  are,  therefore,  in  the  will  two  impulses — one  to  will 
itself  alone,  which  is  the  impulse  of  freedom,  the  other  to 
desire  some  finite  object  outside  of  the  will.  Both  these 
impulses  spring  out  of  the  tendency  of  the  Ego  to  activity. 
They  cannot  be  identified,  and  yet  if  the  self  is  to  be  realised 
they  must  be  both  realised  as  impulses  of  the  one  self.  Both 
of  these  conditions  are  to  a  certain  extent  fulfilled  in  the 
harmonising  of  the  two  impulses,  since  in  harmony  are  con- 
tained the  two  conceptions  of  difference  and  identity.  The 
harmony  of  these  two  impulses  is  the  moral  good,  and  con- 
science is  the  feeling  of  this  harmony.  Still  freedom,  which 
is  absence  of  determination  from  outside,  keeps  ever  shrinking 
from  desire,  always  standing  aloof  from  it,  and  their  complete 
harmony  can  only  be  an  asymptotical  existence,  like  freedom 
itself.  Morality,  therefore,  belongs  not  to  individual  act  so 
much  as  to  the  unchangeable  character.  Hence,  two  moral 
principles  arise — one  from  the  impulse  to  pure  freedom — 
"  Ens  liberum  maneat  liberum  " — the  other  from  the  impulse 
of  conscience  to  harmonise  the  two  impulses — the  impulses  of 
self-determination  and  of  pleasure — "  act  absolutely  in  con- 
formity with  your  conception  of  duty,"  or  "  whatever  end  you 
desire  let  it  harmonise  with  the  principle  of  the  will  itself, 
which  is  duty."  It  is  not,  thercfo-'^, /ro;n  the  concept  of  duty 
that  we  must  act  but  from  the  >icept  of  harmony  with  it. 
This  is  the  moral  law  to  harmonise  the  impulses,  not  to 
annihilate  cither  ;  and  we  know  that  these  two  impulses  are 
Irirmonised  by  the  feeling  of  harmony  or  conscience,  which 
therefore  is  for  us  the  supreme  moral  criterion. 

But  though  the  feeling  of  conscience  is,  according  to 
Fichte,  sufficient  as  empirical  proof  of  the  truth  of  moral  con- 
victions, still  a  rational  science  of  morals  requires  that  our 
duties  be  deduced  from  the  conception  of  the  impulse  to 
freedom,  which  is  the  ground  conception  of  the  Ego  itself. 
That  is,  the  Science  of  Morals  requires  that  the  code  of  duties 
be  rationally  deduced  from  the  conception  of  personality, 
which  is  nothing  more  than  the  freedom  of  the  Ego.  Hence 
the  first  law  of  morals  is  given  by  Fichte — I  must  be  an  inde- 
]H'ndent  person,  and  whatever  forwards  my  personality  shall 
be  used  by  me  to  that  end.  Hut  in  the  conception  of  my  own 
j)ersonality  are  contained  the  three  conceptions  of  causality 


TRANSCENDENTAL  EVOLUTION 


471 


(through  the  body)  substantiaUty  {i.e.,  intelligent  Being)  and 
interaction  (of  one  person  on  another  person).  From  these 
three  conceptions  we  obtain  the  three  laws — (i)  to  use  the 
body  for  the  sake  of  morality,  and  so  to  avoid  insensibility  on 
the  one  hand,  and  pleasure  for  pleasure's  sake  on  the  other ; 
(2)  to  develop  our  intelligence,  since  between  intelligence  and 
morahty  there  can  be  no  opposition  ;  (3)  to  use  other  persons 
not  as  means  but  as  ends  in  themselves. 


CHAPTER  XIV 

THE  MORAL  FACULTY 

By  the  Moral  Faculty  is  meant  that  faculty  by  which 
we  know  the  moral  character 'of  human  acts.  The  ex- 
pression "  moral  faculty "  is  sometimes,  though  not 
commonly,  used  to  indicate  the  faculty  in  which  good 
and  evil  reside,  or  that  faculty  which  elicits  good  and 
evil  acts — namely,  the  will.  But  at  present  we  are 
dealing  with  the  faculty  which  elicits  judgments  about 
good  and  evil — or,  as  it  is  called,  the  faculty  of  moral 
judgment.  If  we  have  not  headed  the  present  chapter 
with  the  title  "  the  faculty  of  moral  judgment,"  and 
thereby  prevented  all  possibility  of  ambiguity,  the  reason 
is  that  by  such  an  expression  we  might  seem  to  anticipate 
a  conclusion  which  we  shall  have  to  establish  in  the 
present  chapter — viz.,  that  the  moral  faculty  is  one  of 
judgment  and  not  a  sense  or  instinct.  This,  we  think, 
is  sufificient  reason  for  speaking  of  the  present  chapter 
as  an  enquiry  into  the  "  moral  faculty  "  simply. 

Now,  from  what  has  been  already,  said  on  the  mean- 
ing of  the  moral  ^'  good  "  and  the  nature  of  the  moral 
criterion,  the  reader  will  have  no  difficulty  in  surmising 
what  the  moral  faculty  is.  We  have  said  that  by  moral 
goodness  is  meant  conformity  between  the  human  act 
and  man's  ultimate  end,  or  between  our  acts  and  the 
law  that  is  imposed  upon  us  by  our  human  nature. 
And  as  the  ultimate  end  of  man  and  the  law  which 
our  nature  imposes  are  known  only  through  Intellect, 
so  Intellect  or  Reason  is  the  faculty  by  which  the  human 
mind  judges  of  morality.  Laws  are  not  presented  to 
the  human  mind  as  facts  are,  immediately  and  in- 
tuitively. Neither  is  the  human  mind  directed  to  the 
fulfilment  of  law,  as  animals  are,  by  the  compulsion  of 

472 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  473 

inner  instinct.  In  the  case  of  man,  the  knowledge  of 
a  law  and  direction  of  conduct  by  means  of  law  always 
imply  reasoning,  and,  therefore,  the  moral  faculty  will 
be  that  faculty  by  which  we  are  enabled  to  elicit  reasoned 
judgments  about  good  and  evil. 

And  the  truth  of  this  proposition  should  be  abundantly 
evident  to  us  even  from  experience.  For  in  ordinarj' 
life  determination  of  morality  involves,  as  we  know,  the 
reasoned  application  of  one  or  many  general  laws  to  an 
individual  case,  and  these  laws  are  even  quoted  in  justi- 
fication of  our  action  whenever  we  are  questioned  about 
it.  The  same  laws  which  we  give  in  justification  of  our  ^ 
action  are  the  premisses  by  which  we  infer  that  we  are 
right  in  performing  them.  Reason,  then,  is  the  faculty 
by  which  the  human  mind  determines  what  is  right  and 
wrong  in  human  action. 

Now,  we  need  not  say  that  in  regarding  Reason  as 
the  moral  faculty  we  arfe  far  from  claiming  infallibility 
for  this  faculty.  For  Reason  may  go  wrong  in  the 
sphere  of  morals  just  as  it  may  in  the  sphere  of  Physical 
Science.  But  Reason  in  the  sphere  of  mprals  is  as 
reliable  as  in  any  other  sphere,  and  can  lead  the  mind 
to  certitude  in  simple  as  well  as  in  complex  cases,  unless, 
indeed,  the  case  be  exceedingly  complex,  in  which  case 
the  fault  lies  not  with  Reason,  but  either  with  the  way 
in  which  the  materials  of  our  moral  judgments  are 
presented  to  us,  or  with  the  will,  since  often  the  will 
forces  the  Reason  to  issue  judgments  on  only  a  slender 
examination  of  the  case,  judgments  which  of  itself  the 
Reason  would  not  have  issued. 

The  moral  faculty  is,  therefore,  the  faculty  of  Reason 
or  Intellect.  It  is  fundamentally  that  very  faculty  by 
which  we  carry  on  our  deductions  in  Mathematics  or 
in  any  other  science  outside  the  sphere  of  morals.  And 
what  is  called  Conscience  is  merely  the  act  which  is 
elicited  when  we  use  this  faculty  on  moral  matters — the 
act,  namely,  by  which  we  judge  whether  an  act  is  good 
or  bad.     Moral  judgments,  therefore,  are  nothing  but 


474  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  judgments  of  our  ordinary  Reason  and  intellect. 
But  Conscience  is  a  particular  function  of  our  intellect, 
for  in  morals  we  have  to  do  not  with  speculative  truth 
but  with  human  actions.  Hence,  Conscience  is  called  an 
act  not  of  the  speculative  but  of  the  practical  intellect. 
But  that  practical  intellect  of  which  Conscience  is  a 
function  is  the  ordinary  practical  intellect — the  ver\- 
same  intellect  which  tells  a  man  what  to  do  or  to  avoid 
in  ordinary  extra-moral  questions  of  the  business  of 
life — how,  for  instance,  he  ought  to  invest  his  money, 
or  carry  on  a  business,  or  preserve  his  health.  Some 
ethicians,  indeed,  speak  of  the  act  of  Conscience  as  if 
it  were  a  different  thing  subjectively  from  all  other 
acts  of  the  practical  intellect,  as  if  Conscience  possessed 
a  certain  sacredness  and  authority  based  on  the  nature 
of  the  faculty  itself  which  are  present  in  no  other  intel- 
lectual act.  The  fact  is  that  the  sacredness  which 
attaches  to  the  act  of  conscience  comes  to  it  not  from 
the  faculty  which  elicits  the  act  but  from  the  object  to 
which  the  act  refers — viz.,  the  "  good  "  and  duty. 
From  the  object  of  the  moral  faculty,  indeed,  there 
comes  an  element  of  sacredness  which  is  not  to  be  found 
in  the  object  of  any  other  faculty.  But  the  act  of 
conscience,  as  an  act,  or  the  faculty  in  which  that  act 
resides,  and  from  which  it  springs,  is  not  more  sacred 
taken  in  itself  than  the  common  practical  or  speculative 
Reason  which  we  use  in  Mathematics  and  the  other 
sciences.  Conscience  is  an  act  of  the  "  sicca  lux  in- 
tellectus  "  and  no  more. 

The  moral  faculty,  then,  we  repeat,  is  the  faculty  of 
Reason  or  the  practical  intellect — the  same  faculty  as 
that  which  guides  us  in  business  matters — in  matters  of 
ordinary  human  prudence. 

We  now  go  on  to  consider  some  of  the  more  promi- 
nent of  those  theories  on  the  nature  of  the  moral  faculty 
which  are  in  direct  opposition  to  the  ethical  theory  of 
Aristotle  and  Aquinas.  But  before  doing  so  we  wish 
to  say  that  if,  as  is  customary  with  modern  ethicians, 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  475 

and  even  with  some  scholastic  writers,  we  should  in 
the  following  pages  speak  of  Conscience  as  a  faculty 
instead  of  as  an  act  we  are  speaking  of  Conscience  only 
in  a  loose  sense,  for,  strictly  speaking,  Conscience  is  an 
act,  an  act  of  the  practical  Reason  whereby  a  man 
recognises  that  certain  things  are  good  and  to  be  done, 
others  evil  and  to  be  avoided. 


[a)  Theory  of  a  distinct  moral  faculty. 

That  there  is  a  special  faculty  for  the  perception  of 
ethical  distinctions  amongst  acts,  and  for  that  end 
alone,  has  been  the  assumption  underlying  many  ethical 
theories  both  ancient  and  modern.  What  that  faculty 
is,  whether  it  is  a  perceptive  sense,  a  feeling  *  or  senti- 
ment, a  spiritual  power,  or  even  a  Divine  power  tran- 
scending, yet  dwelling  in,  human  nature,  are  questions 
on  which  schools  have  been  much  divided.  Jouffroy 
claimed  that  it  was  a  sense  akin  to  the  ordinary  five  ; 
Fichte  and  Bradley  that  it  was  a  rational  sentiment  or 
feeling  ;  Reid  and  Hutcheson  that  it  was  a  sense  of  a 
decidedly  spiritual  nature,  more  affective  than  percep- 
tive, but  distinct  from  every  other  faculty  within  us ; 
More,  that  it  was  a  purely  spiritual  faculty,  worthy  of 
a  separate  name,  the  "  boniform  faculty  " — to  dis- 
tinguish it  oft  from  the  ordinary-  Reason  to  which  it  is 
allied.  But  on  one  matter  these  theories  are  all  in 
agreement — viz.,  on  the  originality  of  the  moral  faculty 
— that  is,  on  its  separateness  from  every  other  faculty 
and  on  the  limited  character  of  the  function  assigned  to 
it — that  of  cognising  moral  distinctions,  or  rather  the 
moral  quaHties  of  acts. 

We  shall  now  adduce  some  of  the  arguments  on  which 
this  theory  of  a  distinct  moral  faculty'  is  based,  j 

*  If  wc  speak  of  feelings  as  a  faculty,  we  use  the  word  "  faculty  " 
in  a  very  wide  sense  indeed. 

t  The  fust  three  arguments  here  given  are  taken  from  Hume's 
"  Treatise  on  Human  Nature,"  the  fourth  from  Macintosh    the  fifth 


476  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Argument  (i) — The  moral  faculty  has  a  certain  influ- 
ence over  conduct — that  is,  is  itself  a  spring  of  moral 
action,  whilst  Reason  is  not  a  spring  of  action.  Reason, 
therefore,  and  the  moral  faculty  cannot  be  one  and  the 
same.  Hutcheson  goes  even  farther  than  Hume  in  this 
matter,  and  declares  that  not  only  is  Conscience  an 
impulse — that  is,  a  spring  of  action — but  that  it  is 
supreme  amongst  all  impulses  commanding  and  over- 
ruling all  the  rest,  so  that  we  have  but  to  follow  this 
impulse  to  be  sure  we  are  doing  the  right.  Wundt 
also  insists  that  no  intellectual  faculty  could  be  a  motive 
of  action,  and  that  consequently  Conscience  could  not 
be  the  ordinary  intellectual  faculty. 

We  reply  that  if  the  moral  faculty  were  the  specula- 
tive intellect  *  it  could  not  possibly  be  a  spring  of  action. 
But  there  is  a  practical  as  well  as  a  speculative  Reason  ; 
and  the  function  of  the  practical  Reason  is  to  tell  a  man 
the  means  that  will  lead  him  to,  and  are  necessary  to, 
any  particular  end.  Conscience  is  nn  act  of  the  practical 
Reason.  It  tells  us  our  duty  or  what  will  lead  us  to  our 
ultimate  end.  It  tells  us  what  acts  are  good,  and  good 
being  naturally  appetible  to  the  will,  it  is  thereby  in- 
directly a  spring  of  action.  Conscience  is,  therefore,  a 
spring  of  action.  But  it  is  a  spring  of  action  in  a  very 
particular  sense.  First,  it  is  a  spring  of  action  not  as 
Reason  simply,  but  as  practical  Reason  ;  and  secondly, 
it  moves  to  action  not  subjectively  as  the  passions  move 
one,  but  objectively — i.e.,  by  putting  before  the  wiil 
objects  to  be  desired.  The  spring  of  action,  then,  in 
the  case  of  Conscience  lies  rather  in  the  object  than  in 
the  Reason,  for  Conscience  merely  determines  what 
objects  ought  to  be  pursued — that  is,  what  objects 
should  be  allowed  to  move  the  will. 

from  Butler.  Hume  has  other  arguments  also,  but  they  arc  too  trifling 
to  merit  serious  attention.  All  the  arguments  here  given  are  intended 
by  their  authors  to  serve  a  double  purpose — first,  to  show  that  Reason 
is  not  the  moral  faculty  ;  secondly,  to  prove  that  the  function  of  the 
moral  faculty  is  distinct. 

•  As  Cudworth  regarded  it. 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  477 

Argument  (2) — The  second  argument  for  the  existence 
of  a  distinct  moral  faculty  is  that  if  virtues  and  vices  (in 
the  sense  of  good  and  bad  acts)  mean  respectively  agree- 
ment and  disagreement  with  Reason,  then,  since  agree- 
ment or  disagreement  with  Reason  does  not  admit  of 
degrees,  virtues  and  vices  could  admit  of  no  degrees, 
and  sins  should  be  all  equal.  But  sins  are  not  all  equal. 
Therefore,  virtue  docs  not  mean  agreement  with  Reason, 
and  Reason  is  not  the  moral  faculty. 

We  reply  (i) — The  question  of  greater  and  less  in  sins 
and  virtues  is  not  a  very  easy  one,  and  we  shall  deal 
with  it  in  its  proper  place.  Clearly,  however,  merely 
positing  a  new  faculty  for  the  perception  of  morality 
does  not  remove  that  difficulty.  (2)  Virtue  *  does  not, 
strictly  speaking,  mean  agreement  with  Reason,  but 
direction  to  the  ultimate  end,  and  vice,  movement  away 
from  it.  And  as  divergence  from  an  end  admits  of 
degrees,  so  there  can  be  degrees  of  vice,  and,  therefore, 
inequality  between  sins.  But  even  in  the  sense  of 
agreement  and  disagreement  with  Reason,  virtue  and 
vice  may  admit  of  degrees.  For  since  in  ordinary 
commercial  and  political  affairs  "  rational  "  and  "  irra- 
tional "  admit  of  degrees,  one  action  being  wiser  or 
more  prudent  than  another,  there  is  no  reason  why  the 
same  should  not  be  the  case  in  the  sphere  of  moral 
action.  The  only  difference  between  the  two  spheres  is 
that,  whereas  morals  relate  primarily  to  the  ultimate 
end  of  life,  commerce  and  politics  refer  more  directly 
to  intermediate  ends. 

Argument  (3) — If  morality  is  a  relation  f  cognised  by 
Reason,  then  wherever  that  relation  is  discovered  it 
should  be  recognised  as  moral.     If,  for  instance,  the  sin 


•  "  Virtue  "  is  spoken  of  by  Hume  in  the  sense  of  the  "  good," 
which  meaning  we  adopt  here  and  in  other  places  in  this  work  for  the 
sake  of  argument.  The  strict  meaning  of  virtue  as  a  habit  informing 
the  faculties  will  be  found  in  our  chapter  on  the  virtues. 

t  Hume  takes  it  for  granted  here  that  if  the  moral  faculty  be 
Reason,  morals  must  consist  in  a  relation,  and  vice  versa,  if  morality 
is  a  relation,  the  moral  faculty  must  be  the  faculty  of  Reason. 


478  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of  ingratitude  is  a  relation  cognised  by  Reason,  then 
wherever  that  same  relation  is  recognised,  even  in 
inanimate  nature,  it  should  be  called  sinful.  So  we 
should  call  the  acorn  morally  vicious  for  growing  up 
and  destroying  the  parent  oak,  just  as  sons  are  morally 
vicious  who  prove  ungrateful  to  their  parents.  But  the 
action  of  the  acorn  is  not  recognised  as  morally  vicious. 
Therefore,  morality  is  not  a  relation  cognised  by 
Reason. 

Reply — It  is  not  true  that  Reason  must  judge  of  the 
ungrateful  son  as  it  judges  of  the  acorn.  For  (i)  Reason 
is  aware  that  without  freedom  there  can  be  no  morality. 
Killing,  even  in  the  case  of  man,  is  not  regarded  as 
immoral  unless  it  be  free  ;  and  since  the  action  of  the 
acorn  is  determined  it  cannot  be  regarded  as  immoral. 
(2)  Even  were  the  killing  of  the  parent  oak  tree  a  free 
and  imputable  action,  it  need  not  necessarily  be  morally 
evil.  Acts  that  are  natural  to  one  agent  may  not  be 
natural  to  another,  and  nature  is  the  standard  of  moral 
good  and  evil. 

Argument  (4) — Objects  that  are  formally  different  re- 
quire distinct  faculties  for  their  perception.  Thus 
colour  requires  one  faculty  for  its  perception,  sound 
another.  But  the  good  is  distinct  from  the  useful, 
the  beautiful,  and  all  other  relations  that  are  perceived 
by  intellect.  Therefore,  the  ordinary  intellect  cannot 
cognise  moral  good  and  evil. 

Reply — Pushed  to  its  logical  extreme,  this  means  that 
the  beautiful  should  be  perceived  by  one  faculty,  the 
useful  by  another,  mathematical  relations  by  another, 
political  relations  by  another,  and  so  on — a  special 
faculty  for  each  distinct  relation.  Nay,  each  distinct 
moral  virtue  should  have  its  own  special  faculty,  and 
consequently  there  could,  on  this  theory,  be  no  one 
faculty  of  morality,  but  an  infinite  number  of  faculties. 
Such  a  view  is  evidently  extreme.  We  may  also  remark 
that  not  every  distinction  in  object  requires  a  distinction 
in  faculty.     One  faculty  suffices  for  the  perception  of 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  479 

red,  and  green,  and  yellow.  And  so,  one  faculty  suffices 
tor  the  perception  of  aU  relations,  including  the  moral 
relation  of  "  act  to  ulfmite  end."  * 

Argument  (5) — Butler's  argument  is  one  which  we 
have  already  referred  to,  and  we  shall  have  occasion  to 
speak  of  it  later  on  in  the  present  chapter.  We  shall, 
therefore,  deal  with  it  only  very  briefly  here.  The 
moral  faculty,  he  tells  us,t  is  "  a  faculty  in  kind  and 
nature  supreme  over  all  others,  and  one  which  bears 
its  own  authority  for  being  so."  That  is.  Conscience 
transcends  every  other  natural  faculty  in  man  from  the 
special  function  of  direction  and  superintendence  which 
it  has  from  nature.  Conscience  is  the  source  of  the 
categorical  imperative,  and  in  commanding  us  it  pro- 
claims its  own  authority  not  only  over  every  other 
faculty  in  man,  but  over  man  as  a  whole.  It  cannot, 
therefore,  be  identified  with  intellect.  It  is  sui  generis 
and  independent. 

Reply — Butler  is  not  always  quite  consistent  on  the 
question  of  tiie  function  of  Conscience,  for  he  tells  us 
also  that  the  three  functions  of  Conscience  are  judgment, 
direction,  and  superintendence — and  judgment  is  cer- 
tainly a  function  of  intellect.  Again,  he  calls  Con- 
science the  faculty  of  cool  self-love.  That  is,  it  is  a 
deliberating  facult}^  But  deliberation  appertains  to 
intellect.  As  to  the  particular  argument  before  us  let 
it  suffice  to  say  that  Conscience  is  not  a  dictatorial  (in 
Butler's  sense  of  the  term)  but  a  judging  faculty.  Con- 
science points  out  to  me  what  I  ought  to  do  and  what 
acts  are  good  or  bad.  It  tells  me  that  I  must  do  certain 
things  just  in  the  same  way  as  my  Reason  tells  me  I 
must  take  a  certain  road  to  a  town — with  the  difference 
that  in  the  former  case  the  judgment  is  categorical,  in 
the  other  case  it  is  hypothetical.  Conscience,  therefore, 
is  not  supreme  over  the  other  faculties.     It  is  simply 

*  For  distinctions  in  the  faculties  dependent  upon  distinction  of 
formal  object,  see  Father  Maher's  "  Psychology." 
t  Second  Sermon. 


48o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  faculty  of  practical  Reason,  or,  to  speak  more  pre- 
cisely, it  is  the  act  of  that  faculty. 

These  are  the  main  arguments  in  favour  of  a  distinct 
moral  faculty.  They  are  used  to  show  that  the  faculty 
must  be  something  distinct  from  Reason,  but  they  do 
not  determine  what  in  particular  the  faculty  is.  We 
now  proceed  to  discuss  some  of  the  several  theories  that 
have  been  offered  on  the  particular  nature  of  the  distinct 
moral  faculty  of  Conscience. 

(b)  Conscience  a  moral  feeling  or  group  of  feelings. 

"  Conscience,"  says  Mill,  "  is  when  the  pain  attendant 
on  the  violation  of  duty  is  disinterested,  and  confined  to. 
the  pure  idea  of  duty  and  not  to  any  particular  form 
of  it."  "  Conscience,"  writes  Leslie  Stephen,  "  is  the 
group  of  feelings  that  makes  conformity  to  the  moral 
law  pleasant  and  non-conformity  painful."  It  is,  says 
Fichte,  the  feeling  of  harmony  between  the  pure  and 
the  natural  impulses  in  man.  "  Conscience,"  says 
Hume,  "  is  not  the  work  of  judgment,  but  of  the 
heart."  *  Hume  also  calls  Conscience  "  humanity," 
meaning  not  the  universal  man  or  the  universal  Reason, 
but  "  humaneness  "  or  the  "  altruistic  feelings."  Brown 
tells  us  that  Conscience  is  not  a  sense  proper  but  the 
"  susceptibility  of  moral  emotion."  And  even  those 
ethicians  who  have  claimed  for  Conscience  a  double 
character — namely,  that  it  is  a  faculty  of  judgment  or 
of  Reason,  and  also  a  feehng — yet  make  it  quite  clear 
that  feeling  is  the  primary  function.  Reason  a  secondary. 
This  certainly  is  the  view  adopted  by  Butler  and  War- 
burton.  In  their  theories  Reason  is  regarded  as  some- 
thing that  merely  "  improves  upon  the  dictates  of  the 
moral  sense,"  either,  as  Burlamaqui  contends,  "  to 
enable  us  the  better  to  discern  and  comprehend  the  true 
rule  of  conduct,"  or,  as  Warburton  puts  li,'^"  to  show 
that  the  love  and  hatred  excited  by  the  moral  sense 

•  i.e.,  principally. 


THE  MORAL   FACULTY  481 

were  not  capricious  in  their  operations,  but  that  in  the 
essential  properties  of  their  objects  there  was  a  specific 
difference."  *  All  these  theories  agree  in  maintaining 
that  Conscience  is  a  feeling  of  some  sort  or  other.  And 
in  support  of  this  view  we  often  find  adduced  certain 
factors  of  man's  moral  life  which,  it  is  said,  each  of  us 
can  discover  in  his  own  inner  experience. 

Grounds  for  this  Theory. f — These  facts  are  (i)  that  the 
most  prominent  element  in  our  moral  consciousness  is  the 
feeling  of  disgust  or  of  liking  with  which  we  contemplate 
acts  usually  designated  bad  or  good,  and  the  feelings  of 
sorrow  and  joy  experienced  when  we  ourselves  are  the 
authors  of  those  acts.  (2)  A  certain  vagueness  in  the  at- 
testation of  Conscience,  notwithstanding  the  fact  that  people 
have  the  full  use  of  Reason  and  have  a  full  conviction  of  the 
moral  character  of  an  act  ;  thus,  men  say  that  they  know 
not  why  an  act  is  bad,  but  they  firmly  believe  it  to  be  so. 
But  vagueness,  we  are  told,  is  a  characteristic  of  feeling  not 
of  Reason.  (3)  The  fact  that  Conscience  often  seems  to 
oppose  Reason  and  all  the  cognitive  faculties.  By  Reason 
men  come  to  the  conclusion  that  such  and  such  an  act  is 
lawful  for  them  ;  still  some  power  deeper  than  their  Reason, 
some  feeling  which  refuses  to  be  quelled  within  them  by 
Reason,  will  often  proclaim  that  it  is  not  lawful.  This  is 
the  "  still  small  voice  "  of  Conscience  which  often  speaks  un- 
compromisingly and  clearly  even  against  our  own  well- 
reasoned  judgments.  (4)  The  fact  that  whereas  Conscience 
grows  and  declines  with  feeling,  it  seems  not  to  grow  with 
Reason,  but  rather  to  lose  in  sharpness  and  delicacj;  as 
Reason  grows  more  acute.    Thus,  Conscience  is  much  keener 


*  We  would  also  class  under  the  present  theory  such  explanations 
of  Conscience  as  make  of  it  an  undefined  habit  or  series  of  habits, 
which  become  conscious  on  the  presence  of  certain  stimuli.  Thus 
Professor  Royce  defines  Conscience  as  "  a  well-knit  system  of  socially 
acquired  habits  of  estimating  acts,  a  system  so  constituted  as  to  be 
easily  aroused  into  conscious  presence  by  the  coming  of  the  idea  of  a 
certain  act." 

t  It  is  not  easy  to  find  formal  written  defences  of  the  theory  of 
Conscience  now  under  discussion,  nor  indeed  of  any  of  the  theories  of 
Conscience  criticised  in  the  present  chapter.  Many  writers  of  this 
school  (for  instance,  M.  Levy-Bruhl  and  Leslie  Stephen)  simply  assume 
that  Conscience  is  a  feeling.  The  above  reasons  have  been  given  to  us 
for  the  most  part  in  controversies  on  the  subject. 

Vol.  I — 31 


482  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

in  childhood  than  in  later  years,  and,  as  a  rule,  is  not  at  all 
so  sensitive  in  the  enlightened  as  in  the  uninstructed. 
Reason  and  Conscience,  therefore,  do  not  seem  to  grow  and 
decline  together.  But  feeling,  like  Conscience,  is  strongest 
in  childhood,  and  both  feeling  and  Conscience  decline  to- 
gether, one  in  the  sense  of  becoming  more  controllable,  the 
other  in  the  sense  of  becoming  less  responsive  as  Reason 
develops.  Later  on  again,  as  Reason  begins  to  decline,  the 
feelings  (of  old  people)  become  stronger  (for  old  people  are 
generally  more  sensitive),  whilst  Conscience  also  seems  to 
grow  more  sensitive,  tending  even  to  the  side  of  timidity 
and  scrupulosity.  Thus  Conscience  and  feeling  grow  and 
decline  together.  (5)  Moral  value  in  acts  is  unintelligible 
except  in  reference  to  feeling — i.e.,  to  feelings  of  pleasure 
and  pain.  Consequently  the  perception  of  value  must  be 
a  feeling. 

For  these  reasons  it  is  held  that  Conscience  is  an 
inner  feeling  implanted  in  man  originally  by  nature 
and  purely  independent  and  self-assertive. 


Disproof  of  the  theory  that  Conscience  is  a  feeling. 

Against  this  view  we  urge  the  following  arguments : 
(i)  Feelings,  as  opposed  to  the  attestations  of  a  sense, 
and  the  cognitions  of  intellect,  are  wholly  unperceptive. 
Pain  is  a  feeling,  and  pain  is  not  perceptive  of  anything  ; 
it  is  only  itself  a  perceived  state  of  the  organism.  So 
the  feelings  of  approbation  and  of  blame  that  accom- 
pany certain  actions  are  not  perceptive.  They  are 
merely  the  tendency  of  the  appetite  to  some  actions  as 
to  suitable — from  others  as  from  unsuitable — ends.  Now, 
if  Conscience  be  anything  it  is  perceptive  or  cognitive. 
In  no  other  way  than  through  a  cognitive  facult}^  can 
we  come  to  know  the  moral  qualities  of  acts.  Cognition 
is  the  primary  and  essential  function  of  the  moral  faculty. 
(2)  When  ignorant  of  or  in  doubt  about  the  moral  law 
we  do  not  seek  to  remove  our  ignorance  and  our  doubt 
by  stirring  up  the  moral  feelings  within  us,  or  by  seek- 
ing to  sharpen  up  our  faculty  of  feeling  for  its  work,  but 
rather  by  using  our  reasoning  facultj' — by  arguing  from 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  483 

premiss  to  conclusion.  Moreover,  it  is  worthy  of  remark 
that  when,  after  such  reasoning  we  do  at  length  discover 
the  moral  quality  0/  the  act,  we  sometimes  experience 
those  very  same  feeUngs  of  approbation  and  disapproval 
which  our  opponents  describe  as  the  fundamental  factor 
in  the  perception  of  good  and  evil.  It  is  scarcely  possible, 
we  maintain,  that  these  feelings  should  in  one  case  be 
the  source  of  our  moral  judgment  and  in  another  case 
the  result  of  it.  (3)  Where  feelings  dwell  in  distinct 
faculties  they  are  easily  distinguishable  from  one  another. 
But  where  different  feelings  belong  to  the  same  faculty, 
then  it  is  not  eas}'  to  distinguish  them  in  consciousness 
from  one  another.  Thus,  in  the  organic  feelings,  it 
very  hard  to  say  what  is  the  painful  and  what  the 
pleasant  element,  though  pleasure  and  pain  are  oft 
present  together,  making  up  one  confused  ma^ 
organic  feelings.  Now,  in  the  case  of  the  moral  act, 
there  must  be  innumerable  counter-feelings  of  pleasure 
and  pain  arising  out  of  the  various  parts  of  the  act — 
for  instance,  in  the  case  of  stealing — pleasure  that  we 
have  grown  richer — sympathy  for  him  that  is  robbed, 
etc.  But  out  from  all  these  stands  the  moral  judg- 
ment, which  condemns  the  act  in  its  totality — even  the 
pleasurable  parts  of  it,  and  the  force  of  this  moral  dis- 
approval within  me  I  know  to  a  nicety — that  is,  I  know- 
it  to  be  absolute,  that  it  outweighs  in  value  everything 
else  in  the  way  of  feeling  which  the  act  excites  within 
me.  If,  then,  the  perception  of  morahty  is  a  feeling, 
how  am  I  able  to  pick  that  element  out  from  the  whole 
mass  of  feehngs  which  the  act  excites  in  me  ?  If  moral 
perception  be  a  feeling  it  should  follow  the  laws  of  feel- 
ing. But  it  certainly  is  not  according  to  the  laws  of 
feeling  that  one  element  in  it  should  stand  out,  in  all 
cases,  quite  distinct  from  the  rest,  in  the  way  in  which 
the  moral  perception  stands  out.  To  answer  that 
morality  is  a  feeling  sui  generis,  and  that  consequently 
it  need  not  follow  the  ordinary  laws  of  feeling,  is  merely 
to  stick  blindly  to  an  hypothesis  and  to  refuse  to  submit 


2SS 

is     ^ 

ir 


484  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

it  to  any  known  scientific  test.  (4)  Often  our  most 
important  moral  perceptions  are  not  accompanied  by 
any  feeling  whatsoever.  This  is  the  clear  testimony  of 
experience,  and  it  proves  that  feeling  is  not  the  essential 
factor  in  moral  perceptions.  (5)  History  shows  that 
men  have  been  known  to  persist  in  doing  good  heroically 
even  when  on  their  own  testimony  their  feelings  were 
neutral  or  even  opposing. 

However,  though  Conscience  is  fundamentally  an 
intellectual  act,  based  chiefly  on  intellectual  considera- 
tions, it  is  nevertheless  guided  partly  by  the  feelings 
which,  as  we  have  already  shown,  are  even  a  secondary 
criterion  of  morality. 

Let  us  now  answer  the  opposing  arguments. 

(i)  Disgust  and  liking  the  most  prominent  elejnent  in 
moral  consciousness. — The  feeling  of  disgust  and  liking, 
we  reply,  are  not  the  most  prominent  element  in  moral 
disapproval  and  approval,  but  rather  the  judgment  of 
disapprobation  and  of  approval.  Often,  as  we  have 
just  pointed  out,  in  approving  an  act  we  have  very  little 
feeling  either  of  disgust  or  of  liking,  and,  as  a  rule,  such 
feeling  becomes  prominent  only  when  some  person  is  a 
beneficiary  under  our  act.*  Even,  however,  w^ere  this 
feeling  uniformly  prominent,  that  would  not  necessarily 
establish  the  priority  of  feeling  in  our  moral  perceptions. 
For  feeling  arouses  a  consciousness  of  itself  more  easily 
than  judgment,  because  to  creatures  of  flesh  and  blood 
the  sensuous  is  more  prominent  and  more  exciting  than 
the  coldly  rational.  But  the  more  prominent  element  is 
not  always  the  more  essential. 

(2)  Moral  consciousness  vague. — Vagueness,  we  reply, 
can  affect  a  man's  rational  convictions  and  judgments 
just  as  well  as  it  affects  his  feelings.  Vagueness  attaches 
to  many  acts  that  are  undoubtedly  intellectual,  such  as 
our  views  of  business  methods  and  relations.     Vague- 

•  The  question  on  which  some  modern  Ethicians  seem  to  lay  so 
much  stress — whether  the  moral  judgment  is  always  accompanied  by 
feeling — is  in  our  view  not  a  question  of  any  Ethical  importance. 


I 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  485 

ness  is,  in  fact,  nothing  more,  generally  speaking,  than 
uncertain  or  badly  formulated  knowledge. 

(3)  Moral  conviction  often  opposes  Reason. — We  reply : 
Reason  has  power  to  oppose  and  criticise  its  own  work, 
and,  therefore,  our  moral  convictions,  though  opposed 
to  some  acts  of  Reason,  may  still  be  themselves  con- 
victions of  our  Reason.  It  is  not  feeling,  for  instance, 
that  revolts  against  dishonest  or  plainly  insufficient 
reasoning-  in  science,  but  rather  one's  better  judgment, 
which  clearly  belongs  to  Reason.  Reasoning,  it  should 
be  remembered,  is  often  dishonest,  because  the  will 
and  passions  can  exercise  a  certain  control  over  the 
reasoning  power  and  extort  judgments  from  it  which 
the  premisses  are  far  from  warranting.  As  a  rule, 
however,  we  are  not  without  consciousness  of  the  un- 
fairness done  to  the  reasoning  faculty  in  such  cases, 
and  it  is  this  consciousness  which  enables  the  reasoning 
faculty  or  the  conscience  still  to  accuse  us  of  wrongdoing, 
even  when  we  have  already  judged  that  a  certain  course 
of  action  is  lawful  for  us.  Even,  therefore,  though 
Conscience  opposes  our  reasoning,  it  may  still  itself  be 
an  act  of  the  reasoning  faculty. 

(4)  Reason  and  Conscience  do  not  grow  together.  Con- 
science and  the  feelings  do. — We  reply  :  (a)  Even  if  it 
were  true  that  as  Reason  develops  Conscience  becomes 
less  tender,  Conscience  might  still  be  an  act  of  the 
reasoning  faculty,  since  it  is  possible  for  Reason  to 
develop  in  one  department  and  at  the  same  time  to 
decline  in  another.  And  morals,  it  should  be  remem- 
bered, are  only  one  department  of  Reason.  (6)  Also 
the  parallelism  between  the  growth  of  feeling  and 
Conscience  is  purely  imaginary.  The  least  conscientious 
man  may  have  the  very  deepest  feelings.  Children  are 
in  general  much  less  conscientious  than  grown  people, 
though  they  are  more  sensitive,  and  on  some  points  of 
morals  even  more  scrupulous  than  grown  people.  Also 
it  is  untrue  that  educated  people,  whose  Reasons,  it  is 
supposed,    are    more    highly    developed,    are   less   con- 


486  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

scientious  than  others.  In  matters  of  Conscience  it  is 
difficult  to  draw  conclusions  about  large  classes  of 
people — everything  depends  on  the  individual.  If  edu- 
cated people  seem  as  a  body  less  conscientious  than 
others,  this  apparent  want  of  moral  discernment  is  to 
be  explained  by  the  fact  that,  accustomed  as  they  are 
to  deal  in  the  larger  affairs  of  society,  where  often  it  is 
not  easy  to  determine  a  man's  obligation,  and  where 
custom  has  come  to  recognise  and  even  to  legalise  a 
certain  broadness  of  spirit  that  has  somewhat  of  the 
appearance  of  laxity,  they  often  seem  to  border  closely 
upon  the  unscrupulous  when  in  reality  they  are  well 
within  the  moral  boundary. 

Conscience,  therefore,  though  not  always  developed  in 
proportion  to  the  general  Reason,  is  not  a  feeling.  It  is 
one  special  function  of  the  practical  intellect. 

(5)  Moral  value  is  determined  by  pleasure  and  pain. — 
This  argument  we  have  fully  considered  in  our  chapter 
on  Hedonism.  Pleasure  is  not  our  sole  end.  And  even 
if  pleasure  were  our  only  object  of  desire  all  "  value  " 
would  still  not  depend  on  feeling.  Some  pleasures  are 
intellectual,  not  feelings  of  the  senses.* 

(c)  Conscience — a  sense  faculty. 

"  Sensistic  Morals "  and  the  theory  of  a  "  moral 
sense  "  are  not  one  and  the  same.  As  a  rule  the  ex- 
pression "  Sensistic  Morals  "  is  applied  to  the  theory 
that  moral  goodness  is  sensuous  pleasure  and  moral 
badness  sensuous  pain.  But  the  theory  of  a  moral 
sense,  which  we  are  now  considering,  is  the  theory  that 
in  man  there  is  a  special  sense  faculty  for  the  percep- 
tion of  good  and  evil.  This  moral  sense  theory  is  loftier 
and  purer  than  the  hedonistic  system,  since  whereas  in 
the   hedonistic   system   morality   is   subjective,    selfish, 

•  An  argument  which  is  sometimes  adduced  is  that  conscience  is 
a  spring  of  action  and  consequently  must  be  a  feeling.  We  have, 
however,  already  shown  that  Kcason  as  well  as  feeling  can  be  a  spring 
of  action. 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  487 

relative,  and  alterable,  morality  on  the  moral  sense 
theory  is  regarded  as  something  objective  and  inherent 
in  our  acts,  something  that  transcends  every  con- 
sideration of  advantage  or  utility  whether  of  the  indi- 
vidual or  of  the  race,  something,  therefore,  worth  pur- 
suing in  and  for  itself.  But  what  we  have  to  discuss 
now  is  not  the  nobility  or  purity  of  the  moral  sense 
theory,  but  its  truth. 

The  "  moral  sense "  theory  of  Conscience  is  not 
always  easily  distinguishable  from  the  theory  just 
criticised  of  "  Conscience  a  moral  feeling."  Speaking 
broadly,  the  moral  sense,  as  described  by  those  ethiciafis 
whom  we  are  now  considering,  is  as  distinct  from  moral 
feeling  as  the  material  senses  are  distinct  from  material 
feelings.  Thus  the  senses  are  primarily  perceptive 
faculties  ;  the  feelings  are  primarily  affective.  Whilst, 
however,  the  upholders  of  this  present  theory  make 
perception  through  sense  the  more  original  element  in 
Conscience,  some  of  them  hold  that  it  also  includes 
feelings  arising  out  of  this  sense  perception.  In  so  far 
as  this  theory  includes  a  feeling-element  in  Conscience 
it  is  identical  with  the  moral-feeling  theory  of  Con- 
science, and  stands  or  falls  with  that  theory.  We  now 
limit  ourselves  to  the  theory  that  Conscience  is  a  sense 
faculty. 

The  theory  of  "  Conscience — a  moral  sense "  has 
many  forms.  With  Hutcheson  the  moral  sense  is 
described  as  a  faculty  which  not  only  reveals  to  us  the 
general  laws  of  good  and  evil,  but  also  "  diffuses  itself 
through  all  the  conditions  of  life  and  every  part  of 
it  "  * — that  is,  it  recognises  the  morality  of  every  par- 
ticular act.  Brown  and  Reid,  on  the  other  hand,  con- 
sider that  the  moral  sense  is  capable  of  perceiving  only 
general  rules  of  morality,  f  Then,  too,  to  emphasise 
another  point   of  distinction,   with  Robinet  the  moral 

*  "  On  Human  Nature,"  Chapter  I. 

t  On  the  question  of  the  object  of  the  moral  sense,  these  '  moral 
sense  '  ethicians  arc  as  undecided  as  they  are  divided  from  one  another. 


488  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

sense  is  regarded  as  purely  material — a  sixth  sense  on 
a  par  with  the  five  external  senses  ;  whilst  with  Reid 
and  Hutcheson  it  is  a  spiritual  sense  and  quite  different 
from  what  are  known  as  the  material  senses.*  Putting 
aside  now  all  minor  questions  about  the  particular 
nature  and  qualities  of  the  moral  sense,  we  shall  con- 
fine our  attention  to  this  one  question — is  the  moral 
faculty  a  sense  faculty — i.e.,  a  non-intellectual  faculty  ? 
Can  we  cognise  morality  by  a  sense  as  we  cognise  colour 
by  sight  and  perfumes  by  smell  ?  We  reply  that  we 
cannot ;   that  the  moral  faculty  is  not  a  sense.     For — 

I.  Every  sense  has  its  own  particular  object,  which 
object  is  always  some  corporeal  or  material  quality. 
By  vision  we  see  colour,  by  hearing  sound.  No  sense 
has  relation  as  its  formal  object.  Now,  moral  goodness 
is  in  its  essence  a  relation — the  relation  of  an  act  to 
man's  last  end,  and  this  can  be  the  proper  object  of  an 
intellectual  faculty  alone.  It  may,  indeed,  be  said  that 
sight  perceives  the  spatial  relations  of  position  between 
one  coloured  body  and  another,  and  hearing  a  relation 
of  pitch  between  different  notes.  It  does  not  follow, 
however,  that  moral  relations  are  also  cognisable  by  a 
sense,  for  local  relations  are  relations  between  material 
objects,  and  if  sight  perceives  relations  of  space  it  is 
because,  primarily  and  directly,  it  perceives  the  bodies 
as  coloured,  space  being  an  attribute  of  material  bodies. 
But  morality  is  a  relation  subsisting  not  between  body 
and  body,  but  between  act  and  end,  or,  more  precisely 
still,  between  the  internal  act  or  act  of  the  will  (which 
sense  cannot  perceive),  and  an  end  which  is  also  un- 
perceivable  by  sense.  All  that  the  eye,  for  instance, 
can  see  is  the  dagger  plunged  into  a  body,  but  murder 
itself,  in  so  far  as  it  is  immoral,  lies  primarily  in  the  act 
of  the  will  directing  us  to  kill  something  which  ought 
not  to  be  killed.  This  inner  relation  the  senses  cannot 
perceive.      That,    therefore,    which    is    primarily    and 

♦  Curiously  enough  the  moral  sense,  according  to  Rcid,  gives  the 
general  principles  of  morality,  Reason  gives  the  particular  concluhion. 


I 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  489 

essentially  the  seat  of  morality  in  human  action  is  out 
of  the  reach  of  the  senses  altogether.  Consequently, 
morality  cannot  be  cognised  by  sense. 

2.  Many  acts  are  bad  merely  because  they  are  for- 
bidden— I.e.,  they  become  bad  through  a  positive  law 
directed  against  them.  Now,  such  acts,  regarded  merely 
as  acts,  are  the  very  same  before  and  after  legislation. 
Their  badness  therefore  consists  in  the  super-added 
relation  between  them  and  the  prohibitory  law  ;  and, 
so,  the  faculty  that  distinguishes  between  the  moral 
quality  of  these  acts  before  and  after  legislation  directed 
against  them  must  be  capable  not  only  of  perceiving 
the  act  done  but  also  of  appreciating  the  binding  power 
of  legislation.  And  since  this  is  impossible  to  sense, 
the  moral  faculty  cannot  be  a  sense. 

3,  It  is  as  directed  against  the  moral  sense  theory 
now  under  discussion,  and  not  against  the  theory  of  a 
rational  moral  faculty,  that  Hume's  celebrated  difficulty 
assumes  importance.  If,  Hume  argues,  immorality  be 
a  definite  relation  cognised  by  Reason,  then  wherever 
that  particular  relation  happens  to  be  realised,  whether 
in  a  free  or  a  determined  subject,  a  conscious  or  an 
unconscious  one,  the  Reason  should  instantly  recognise 
its  immorality.  Now,  we  have  seen  that  this  argument 
does  not  hold  in  the  case  of  Reason,  since  Reason  is 
able  to  distinguish  between  conscious  and  deliberate 
violations  of  a  law  and  mere  unconscious  action,  and, 
therefore,  though  we  condemn  ingratitude  in  men  we 
do  not  condemn  the  acorn  which  kills  the  parent  oak. 
But,  on  the  other  hand,  if  sense  were  the  faculty  by 
which  morality  is  perceived,  it  should  be  affected  in  the 
same  way  towards  the  ingratitude  of  a  son  who  ill-treats 
his  father  and  the  ingratitude  of  an  acorn  which  rises 
up  to  destroy  the  parent  oak.  For  a  sense  could  not 
realise,  as  Reason  can,  that  in  one  case  the  act  was 
conscious  and  free  and  in  the  other  unconscious  and 
determined.  Its  judgment,  therefore,  should  be  the 
same   in    regard   to   both   cases.     But    we   know   from 


490  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

experience  that  the  moral  faculty  is  able  to  distinguish 
clearly  the  merits  of  the  two  cases.  It  is  able  to  recognise 
that,  whereas  the  action  of  the  acorn  is  not  a  crime,  in- 
gratitude is  a  crime.  Hence,  the  moral  faculty  is  not  a 
sense. 

4.  The  senses  perceive  by  direct  intuition.  All,  there- 
fore, that  we  shall  have  to  say  later  against  intuitive 
morals  tells  equally  well  against  this  theory  of  a  moral 
sense  as  against  the  intuitive  theory  generally.  Thus, 
if  man  were  endowed  with  a  special  sense  faculty  for 
the  perception  of  morality,  there  is  no  reason  why  the 
morality  of  certain  acts  should  remain  completely 
hidden  from  him  whilst  the  morality  of  others  is  know- 
able.  Yet  there  are  acts  the  morality  of  which  is  not 
known.  The  other  arguments  against  the  intuitionist 
theory  we  need  not  anticipate  here. 

We  see,  therefore,  that  sense  is  wholly  inadequate  to 
the  fulfilling  of  the  most  essential  functions  of  the  moral 
faculty.  Of  course  it  might  be  argued  that  the  moral 
sense  is  sui  generis  and  not  in  anything  like  the  other 
senses,  and  that  consequently  we  should  not,  as  in  the 
foregoing  arguments,  expect  it  to  follow  the  laws  of  the 
other  senses — e.g.,  that  a  sense  perceives  only  what  is 
material,  that  it  perceives  only  the  external  element  of 
acts,  not  the  internal,  etc.  We  answer,  as  before,  that 
such  a  form  of  argument  is  quite  illogical,  and  that  it 
springs  from  an  unwillingness  to  submit  a  theory  to  any 
kind  of  serious  scientific  test.  There  are,  if  we  might 
adopt  an  analogy  from  Physical  Science,  arguments 
that  go  to  prove  that  electricity  is  not  a  fluid,  which 
arguments,  of  course,  presuppose  certain  essential 
characteristics  in  fluids  which  are  not  to  be  found  in 
electricity.  What  would  be  thought  of  the  scientist 
who  would  answer  these  arguments  by  claiming  that 
though  electricity  is  a  fluid,  it  is  a  fluid  sui  generis, 
and  has  none  of  the  characteristics  of  other  fluids  ? 
The  plain  answer  is — If  it  has  none  of  the  characteristics 
of  other  fluids  it  is  not  a  fluid.    So  if  the  moral  faculty 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  491 

be  a  sense  it  will  exhibit  at  least  those  essential  qualities 
that  characterise  all  the  other  senses.  If  it  has  none  of 
these  it  is  not  a  sense. 

{d)  Conscience  the  universal  or  impersonal  Reason. 

The  tendency  of  certain  schools  of  modern  Ethics  is 
to  regard  the  individual  Conscience  as  merely  a  phase 
or  moment  in  the  Universal  Reason,  which  latter,  it  is 
asserted,  is  the  only  true  and  genuine  Conscience — the 
only  Conscience  to  be  followed  and  believed.  This 
universalisation  of  Conscience  is  not  always  expressed 
in  the  same  way  by  Ethicians,  and  consequently  it  is 
often  not  easy  to  find  anything  like  common  ground 
amongst  theories  which  are  usually  classed  as  universal- 
istic.  Thus  Hegel  describes  conscience  as  "  the  ob- 
jective Universal  Spirit  "  ;  Clifford,  as  "  the  voice  of 
the  tribal  self  "  ;  Leslie  Stephen,  as  "  the  utterance  of 
the  public  spirit  of  the  race."  These  latter  two  ex- 
pressions represent,  indeed,  modified  forms  of  the 
universalistic  theory  of  Conscience  which  at  present 
we  shall  not  further  consider.  Our  examination  will 
be  confined  to  the  theory  expressly  stated  by  some 
Transcendentalists  and  Monists  and  implicitly  held  by 
all,  that  Conscience  is  the  Universal  Reason,  the  absolute 
Reason,  in  which  all  things  subsist  and  through  which 
they  come  into  being. 

Criticism — We  shall  here  set  forth  just  one  of  the 
arguments  adducible  against  this  theory  of  the  "  Uni- 
versal Conscience."  *  If  men  be  ruled  by  a  single 
universal  conscience  it  is  impossible  that  they  should 
consciously  entertain  opposed  moral  beliefs.     Now  that 

♦  As  we  are  here  dealing  with  moral  questions  only,  it  is  not  in  our 
province  at  present  to  disprove  the  general  Metaphysical  theory  (advo- 
cated by  Green  and  others)  that  there  exists  a  Universal  Ego  or  Self 
in  which  all  individual  selves  subsist.  This  theory  has  been  severely 
handled  by  many  modern  ethicians,  notably  by  Professor  Taylor  in  his 
"  Problems  of  Conduct."  Here  we  can  only  examine  the  question  on 
its  moral  side.  See,  however,  note,  page  457  ;  also  chapter  on 
Evolutionist  Ethics,  page  451. 


492  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

there  are  such  differences  in  our  moral  beliefs  will  not 
readily  be  denied.  The  question  then  is — how  could 
these  differences  be  reconciled  with  the  theory  that  there 
is  but  one  single  Conscience  existing  amongst  men,  since 
if  there  be  but  one  universal  moral  Conscience  it  is  in 
that  one  Conscience  that  such  opposed  beliefs  must 
consciously  reside  ?  Opposition  between  judgments  con- 
sciously entertained  are  possible  only  in  some  one  of 
the  three  following  ways — (i)  same  principle  of  judgment 
— i.e.,  same  mind  judging,  same  time  condition,  but 
distinction  in  the  objects  about  which  one  judges.* 
Thus  a  man  could  judge  that  one  object  is  white  and 
that  another  is  not  white  :  that  two  and  two  are  four, 
and  that  two  and  three  are  not  four.f  (2)  Same  prin- 
ciple or  mind  judging,  same  object  of  judgment,  but 
difference  in  time  conditions.  Thus,  about  a  particular 
object  the  same  intellect  can  elicit  one  judgment  to-day 
and  its  exact  contradictory  to-morrow.  (3)  Identity  of 
object  and  time,  but  difference  in  the  judging  principle, 
as  when  many  minds  hold  various  opinions  simul- 
taneously about  the  same  subject-matter.  We  can,  of 
course,  have  distinctions  under  all  three  heads  together 
— distinction  of  knowing  mind,  of  time,  and  of  object, 
and  correspondingly  different  acts  of  judgment.  But 
where  the  judging  intellect  is  one,  the  time  one,  and 
the  object  one,  a  qualitative  opposition  in  the  conscious 
moral  judgment  becomes  absolutely  impossible.  Indeed, 
in  any  mind  there  can  be  but  one  conscious  act  of  judg- 
ment at  any  particular  moment,  and  it  could  no  more 
be  positive  and  negative  than  an  object  could  at  the 
same  time  be  black  and  white.  Hence,  if  the  conscience 
of  all  men  be  one,  it  is  quite  impossible  that  at  one  and 
the  same  time  there  could  be  opposing  conscious  moral 

•  Note. — If  the  subject  be  out  of  all-time  conditions,  as  is  supposed 
in  the  theory  of  the  "  Timeless  Self,"  then  the  laws  stated  above  in 
(i)  and  (3)  hold  good.  For  such  a  being  any  contradiction  once 
cllccted  or  asserted  is  eternal. 

t  This  is  "  opposition  "  only  in  a  very  loose  sense  of  the  term — 
opp'jsition  of  quality  in  judgments. 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  493 

convictions  about  any  particular  subject-matter.  Bui 
contradictory  judgments  do  exist  in  the  consciousness 
of  different  men.  Therefore,  the  theory  of  the  Uni- 
versal Conscience  is  untrue. 

To  this  argument  there  are  three  replies  which  we 
must  consider  : — 

L  ihere  is,  in  the  first  place,  the  obvious  reply  that  the 
"  Absolute,"  as  the  monists  or  transcendentalists  teach,  con- 
tains many  individuals.  Now,  individuals  are  opposed  to 
one  another,  consequently  it  is  possible  that  an  Absolute 
Consciousness  should  contain  many  different  and  opposed 
moral  judgments  also. 

We  rejoin.— {a)  The  monistic  theory  that  all  individuals 
are  contained  as  parts  in  the  one  all-embracing  Absolute  is 
untrue  and  impossible.  The  disproof  of  this  theory,  how- 
ever, belong  to  Metaphysics  not  to  Ethics,  {b)  Even  if  it 
were  true  that  many  individuals  could  susbist  in  the  one 
Absolute  it  does  not  follow  that  many  contradictory  judg- 
ments could  subsist  in  the  one  consciousness,  for  individuals 
are  not  opposed  in  the  same  sense  in  which  contradictory 
judgments  are  opposed.  Individuals  are  opposed  in  the 
sense  that  one  is  not  and  could  not  be  the  other.  Contra- 
dictory judgments  are  opposed  in  the  sense  that  if  one  is 
true  the  other  is  false.  Individuals,  therefore,  can  exist 
together  in  the  one  world.  But  contradictories  cannot  sub- 
sist consciously  together  in  the  one  mind. 

II.  A  second  reply  to  our  argument  that  there  cannot  be  a 
single  Universal  Conscience,  since  such  a  Conscience  should 
consciously  harbour  opposed  moral  judgments,  is  given  by 
Fichte  as  follows  : — Conscience  is  not  a  judging  faculty  at  all, 
and  consequently  a  universal  conscience  could  not  contradict 
itself  *  even  though  all  consciences  were  contained  in  it. 
"  Conscience,"  Fichte  writes,  "  is  no  power  of  judgment," 
its  office  is  legislative  not  judicial.  It  does  not  tell  us  what 
is  right,  but  it  commands  us  to  do  the  right  and  for  the  sake 
of  the  right.  In  Kantian  language  (Fichte  only  develops 
Kant's  own  view)  Conscience  is  not  a  judgment  proper,  but 
the  "  pure  form  of  the  moral  judgment."  Its  act  is  not  a 
judgment  that  something  is  good,  but  an  imperative  to  do 
the  good  for  the  sake  of  duty.  It  is  what  Lass  calls  the 
"  pure  empty  form  of  scrupulosity."  To  know  what  is  the 
good  or  our  duty  in  any  particular  case  is,  according  to 

*  "  Science  of  Ethics,"  page  183. 


494  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Fichte,  the  work  not  of  conscience  but  of  a  man's  individual 
Reason,  and  it  is  in  that  work  alone  that  error  and  variation 
appear.  The  command  to  do  the  good  is  a  necessary  dictate 
of  every  man's  conscience.  Hence,  it  is  possible  that  all 
individual  consciences  should  be  contained  as  parts  in  the 
one  Universal  or  Absolute  Conscience,  nor  need  the  diversity 
of  men's  judgments  on  moral  matters  render  the  Universal 
Conscience  a  repository  of  contradictory  moral  decisions. 

Reply  to  this  second  argument : — We  assume  that  since  a 
man  does  sometimes  reason  on  moral  matters,  and  since  in 
these  cases  his  conclusions  are  expressions  of  some  particular 
duty — assertions,  namely,  that  something  is  to  be  done,  two 
premisses  at  least  are  required  from  which  to  reason,  one, 
that  the  good  is  to  be  done,  another,  that  this  act  is  good. 
Two  things  follow — {a)  that  our  two  premisses  must  both  be 
judgments ;  {b)  that  they  must  both  reside  in  the  same 
faculty  as  that  which  draws  the  conclusion.  For  {a)  if  the 
two  premisses  be  one  a  judgment  and  another  a  mere  com- 
mand, they  could  not  yield  a  conclusion.  Hence,  Conscience, 
in  giving  the  premiss  "  the  good  is  to  be  done,"  is  a  judicial 
and  not  a  dictatorial  faculty — that  is,  its  act  is  an  act  of 
judgment,  not  a  command,  (b)  The  same  faculty  that  draws 
the  conclusion,  "  this  ought  be  done,"  must  be  the  faculty 
which  issues  the  two  judgments,  "  the  good  ought  to  be 
done  "  and  "  this  is  good."  If  not,  no  conclusion  could  be 
drawn.  And  since  the  drawing  of  the  conclusion  is  the  work 
of  the  individual  Reason,  so  the  law  "  the  good  is  to  be 
done  "  cannot  come  from  the  Universal  Reason. 

III.  A  third  reply  is  given  by  Hegel,  and  is  as  follows : — 
In  man,  there  is  a  double  conscience — one,  the  "  true  con- 
science," in  which  all  men  agree  ;  the  other,  the  "  moral 
conscience,"  which  is  proper  to  each  individual,  and  by 
which  they  may  differ.  The  first  is  the  pure  "  Universal 
Conscience,"  the  second  is  the  Universal  Conscience  working 
along  with  the  individual  intellect  in  an  individual  mind. 
The  first  is  always  true  and  cannot  go  wrong ;  the  second 
may  err,*  but  the  ground  of  the  error  is  the  individual 
element    or    individual    intellect — the    element    which    the 

•  "  Philosophy  of  Right,"  page  131  (Dyde).  The  True  or  Universal 
Conscience  is  none  other  than  the  State  or  the  Ethical  objective  Spirit 
(the  absolute  Universal)  or  a  phase  of  it.  Subjective  or  formal  con- 
science belongs  to  the  individual.  The  first  cannot  err.  It  is  "  the 
disposition  to  desire  what  is  absolutely  good."  Subjective  conscience 
should  be  made  to  conform  to  the  true  conscience. 

A  full  and  interesting  account  of  Hegel's  theory  is  to  W  found  in 
Elscnhanv'  "  Entstohung  des  Cowissens.'' 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  495 

Universal  Conscience  has  not  wholly  "  taken  up  into  itself  " 
or  with  which  it  is  not  wholly  identified. 

Reply  to  Hegel. — -Now,  the  question  is — are  there  in  each 
man  two  consciences,  one  the  individual  and  one  the  Un- 
versal  ?  No  doubt,  according  to  Hegel,  the  true  Conscience 
is  the  State.  But  this  true  conscience  is  supposed  to  be  a 
formative  principle  of  the  individual  Reason.  For  State  and 
individual  are,  according  to  Hegel,  only  phases  of  the 
Absolute.  If,  then,  this  Universal  Conscience  exists  at  all 
it  must  exist  in  individuals.  If  not  we  have  nothing  to  do 
with  it,  for  our  present  question  relates  to  errors  in  individual 
moral  judgments,  and  Hegel's  theory  is  meant  to  solve 
the  difficulty  of  the  individual  error. 

If,  then,  in  the  individual  there  are  two  consciences,  how  is 
it  that  when  we  do  actually  err  in  conscience  we  are  never 
conscious  of  two  judgments,  one  that  of  the  Universal  Con- 
science (a  true  judgment),  and  one  a  judgment  of  the 
individual  and  false  ?  If  the  Universal  Intellect  be  part  of 
ourselves  or  in  ourselves,  its  judgment,  if  there  be  any, 
ought  be  recognisable  within  us,  and  then  there  is  no  reason 
why  we  should  not  be  conscious  of  it  in  cases  in  which  the 
individual  Conscience  falls  into  error.  But  when  in  error  we 
are  conscious  of  one  judgment  only — viz.,  the  false  judgment 
— and  hence  we  conclude  that  it  (the  false  judgment)  is  the 
only  one  which  is  issued  in  case  of  error.  Someone  may  say 
that  the  Universal  Conscience  is  as  yet  not  able  to  assert 
itself,  so  buried  is  it  in  the  individual  elements  from  which 
it  is  struggling  to  free  itself,  and  that  hence  its  judgment 
may  not  be  able  to  rise  above  the  threshold  of  our  Conscious- 
ness even  though  it  exists  within  us.  Our  reply  is  that  if 
after  so  many  years  of  development  it  has  not  yet  sufficiently 
freed  itself  within  us,  or  sufficiently  gained  possession  of  us 
to  make  itself  felt  or  heard  at  least  faintly  and,  as  it  were, 
from  afar,  it  is  idle  to  hope  that  it  is  ever  going  to  free  itself 
or  manifest  itself  to  us  in  any  way.  But  in  reality  there  is 
no  trace  of  any  such  second  judgment  within  us.  It  is  the 
purest  imagination.  There  is  present  in  our  consciousness 
but  one  moral  judgment  in  the  case  of  each  moral  decision. 
What  then,  if  it  exists,  is  the  Universal  Conscience  doing  ? 
Its  judgment,  it  is  maintained,  is  true  ;  but  where  is  its 
judgment  to  be  found  ?  *     And  if  it  is  not  to  be  found,  how 


*  The  pure  Universal  Conscience,  according  to  Hegei,  finds  its  ob- 
jective expression  in  the  State,  not  indeed  in  this  or  that  State  or  any 
State  that  we  know,  but  in  the  Universal  Slate.     To  look,  therefore, 


496  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

is  this  Universal  Conscience  known,  or  how  is  it  part  of  us  or 
we  part  of  it  ?  At  all  events,  the  individual  conscience  being 
the  only  one  of  which  we  have  any  knowledge,  the  individual 
conscience  is  the  only  one  that  does  the  work  we  have 
attributed  to  conscience,  and  hence  the  judgments  of  the 
Universal  Conscience  are  of  very  little  consequence  to  Moral 
Science. 

Again,  there  are  such  things  as  controversies  upon  moral 
matters.  Controversy  means  that  two  men,  A.  and  B.,  have 
opposite  convictions,  that  these  convictions  are  pitted  one 
against  another,  until  finally  one  conviction — namely,  the 
false  one — vanishes.  Now,  it  is  quite  certain  that  he  in 
whom  a  particular  conviction  has  vanished  is  conscious  that 
the  substitution  of  another  conviction  for  the  one  that  is 
gone  is  the  work  of  the  very  same  faculty  as  that  which 
formerly  was  convinced  of  the  opposite  view.  That  indi-' 
vidual  faculty  therefore  which  has  now  created  in  him  the 
true  view  of  the  case  is  the  same  that  once  was  false.  The 
true  judgment  and  the  false  belong  to  one  and  the  same 
faculty.  Further,  as  one  of  these  two  opposing  convictions 
grows  stronger  and  stronger  the  other  of  necessity  grows 
weaker  and  weaker,  until  finally  it  disappears.  But  the 
law  of  inverse  proportion  in  opposing  characteristics  holds 
only  where  the  subject  is  a  single  unit.  If  a  thing  be  one, 
then  increase  of  black  on  its  surface  .means  diminution  of 
white.  But  if  the  objects  are  two,  no  such  law  of  inverse 
proportion  holds  ;  one  can  be  black  and  the  other  white, 
and  increase  of  white  in  one  does  not  mean  decrease  of  black 
in  the  other.  So  neither  could  the  law  of  inverse  proportion 
hold  in  the  case  in  which  a  true  moral  judgment  replaces  the 
false  unless  that  very  same  faculty  or  thing  which  was  sub- 
ject of  the  false  judgment  (on  Hegel's  own  confession  the 
individual  Reason)  is  subject  also  of  the  true. 

It  will  be  said,  however,  that  our  representation  of  this 
theory  of  the  Universal  Conscience  is  crude  and  inadequate, 
that  an  individual  man  need  not  be  conscious  of  this  uni- 
versal intellect  or  its  judgments,  whilst  yet  it  may  so  trans- 
form individuals  as  gradually  to  harmonise  all  differences 
of  moral  opinion  and  bring  out  the  true  scientific  conviction 
of  the  race.     We  can  only  say  that,  whether  our  account  of 


for  attestations  of  the  Universal  Conscience  in  the  laws  of  the  State 
would  be  quite  as  irrational  as  searching  for  them  in  our  sclf- 
consciousnoss,  for  the  only  States  which  we  know  are  the  individual 
States,  just  as  the  only  Conscience  tliat  we  know  is  our  individual 
conscience. 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  497 

it  is  adequate  or  inadequate,  the  existence  of  a  Universal 
Conscience  is  a  pure  hypothesis ;  that  its  existence  has  not 
been  proved  ;  that  it  is  not  necessary  for  moral  science ; 
that,  on  the  contrary,  it  runs  counter  to  the  very  root 
elements  of  the  science.  Also,  we  may  repeat,  if  this 
Universal  Conscience  exists  in  me  and  if  I  subsist  in  it,  if  ii 
be  the  "  true  conscience,"  it  must  influence  me  in  every  act 
in  which  conscience  has  a  part ;  and  since  it  must  have,  in 
all  the  years  gone  by,  to  some  extent  at  ail  events,  shaken 
itself  free  of  the  individual  fetters — i.e.,  have  overcome  the 
individual  instead  of  being  overcome  by  the  individual — it 
must  by  this  time  have  so  asserted  itself  in  me  as  to  make 
me  at  least  faintly  conscious  of  it  when  it  speaks.  But  I 
am  not  conscious  of  it.  I  know  from  experience  that  in 
many  acts  it  exerts  no  influence  whatsoever  over  me,  so  that 
I  can  and  often  do  err  without  the  faintest  suspicion  that  I 
am  in  error.* 

There  is,  therefore,  in  each  man  but  one  Conscience — 
which  is  his  own  individual  Reason.  But  it  is  right  to 
add  that  above  us  and  distinct  from  us  there  is  one 
Universal  Reason  which  is  the  ultimate  type  and 
foundation  of  the  truth  for  every  man — namely,  God's 
Reason — to  which  all  our  judgments  must  conform  if 
knowledge  is  to  be  true. 

[e)  Theory  of  "  Conscience  the  voice  of  God." 

Briefly  stated,  this  theory  is  as  follows  :  Conscience 
has  by  nature  certain  functions  to  perform  within  us. 
These  functions  are  mainly  three  :  (i)  Conscience  con- 
fronts us  with  our  deeds  in  order  to  pass  sentence  on 
them  {iestificari) .  (2)  It  declares  the  act  which  it  has 
so  imputed  to  us  either  blameworthy  or  innocent 
{accitsare  and  excusare).     (3)  It  gives  us  a  law  for  our 

*  This  dif&culty  of  the  "  erring  conscience  "  is,  indeed,  the  night- 
mare of  Universalism.  Schleiermacher  also  attempts  to  answer  it, 
but  he  can  only  repeat  Hegel's  reply.  Conscience,  he  tells  us,  is  God 
Himself.  How,  then,  can  conscience  err  ?  Conscience,  he  answers, 
is  the  Infinite  God  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  true.  In  so  far  as  it  is  false 
it  is  identified  with  the  individual.  God  is  the  Universal  fully  de- 
veloped.    In  the  false  conscience  the  Universal  is  not  fully  developed. 

Such  childish  reasoning  can  really  only  bring  the  Science  of  Ethics 
into  disrepute. 

Vol.  I — 32 


498  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

future  conduct  commanding  us  to  do  certain  actions 
and  to  avoid  others  [instigare  and  ligare).*  Conscience 
exercises  all  these  three  functions,  and  it  exercises  them 
without  regard  to  our  wills  or  our  desires.  It  brings 
our  faults  before  us  and  chides  us  with  them  and  passes 
sentence  upon  us  coldly  and  impartially,  without  fear 
or  favour,  as  if  it  were  not  part  of  us  or  had  any  de- 
pendence on  us  whatsoever.  Conscience,  then,  bears 
upon  it  every  mark  of  supremacy.  It,  in  Butler's  words, 
"  carries  its  own  authority  with  it,"  and  is  its  own 
guarantee  that  it  has  the  right  to  try  and  condemn 
us,  to  legislate  for  us,  and  to  direct  us  in  all  that  we  do. 
We  feel  that  it  is  above  us,  that  we  cannot  evade  it, 
that  if  we  try  to  escape  it  will  pursue  and  run  us  down, 
that  it  is  always  with  us,  and  always  superior  to  us. 
It  fears  nothing  from  us,  and  delivers  its  judgments 
quite  unsympathetically,  but  always  in  such  a  way  as 
to  gain  our  instant  submission.  We  may  disobey  it, 
but  we  feel  that  we  should  not  do  so.  "  Our  mortal 
nature,"  "WTites  Professor  Caird,  "  trembles  like  a  guilty 
thing  before  this  awful  legislation  of  Reason."  It  uses 
no  material  forces  to  bring  its  laws  to  good  effect.  It 
merely  proclaims  its  right  to  legislate.  "  Had  it  might 
as  it  has  right  it  would  rule  the  world,"  says  Butler. 
We  have,  then,  within  us  a  voice  that  is  ever  calling 
us  to  account,  ever  proving  to  us  its  own  supremacy 
and  its  sanctity.  It  is  not  part  of  ourselves  because  it 
is  often  against  us.  It  is  above  us  because  it  subdues 
us,  not  externally,  but  in  the  heart.  Each  man  feels 
that  it  is  supreme  over  him,  and  that,  as  it  is  supreme 
over  him  personally,  so  it  is  supreme  over  every  man 
and  over  the  race.  What,  therefore,  is  it  ?  It  is  not 
a  creature,  for  no  creature  could  exact  from  us  such 
absolute  homage,  such  unconditional  reverence,  nor 
create  in  us  the  confusion  which  this  invisible  power 

•  On  these  three  functions  of  GDnscicncc  all  scholastic  cthiciars 
arc  agreed.  It  is  to  the  inference  from  tlicm  given  in  the  text  tl  at 
we  take  exception. 


.      THE   MORAL  FACULTY  499 

creates.  Putting  together  all  the  attributes  that  are 
exhibited  in  its  least  word — Power,  Majesty,  Beauty, 
Holiness,  etc. — we  can  only  say  that  it  bears  all  the 
marks  of  the  Supreme  Being,  the  One  all-pervading 
Spirit  who  is  above  all  things.  Conscience,  therefore, 
is  the  voice  of  God.  It  is  not  a  faculty  in  the  ordinary 
sense  of  the  word.  It  is  not  merely  a  statute  book, 
enshrining  the  Divine  law.  It  is  the  voice  of  the 
Creator  Himself,  and  when  I  hear  it  I  am  listening  to 
God  Himself,  am  in  His  presence,  just  as  I  am  present 
to  any  friend  that  I  hear  and  do  not  see.  Had  we  no 
knowledge  of  God  aliunde,  and  no  proof  of  His  existence 
as  first  cause  of  the  universe,  we  should  in  these  inti- 
mations of  conscience  find  proof  of  His  existence,  or 
rather  we  should  find  in  them  something  more  convinc- 
ing than  proof — viz.,  we  should  have  actual  experience 
of  Him  in  the  hearing  of  His  voice  and  the  receiving 
of  His  personal  commands. 

Criticism — ^To  this  line  of  argument  we  reply  as 
follows :  (i)  Conscience  is  God's  voice,  in  the  sense 
that  from  the  attestations  of  Conscience  we  may  learn 
God's  law.  (2)  Conscience  is  not  the  immediate  personal 
Voice  of  God.  (3)  In  Conscience  we  find  no  proof  of 
God's  existence. 

(i)  Conscience  is  God's  Voice  in  the  sense  that  from 
the  attestations  of  Conscience  we  may  learn  God's  law. — 
Conscience  is  that  function  of  the  practical  Reason  by 
which  we  establish  moral  conclusions.  As  a  faculty  it 
is  not  in  any  way  different  from  that  which  directs  a 
man  in  the  other  practical  concerns  of  life,  political, 
economical,  and  commercial.  Now,  if  the  practical 
Reason  be  used  aright  it  must  be  true.  If  it  is  not 
used  aright  it  will  go  wrong.  But  just  as  the  speculative  *^ 
Reason,  when  true,  is  in  perfect  harmony  with  the 
objective  order  which  it  represents,  whether  mathe- 
matical, metaphysical,  or  physical,  so  when  the  con- 
science is  true  it  expresses  and  accords  with  the  facts 
of   the   moral   world.     Now,    God's   intellect   is   always 


50O  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS   . 

true ;  nay,  from  Him  all  truth  proceeds.  Hence,  the 
true  Conscience,  the  Conscience  which  harmonises  with 
objective  truth,  is  an  exact  replica  of  God's  mind  on 
morality.  In  this  sense,  therefore.  Conscience  is  the 
voice  of  God — viz.,  as  truly  representing  God's  mind 
.  on  human  good  and  duty.  Thus,  Conscience  claims 
from  us  reverence  and  submission,  not  from  wliat  it 
is  in  itself,  but  because  through  it  we  can  come  to  know 
God's  law  in  our  regard.  Directly  and  immediately, 
therefore.  Conscience  only  tells  us  what  is  good  and 
what  is  our  duty.  But  indirectly  it  tells  us  also  what 
is  God's  mind  in  regard  to  human  obligations. 

(2)  Conscience   not   the   immediate   personal   voice   of 
God. 

(a)  Our  first  proof  of  this  proposition  is  that  if  Con- 
science were  the  personal  voice  of  God — that  is,  if  the 
personal  voice  of  God  were  the  source  of  our  knowledge 
of  moral  distinctions — then  we  should  not  be  able  to 
distinguish  between  natural  and  positive  law.  That  is, 
we  should  not  know  what  was  naturally  and  necessarily 
forbidden  by  God,  and  what  freely.  If  a  ruler  says  to 
his  subject  "  Do  this,"  and  if  this  be  the  only  way  in 
which  the  subject  can  know  that  such  and  such  an  act  is 
commanded,  he  could  not  possibly  say  whether  that  act 
was  necessarily  or  freely  commanded.  But,  now,  I  do 
distinguish  between  the  natural  and  the  positive  law. 
I  know  there  are  some  acts  that  God  must  forbid. 
Therefore,  I  am  able  without  the  aid  of  the  voice  of 
God  to  know  that  some  acts  are  bad  intrinsically.  And, 
consequently,  since  Conscience  is  the  faculty  of  the 
knowledge  of  moral  distinctions.  Conscience  is  not  the 
personal  voice  of  God. 

{b)  If  Conscience  be  the  voice  of  God,  how  can  there 
be  differences  in  men's  moral  judgments  ?  The  voice 
of  God  must  speak  truly  if  it  speaks  at  all.  Yet  the 
consciences   of   some   do   not   speak   truly.    Therefore, 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  501 

Conscience  is  not  God's  personal  voice.  And  in  this 
connection  it  is  worthy  of  remark  that  in  the  true 
judgments  of  Conscience  there  is  not  a  single  psycho- 
logical experience  which  might  in  any  sense  be  regarded 
as  indicating  the  presence  of  God  personally  in  Conscience 
which  is  not  to  be  found  also  when  our  judgment  is 
false.  This  second  portion  of  our  argument  we  recom- 
mend to  the  reader's  earnest  consideration  not  only  in 
relation  to  our  present  question  but  also  in  regard  to 
our  criticism  of  Hegel's  view  of  Conscience. 

(c).  If  Conscience  is  the  immediate  personal  voice  of 
God,  why  am  I  left  in  ignorance  about  a  great  part  of 
the  law  concerning  which  I  even  wish  for  information  ? 
It  is  worthy  of  remark,  too,  that  those  cases  in  which 
I  am  left  in  ignorance  are,  for  the  most  part,  the  more 
complicated  moral  problems,  not  the  easier  ones  ;  and 
it  is  not  likely  that  God  would  make  known  only  the 
easier  truths,  when  often  the  difficult  ones  are  more 
important. 

These  arguments  some  might  answer  by  saying  that 
God's  voice  gives  utterance  only  to  the  judgment  that 
we  ought  to  do  the  good,  and  that  then  the  individual 
Reason  determines  what  is  good  in  any  particular  case. 
But  this  form  of  the  theory  is  practically  the  same  as 
Fichte's,  and  needs  no  further  examination. 

(3)  Conscience  offers  no  proof  of  God's  existence. 

In  a  former  chapter  we  showed  where  in  the  science 
of  morals  we  might  look  for  an  ethical  proof  of  God's 
existence — not  in  the  attestation  of  Conscience,  but  in 
the  fact  that  the  natural  end  of  the  human  will  is  the 
Infinite  Good.  And  since  the  natural  end  of  any 
natural  faculty  must  be  real,  therefore  the  Infinite 
Good  is  real.     But  this  real  Infinity  is  God.* 

*  This  argument,  as  we  said  before,  is  a  rational  proof.  It  has  no 
dependence  on  mere  subjective  feelings.  It  therefore  falls  in  with  the 
other  rational  proofs  for  God's  existence  like  that  from  the  necessity 
of  a  First  Cause. 


502  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Very  different  is  the  proof  from  Conscience  as  de- 
veloped by  Cardinal  Newman  and  others.*  "  As  from 
a  multitude  of  instinctive  perceptions,"  writes  Cardinal 
Newman,  "  acting  in  particular  instances  of  something 
be}-ond  the  senses,  we  generalise  the  notion  of  an 
external  world  and  then  picture  that  world  in  and 
according  to  the  particular  phenomena  from  which  we 
started,  so  from  the  perceptive  power,  which  identifies 
the  intimations  of  conscience  with  the  reverberations 
or  echoes  (so  to  say)  of  an  external  admonition,  we 
proceed  on  to  the  notion  of  a  Supreme  Ruler  and  Judge, 
and  then  again  we  image  Him  and  His  attributes  in 
those  recurring  intimations,  otd  of  which  as  mental 
phenomena  our  recognition  of  His  existence  was  originally 
gained." 

We  reply — It  is  because  we  know  aliunde  the  existence 
of  God,  and  know  also  aliunde  that  the  intuitions  of 
Conscience  represent  the  Divine  will  that  therefore  we 
conclude  that  the  objective  moral  relations  revealed  by 
Conscience  are  commands  of  God — commands,  that  is, 
of  a  Ruler  who  is  all-perfect,  wise,  just,  and  powerful, 
of  One  who  is  not  indifferent  towards  His  own  laws, 
but  who,  as  Creator  of  that  very  order  which  Conscience 
reveals  to  us,  is  offended  and  pained  at  its  violation  by 
those  who  owe  Him  all  the  love  that  He  ma}'  claim 
from  them.  But  could  we  per  impossible  imagine  a 
state  of  civilisation  in  which  men  had  not  as  yet  thought 
about  the  existence  of  God,  and,  consequentl}',  had  as 
yet  no  idea  of  Him,  then,  indeed,  would  all  this  sacred- 
ness  of  which  Newman  speaks  be  gone  from  Conscience 
— the  sense,  that  is,  of  a  loving  Father  offended,  of 
personal  Majesty  outraged,  of  a  trust  betrayed.  We 
cannot  agree,  therefore,  with  Cardinal  Newman  when 
he  writes :  "  Though  I  lost  my  sense  of  the  moral 
deformity  of  my  acts,  I  should  not,  therefore,  lose  my 
sense  that  they  were  forbidden  to  me  " — meaning  that 
Conscience  reveals  to  me,   first   and  before  all   tilings, 

•  "  Grammar  of  Assent,"  page  104. 


\ 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  503 

not  that  an  act  is  bad,  but  that  an  act  is  forbidden  to 
us — the  badness  being  only  an  inference  from  the  pro- 
iiibition.  This,  in  leed,  is  the  plain  summing  up  of  the 
theory  of  "  Conscience  — the  voice  of  God,"  and  it  is 
disproved  by  ordinary  experience.  For,  first,  apart 
from  Revelation  it  is  not  possible  to  know  what  acts 
God  forbids  unless  our  reasoning  first  shows  tliem  to 
be  bad.  Secondly,  if  we  know  directly  the  Divine 
prohibitions,  we  should  not  need  to  reason  in  morals. 
Again,  thirdly,  if  prohibition  be  the  sole  source  of  my 
knowledge  of  evil  it  is  impossible  that  I  should  be  able 
to  distinguish  between  acts  which  God  prohibits  because 
He  must  and  acts  that  He  proliibits  because  He  freely 
wills  to  do  so.  But  we  can  and  do  make  such  distinc- 
tions. Therefore,  that  acts  are  bad  is  known  on  other 
grounds  than  those  of  Divine  prohibition. 

Our  conclusion  is  that  in  Conscience  we  find  no  proof 
of  God's  existence. 

Note. — That  Conscience  is  the  Voice  of  God  or  some 
other  direct  expression  or  manifestation  of  Him  has  been 
held  by  various  sch«>()ls  of  etiiicians,  whom  we  do  not  think 
it  necessary  to  con.^iller  in  any  special  or  formal  manner 
here.  This  tlieory  is  natural!}-  adopted  by  nearly  all  pan- 
theists and  monists,  especially  by  those  wlio  make  Reason 
the  universal  principl<'.  Thus  Krause  [author  of  many 
P^thical  works,  principally  the  "  System  der  Sittenlehre " 
(1810),  "  Das  Urbild  der  Menscheit "  (1812)  ]  represents 
Morality  as  fell  within  us,  as  a  result  of  the  impulse  of  the 
Divinity  to  realise  itself  in  the  world.  Duty  is  tlie  constrain- 
ing force  of  this  impulse.  Krause's  theory  is  brieliy  described 
by  Jodl,  "  Gcschichte  der  Ethik,"  page  96,  from  whom  we 
take  the  following  :  "  The  one  all-embracing  Reason  (which 
Krause  regards  as  an  Eternal  sphere  within  the  Divine 
Being  and  co-ordinate  with  nature,  somewhat  after  the 
manner  of  Spinoza's  attributes)  passes  over  into  the  indivi- 
dual and  into  the  time-series  of  (nature),  in  order  to  manifest 
God  (to  men)  through  the  realisation  of  Reason  in  nature, 
whilst  (at  the  same  time)  it  works  in  the  individual  as  the 
fundamental  impulse  of  things  (Urtrieb).  This  imjuilse  is  the 
eternal  God-directed  causality  of  the  (absolute)  Reason  itself. 
It  carries  with  itself  its  own  authority  as  the  feeling  of  the 


504  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

unconditioned  original  '  ought ' — of  unconditioned  obliga- 
tion, of  the  unchanging  command  that  the  Urtrieb  alone 
should  regulate  the  construction  of  the  time-series,  because 
it  (the  Urtrieb)  tends  to  the  one  highest  good.  The  activity 
of  this  impulse  may  be  regarded  either  as  necessary  or  as 
free.  .  .  .  it  is  necessary  in  so  far  as  it  is  the  universal 
essential  form  of  all  rational  activity  as  well  as  its  eternal 
life-form.  It  is  free  in  so  far  as  it  is  present  in  and  is 
formative  of  this  time  sphere." 

Whether  this  account  of  Conscience  is  of  real  value  to 
Philosophy  we  leave  the  reader  to  determine. 


APPENDIX 
On  Probabilism 


It  would  be  impossible  for  us  to  give  a  full  account  of  the 
theory  of  Probabilism  in  the  present  work,  but  we  may 
mention  its  essential  features.  Its  first  principle  is  that  it  is 
unlawful  for  a  maii  to  act  ejccept  with  a  certain  Conscience  of 
the  lawfulness  of  his  act,  since  the  same  law  that  forbids  any 
man  from  doing  evil  forbids  him  also  from  running  the  risk 
of  evil  or  of  doing  what  may  he  evil.  Now,  when  we  say  that 
a  man  should  have  a  certain  Conscience  that  his  act  is  lawful 
we  do  not  mean  that  he  should  be  certain  that  the  act  that 
is  done,  considered  abstractedly  or  in  itself,  is  a  good  act, 
but  he  should  be  certain  that  his  doing  of  this  act  is  lawful. 
Different  ethicians  often  hold  different  views  as  to  the^ 
lawfulness  or  unlawfulness  of  certain  courses  taken  in  them- 
selves. Some  say  these  courses  are  good,  some  that  they  are 
evil ;  but,  provided  that  these  views  are  solidly  grounded — 
khat  is,  are  supported  by  prudent  and  well-grounded  reasons 
I — then  it  is  certainly  lawful  for  us  to  follow  either  view,  even 
[though  the  other  view  which  we  do  not  follow  is  more  probable 
Ithan  the  view  which  we  follow.  We  say  "it  is  certainly 
lawful,"  because  it  is  certain  that  no  law  can  bind  in  con- 
science, in  such  a  way  that  to  violate  it  is  a  sin,  unless  the 
law  be  fully  and  certainly  promulgated  to  our  reason  ;  but 
a  law  which  is  only  probable,  or  which  only  probably  forbids 
a  certain  course  of  conduct,  is  not  fully  promulgated  to  ns, 
and  hence  it  is  certainly  lawful  for  us  to  ignore  such  a  law  and 
to  do  those  things  which  it  is  supposed  to  forbid.  Hence  it 
is  certainly  lawful  to  do  an  act  which  is  only  proba])ly  for- 


THE  MORAL  FACULTY  505 

bidden,  or,  as  Ethicians  say,  it  is  lawful  to  use  a  probable 
'opmion  against  a  law. 

It  is  necessary  to  point  out  two  things  in  regard  to  this 
rule  of  Probabilism  that  it  is  lawful  to  do  a  thing  which  only 
probably  violates  a  law.  JOne  is  that  the  rule  applies  princi- 
pally to  questions  of  lawfulness..  It  has  as  a  rule  nothing 
to  do~with  questions  of  va,ri3iFy,  For  inslanuy'llli  contract 
would  still  be  invalid  which  opposes  some  invalidating  law, 
even  though,  at  the  time  of  making  it,  it  wasnot  certain 
that  the  law  invalidated  the  contract.  SeconoljL^^here  are 
some  supposed  exceptions  to  the  rule  of  Probabmsm,  cases, 
viz.,  of  mere  lawfulness,  where  yet  the  rule  fails  to  apply. 
An  example  is  that  of  a  man  who  shoots  for  fun  into 'a 
street  crowded  with  people.  Now,  even  though,  in  this 
case,  it  is  only  probable  that  some  one  will  be  killed,  still 
the  law  of  Probabilism  does  not  hold.  The  person  con- 
cerned cannot  say  it  is  probable  all  will  escape,  and  therefore 
I  may  shoot.  Such  an  act  would  be  quite  unlawful.  We 
believe,  however,  that  the  case  is  not  a  genuine  exception 
to  the  rule  of  Probabilism.  For  the  question  in  this  case  is 
not  of  a  right  or  law  which  is  being  only  probably  violated, 
but  of  a  right  which  is  being  certainly  violated  ;  and  the 
right  which  is  certainly  violated  is  the  right  each  man  has 
not  only  that  others  should  not  take  away  his  life,  but  that 
tlicy  should  not  wantonly  endanger  it. 


CHAPTER  XV 

ON    INTUITIONISM :     OR,    IS    MORALITY    SELF- 
EVIDENT  ? 

Having  seen  that  the  moral  faculty  is  none  other  than 
the  practical  intellect,  the  question  naturally  arises  how 
the  intellect  attains  to  the  knowledge  of  moral  truth — 
whether  the  knowledge  of  moral  distinctions  is  intuitive 
and  immediate  or  whether  it  results  from  reasoning. 

The  importance  of  the  question  whether  morality  is 
self-evident — that  is,  is  known  immediately  or  intui-  "^ 
tively — ^will  not,  we  think,  be  called  in  question  by  any- 
one who  knows  the  requirements  of  a  science  of  morals. 
In  any  science  it  is  important  to  know  what  truths  are 
self-evident — that  is,  what  truths  may  be  accepted  with- 
out proof.  In  every  science,  and  even  in  every  art, 
something  may  always  be  accepted  without  proof. 
"  There  aie  some  people,"  writes  Aquinas,  "  who  want 
to  have  (even)  the  principle  of  contradiction  proved  to 
them,  (a  state  of  mind)  which  is  the  result  of  '  apae- 
deusia,'  or  want  of  education  and  discipline.  It  is  from 
want  of  education  that  some  men  never  know  what 
propositions  need  proof  and  what  do  not,  for  not  every- 
thing can  be  proved."  *  We  must,  then,  in  each  science 
accept  certain  principles  as  self-evident. 

On  the  other  hand,  to  regard  everything  as  self- 
evident  or  intuitively  known  would  mean  the  complete 
abolition  of  science,  because  for  things  intuitively  known 
there  is  no  need  of  a  science,  whose  function  is  to  pro- 
ceed from  the  known  to  the  unknown. 

Now,  some  authorities  seem  disinclined  to  allow  that 
anything  in  morals  is  intuitively  known,  whilst  others 

•  "  Commentaries  on  Aristotle."  Metaphysicorum,  Liber  1V.> 
Lectio  VI. 

506 


ON  INTUITIONISM  507 

regard  everything  as  intuitive,  and  hence  we  have 
undertaken  to  discuss  this  question  of  how  far 
we  may  regard  the  morahty  of  actions  as  intuitively 
known  or  self-evident,  and  how  far  it  requires  reason- 
ing. 

The  question  whether  morality  is  self-evident  will  be 
treated  by  us  under  the  following  headings  : — 

{a)  Exposition  of  our  own  view,  which  is  based  on 
the  Ethics  of  Aquinas,  that  some  of  the  more  funda- 
mental moral  truths  are  self-evident. 

{b)  The  theory  of  Perceptional  or  Unphilosophic 
Intuitionism,  that  not  only  all  moral  principles,  but 
even  the  morality  of  all  individual  acts,  are  self-evident 
or  are  known  intuitively. 

(c)  The  theory  of  Common  Sense  or  Philosophic 
Intuitionism,  that  all  general  moral  truths  are  known 
intuitively  (with,  however,  a  vague  use  of  the  word 
"  general  "). 

[d]  Some  special  theories  of  Intuitive  Morality. 


{a)  Exposition  of  our  own  Doctrine 
(i)  Meaning  of  "  Self-evident  truth." 

Before  making  a  critical  examination  of  theories  of 
self-evident  morality  we  must  explain  precisely'  what 
is  meant  b}^  a  self-evident  truth.  A  self-evident  truth 
(or,  as  Aquinas  calls  it,  per  se  nota)  is  a  truth  which 
is  evident  to  anybody  who  knows  the  meaning  of  the 
terms — that  is  to  say,  the  truth  in  question  is  appre- 
hended without  reasoning,  and  on  the  mere  enunciation 
of  the  proposition  it  is  seen  that  the  predicate  is  con- 
tained in  the  subject. 

There  are  some  self-evident  truths  the  terms  of  which 
are  understood  by  all  men — for  example,  the  truth  that 
the  whole  is  greater  than  the  part.  These  self-evident 
truths  are  self-evident  to  all  men.     There  are  other  self- 


5o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

evident  truths  the  terms  of  which  are  understood  only 
by  the  wise.  These  truths  are  self-evident  only  to 
the  wise.* 

It  is  hardly  necessary  to  point  out  that  it  does  not 
follow  from  what  we  have  just  said  that  whatever  pro- 
positions are  known  to  all  are  also,  in  the  strict  sense  of 
the  word,  self-evident.  For  there  are  some  truths  that 
can  be  known  by  a  very  simple  process  of  reasoning,  so 
simple,  indeed,  that  the  mind  cannot  help  performing  it 
if  it  thinks  at  all,  and  these  truths  may  be  known  to 
all.  Now,  since  they  involve  reasoning,  these  truths 
are  technically  and  strictly  not  self-evident  or  intuitive. 
Yet  they  may  be  almost  intuitive,  and  we  think  that 
Ethicians  generally  would  be  willing  in  practice  to 
regard  such  truths  as  self-evident  or  intuitive. 

In  our  discussion  on  Intuitive  Morality  our  position 
(in  agreement  with  Aquinas)  is  that  some  fundamental 
moral  truths  are  self-evident,  and  by  this  we  mean 
that  they  are  self-evident  to  all  men  because  the  terms 
of  a  moral  proposition  are  simple  and  understood  by 
all  men.  We  will  now  in  this  sense  take  up  the 
question — 


(2)  Are  any  moral  principles  self-evident  ? 

That  some  fundamental  moral  truths  are  self-evident 
is  manifestly  Aquinas'  teaching,  for  he  makes  frequent 
reference  to  the  primary  precepts  of  the  natural  law  in 
the  human  Reason  as  holding  the  same  place  in  morals 
that  self-evident  principles  hold  in  the  speculative 
sciences.  Thus,  regarding  the  question  whether  the 
precepts  of  the  natural  law  are  one  or  many  he  writes : 
"  The  precepts  of  the  natural  law  in  man  in  regard  to 


•  A  self-evident  truth  considered  in  itself  and  without  refcrciice  to 
its  being  presented  to  or  understood  by  a  human  intellect  is  called  by 
Aquinas  per  se  nola  in  se.  A  self-evident  truth  actually  presented  to 
our  intellect,  and  consequently  understood  by  us  if  wc  understand  its 
terms,  is  called  per  se  nota  quoad  nos. 


ON  INTUITIONISM  509 

action  are  like  the  primary  principles  in  the  demonstra- 
tive (sciences).  But  the  primary  indemonstrable  "  {i.e., 
self-evident)  "  principles  are  many  ;  therefore  the  pre- 
cepts of  the  law  of  nature  are  many."  * 

Now,  it  is  clear  that  some  moral  propositions  must 
be  self-evident,  for  many  of  our  moral  beliefs  are 
deduced  from  other  beliefs,  and  all  deductions  must 
ultimately  begin  with  principles  that  are  self-evident. 
If  any  deductive  science  were  without  such  principles 
it  is  impossible  that  we  should  ever  reason  in  that 
science.  For  all  reasoning,  like  all  movement,  must 
begin  from  a  fixed  point,  and  in  the  case  of  reasoning 
the  fixed  point  is  the  principle,  or  group  of  principles, 
which  the  human  intellect  accepts  without  the  need  of 
reasoning  and  on  the  ground  of  their  own  intrinsic 
evidence.  Hence,  there  must  be  some  self-evident 
moral  principles. 

Some  might  urge  against  this  view  that  the  first 
principles  of  Morals — though  first  and  indemonstrable 
in  the  science  of  Morals — may  yet  be  capable  of  and 
require  proof  in  some  other  science  more  fundamental 
than  that  of  Morals,  and  that  consequently  they  are 
not  self-evident.  Our  reply  is  that  the  principles  of 
Morals  are  principles  about  goodness  and  duty,  and 
such  principles  could  not  be  proved  except  by  other 
premisses  that  concern  goodness  and  duty — wliich 
latter  premisses  are,  therefore,  themselves  moral 
propositions  ("  the  first  principles  of  Ethics  must 
themselves  be  Ethical ")  ;  and  since  reasoning  must 
begin  with  what  is  self-evident  these  fundamental 
moral  propositions,  on  which  all  others  are  grounded 
and  by  which  they  are   proved,    must    be   self-evident 

*  "  S.  Theol.,"  I.,  II.,  Q.  XCIV.,  Art.  2.  Again  Aquinas  writes— 
"  S.  Theol.,"  I.,  Q.  LXXIX.,  Art.  12 — "  Sicut  ratio  speculativa  ratio- 
cinatur  de  speculativis,  ita  ratio  practica  ratiocinatur  de  operabilibus  ; 
oportet  igitur  naturaliter  nobis  esse  indita  sicut  principia  speculabilium 
ita  et  principia  operabilium.  .  .  .  Principia  operabilium  nobis  natural- 
iter indita  non  pertinent  ad  specialem  potentiam  sed  ad  specialem 
Ijabitum  naturalem  quem  dicimus  synderesim,  unde  et  synderesis 
dicitur  instigare  ad  bonum,"  etc. 


510  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

principles.  There  are,  then,  some  self-evident  moral 
propositions. 

But  now  we  come  to  the  much  more  difficult  ques- 
tion— ^Which  are  these  self-evident  moral  principles  ? 

The  reader  must  not  expect,  nor  would  it  be  possible 
to  give,  a  full  enumeration  of  all  those  propositions 
which  we  regard  as  self-evident.  But  the  following 
\vill  represent  which,  in  our  view,  are  the  main  classes 
of  self-evident  truths,  and  what  the  principle  under 
which  we  class  them  as  self-evident. 

In  the  first  place,  it  is  a  self-evident  proposition  that 
"  the  good  must  be  done  and  evil  must  be  avoided," 
for  every  man's  will  is  necessarily  fixed  upon  the  good 
in  general  and  necessaril}-  repelled  by  evil  as  such.  We 
cannot  help  approving  the  good  as  something  to  be 
done.* 

But  not  only  is  it  self-evident  that  the  good  must  be 
done,  but  it  is  also  self-evident  that  certain  ends  or 
objects  or  acts  are  good.  For,  since  goodness  means 
the  object  of  appetite  {honiim  est  appetihile  being  our 
definition  of  good)  it  follows  that  that  will  be  self- 
evidently  good  which  we  naturally  desire,  that  when  a 
man  is  moved  by  a  natural  appetite  to  the  pursuit  of 
any  particular  kind  of  object,  the  Practical  Reason 
must,  without  reasoning  of  any  kind,  represent  that 
object  as  a  good.  Thus,  no  man  could  fail  to  recognise 
the  goodness  of  food  or  of  society,  for  every  man  is 
moved  by  natural  appetite  or  inclination  to  food  and 
to  society,  and  the  definition  of  goodness  is  "  that  to 
wliich  we  are  moved  by  appetite."  Hence,  their  good- 
ness is  self-evident.  This  does  not  mean  that  the  pur- 
suit of  these  objects  under  all  circumstances  is  good. 
For  even  when  we  have  recognised  that  certain  things 
are  good  in  themselves,  we  must  still  recognise  that 
even  such  goods  must  be  pursued  in  a  due  manner — 

•  A  proximate  and  easy  deduction  from  this  self-evident  trutli  is 
that  the  necessary  means  to  our  final  end  ought  to  be  taken,  which, 
as  we  saw,  is  the  principle  of  moral  duty. 


ON  INTUITIONISM  511 

that  is,  under  laws  and  conditions  that  regulate  the 
attaining  of  these  natural  ends.  Thus,  every  man 
knows  that  though  eating  is  good,  eating  in  such  a  way 
as  to  injure  oneself  is  not  good.  So  also  the  desire  of 
sex  is  a  good  thing.  But  this  end  must  be  pursued  in 
such  a  way  as  that  the  natural  object  of  such  a  faculty 
may  be  obtained,  that  is,  the  birth  and  rearing  of  off- 
spring.* The  pursuit,  then,  of  even  the  natural  objects 
is  subject  to  certain  defmite  laws  and  conditions.  The 
determination  of  these  laws  and  conditions  may  require 
much  reasoning.  But,  taken  in  itself,  every  object  to 
which  our  appetites  naturally  incline  us  must  appear 
to  us  as  good. 

These  self-evidently  good  ends  may  be  divided  into 
different  classes  according  to  the  class  of  appetite  that 
inclines  us  towards  them.  Thus,  since  in  common  with 
every  substance  man  possesses  a  natural  appetite  for 
his  own  continued  existence,  and  since  goodness  is 
defined  as  the  object  of  appetite,  it  follows  that  to  each 
man  his  existence  is  a  self-evident  good.  In  common, 
too,  with  all  animals,  man  has  certain  natural  appetites, 
like  those  for  food,  for  racial  intercourse,  and  for  the 
care  of  offspring,  f  and,  therefore,  the  goodness  of  these 
ends  is  manifest  and  self-evident.  Other  natural 
appetites  are  proper  to  man  as  a  rational  being,  like 
the  appetite  for  society  and  for  knowledge  ;  and  hence 
it  is  a  self-evident  truth  that  society  and  advance  in 
knowledge  are  human  goods.  We  should  explain,  how- 
ever, that  by  society  as  end  of  a  natural  appetite  we  do 
not  mean  mere  living  together  (for  animals  also  live 
together),  but  the  amicable  intercourse  of  one  person 
with  another,  and  general  interchange  of  services  ac- 
cording to  our  needs.  And  since  society,  in  this  sense, 
is  a  self-evident  good,  the  law  to  treat  amicably  those 

*  See  Vol.  II.,  pages  59-64. 

f  The  necessity  of  marriage  in  the  sense  of  a  stable  (not  necessarily 
an  indissoluble)  union  of  the  sexes  is  an  obvious  conclusion  from  the 
necessity  of  the  care  of  offspring.  For  a  fuller  treatment  of  these 
natural  appetites,  see  chapter  on  The  Good. 


512  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

with  whom  we  Hve  (as  Aquinas  says,  "  quod  aHos  non 
offendat  cum  quibus  debet  conversari ")  and  not  to 
injure  them,  is  a  self-evident  law.* 

These  are  aU  examples  of  self-evident  moral  truths. 
And  being  self-evident  we  do  not  think  it  possible  that 
any  nation  could  be  without  a  knowledge  of  them  ; 
for  what  is  self-evident  must  be  known  to  all.  Thus, 
it  is  impossible  that  any  nation  should  fail  to  recognise 
that  it  is  a  good  thing  in  general  to  preserve  one's  own 
being  and  that  to  injure  it  is  evil.  (The  goodness  of 
preserving  our  own  being  in  all  farticular  cases  and 
circumstances  is  not  self-evident,  but  is  a  conclusion  of 
our  reasoning.)  Also,  no  nation  could  regard  the  care 
of  offspring  as  bad  or  indifferent  (and  if  it  thinks  at 
all  it  could  not  fail  to  recognise  the  necessity  of  mar- 
riage, which  is  a  proximate  and  obvious  conclusion 
from  the  necessity  of  the  care  of  offspring).  Again, 
no  nation  could  be  ignorant  of  the  goodness  of  society 
and  of  the  necessity  of  a  law  of  justice  for  its  main- 
tenance. This  law  of  justice  arises  from  the  fact  that 
to  injure  others  is  wrong,  and  self -evidently  wrong  ; 
for,  as  we  have  said,  the  social  life  to  which  we  are  im- 
pelled by  natural  appetite  is  not  mere  living  together, 
but  a  life  of  amicable  intercourse  of  many  persons  in 
one  community.  And  as  amicable  intercourse  and 
injury  are  direct  opposites  it  is  self-evident  that  injury 
within  our  own  communion  is  evil.f 

•  As  we  explained  elsewhere,  there  are  certain  ends  for  which  we 
have  natural  appetites,  and  which  are  therefore  self-evidently  good, 
which  would  also  appear  to  us  as  good  and  necessary,  even  though 
we  had  no  special  appetite  for  them,  since  they  are  necessary  means 
to  other  ends  which  are  objects  of  appetite.  Thus,  even  if  we  had  no 
special  appetite  for  food,  we  should  regard  food  as  good  and  eating  as 
a  duty  since  it  is  necessary  for  life,  which  naturally  we  desire. 

\  We  speak  here  of  the  general  law  only.  The  morality  of  par- 
ticular cases,  esfxicially  those  in  which  there  is  a  conflict  of  appetites, 
is  not  necessarily  self-evident. 

The  law  against  stealing  is  not  a  self-evident  law  but  a  deduction 
from  the  law  forbidding  injury.  Hence  some  nations  have  been 
ignorant  of  the  wrongfulness  of  stealing,  as  Aquinas  himself  testifies. 

Again,  though  the  killing  of  others  of  the  same  society  with  our- 
selves is  self-evidently  wrong,  the  killing  of  men  of  other  societies  is 


ON  INTUITIONISM  513 

Our  view,  then,  of  the  question  whether  morality  is 
self-evident  is  that  certain  fundamental  truths  are  self- 
evident  and  intuitive,  and  known  to  all,  that  other 
proximate  and  obvious  deductions  from  these,  though 
not  technically  self-evident,  are  almost  so,  for  they 
become  evident  to  anyone  who  exercises  his  Reason. 
These  truths  are  also  known  to  all.  The  remote  con- 
clusions are  obtained  only  after  much  reasoning,  and 
sometimes  only  after  some  experience,  and  these  truths, 
though  perhaps  necessary  truths,  are  neither  self-evident 
nor  known  to  all. 

This  view  of  the  question  "  which  are  the  self-evident 
principles  of  morals  "  recommends  itself  to  us  for  many 
reasons.  First,  we  believe  that  it  is  in  accordance  with 
sound  psychological  principles — namely,  {a)  that  there 
are  certain  natural  objects  of  appetite,  (6)  that  the 
object  of  a  natural  appetite  is  necessarily  known  to  us. 
Second,  it  harmonises  with  experience  and  with  the 
conclusions  of  Anthropology  concerning  the  moral 
beliefs  of  various  nations.  There  are  certain  broad 
general  principles  that  are  known  to  all.  This  will 
be  proved  in  the  following  chapter.  Thirdly,  it  is 
grounded  on  the  Ethical  teachings  of  Aquinas.  For, 
though  Aquinas  does  not  expressly  state  that  the  laws 
which  we  have  given  as  self-evident,  and  which  we  have 
taken  from  him,  are  self-evident  in  the  strict  sense  of 
the   word,    he   ne\'ertheless   speaks   of   them    as   being 

not  self-evidently  wrong,  but  is  a  conclusion  of  our  Reason  based  on 
the  consideration  of  man's  natural  end.  The  necessity  of  maintaining 
that  society  in  which  we  live  is  also  self-evident.  But  the  question  of 
the  extent  of  society  and  of  our  relations  to  the  members  of  other 
social  bodies  requires  reasoning.  Hence  some  savage  tribes  did  not 
know  that  it  was  wrong  to  kill  the  members  of  other  tribes.  Of  this 
however,  we  shall  speak  later,  page  565. 

The  reader  should  understand  that  though  we  claim  that  certain 
ends  are  self-evidently  good,  and  give  rise  to  self-evident  laws,  still  the 
proper  formulation  of  these  laws  so  as  to  bring  them  into  harmony 
with  the  whole  organic  system  of  human  requirements  is  by  no  means 
an  easy  thing,  and  is  a  result  often  of  the  most  advanced  reasoning. 
Thus,  though  injury  is  an  evident  evil  considered  in  itself,  the  law 
against  homicide  is  by  no  means  an  easy  law  to  formulate.  Us 
formulation  is  the  work  of  the  scientific  ethician  only. 
Vol.  1—33 


514  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

known  to  the  intellect  naturaliter*  and  also  as  being 
known  to  all  men  and  as  incapable  of  being  -blotted 
out  of  the  human  heart. 


Other  Views  on  Intuitionism 

Having  now  stated  our  own  theory  we  will  take  up 
some  modern  theories  of  Intuitionism.  To  these  we  will 
prefix,  by  way  of  prefatory  note,  a  short  statement  of 
the  different  senses  in  which  the  expression  "  Intuitive 
knowledge  of  Morality  "  is  used  by  modern  writers. 

The  distinction  between  "  intuitive  knowledge  "  and 
other  knowledge  is  based  by  some  on  the  character  of 
the  object  of  the  intuition,  by  others  on  the  origin  of 
this  intuitive  knowledge.  Thus  the  phrase  "  Intuition 
of  Morality  "  has  been  used  to  signify — (i)  Knowledge 
of  the  morality  of  an  act  through  the  intrinsic  nature 
of  the  act  without  reference  to  the  act's  consequences. 
Here  intuitive  character  depends  on  object.  (2)  Innate 
knowledge  of  morality.  (3)  A  -priori  knowledge  of 
morality.  (4)  Knowledge  of  morality  obtained  without 
reasoning — that  is,  without  a  discursive  act  of  the 
intellect.  This  knowledge  is  called  immediate  know- 
ledge, and  is  contrasted  with  mediate  knowledge,  which 
is  knowledge  obtained  by  reasoning. 

The  word  "  Intuition  "  is  used  in  the  first  sensfe  (the 
'knowing  of  the  morality  of  an  act  independently  of  the 

• "  S.  Theol.,"  I.,  II.,  Q.  XCIV.,  Art.  2.  "  Quia  vero  bonum 
habct  rationcm  finis,  malum  autem  rationem  contrarii,  inde  est  quod 
omnia  ilia  ad  quae  homo  habet  naturalcm  inclinationem,  ratio  naturaliter 
aprchendit  ut  bona  et  per  consequcns  ut  operc  proscqucnda,  ct  con- 
traria  eorum  ut  mala  ct  vitanda." 

The  general  meaning  of  this  word  naturaliter  is  given  in  Aquinas' 
"  Commentaries  on  Aristotle  " — Liber  IV.  Metaphysicorum,  Lectio  VI., 
where  writing  on  the  conditions  of  a  first  speculative  principle,  he  says  : 
"  Tertia  conditio  est  ut  non  acquiratur  per  dcmonstrationcm  vel  alio 
simili  modo  sed  adveniat  quasi  per  naturam  habenti  ipsum,  quasi  ut 
naturaliter  cognoscatur  et  non  per  acquisitioncm.  Ex  ipso  onim  lumine 
natural!  intellectus  agentis  prima  principa  fiunt  cognita  ;  ncc  ac- 
quiruntur  per  ratiocinationcui  sed  solum  per  hoc  quod  corum  termini 
innotcscunt." 


ON  INTUITIONISM  515 

consequences)  b}^  Sidgwick  and  Rashdall.*  "  Intui- 
tion "  is  used  in  the  second  sense  by  Paley  and  Bain, 
with  whom  intuitive  knowledge  means  "  Innate  Know- 
ledge," and  the  expression  "  Intuitive  Morals  "  means 
"  Innate  Moral  Judgments."  "  Intuition  "  is  used  in 
the  third  sense  by  Professor  Seth,  who  applies  the  term 
to  all  a  priori  knowledge — that  is,  to  all  knowledge  not 
gained  by  experience.  "  Intuition "  is  used  in  the 
fourth  sense  by  Reid  and  Cumberland,  in  whose  writ- 
ings "  Intuition  "  is  "  immediate  knowledge  "  (in  which 
they  include  knowledge  both  of  sense  and  intellect). 
This  meaning  of  "  intuition  "  in  the  sense  of  immediate 
knowledge  forms,  as  the  reader  has  already  seen,  the 
chief  subject  of  our  present  chapter.  Most  schools 
mean  by  "  intuitive  Morals  "  the  theory  that  we  have 
an  immediate,  as  opposed  to  a  mediate  knowledge  of 
morality — that  we  know  morality  without  the  need  of 
reasoning.  We  shall,  therefore,  in  the  following  pages 
use   the   word   Intuitionism   in   this   sense — namely,   to 

♦  The  meaning  of  Intuitionism  which  we  here  give  as  the  sense  in 
which  the  word  is  used  by  Sidgwick,  is  that  which  it  has  in  the  opening 
pages  of  his  chapter  on  Intuitionism.  But  it  is  not  his  fundamental 
definition  of  "  Intuition."  This  fundamental  definition  is  found  in 
Sidgwick's  "  Methods,"  page  211,  where,  writing  on  the  question 
whether  "  Intuition  "  is  always  supposed  to  be  true,  he  says  :  "  I  wish 
therefore  to  say  expressly  that  by  calling  any  affirmation  as  to  the 
tightness  or  wrongness  of  acts  intuitive  ...  I  only  mean  that  its 
truth  is  apparently  known  immediately  and  not  as  a  result  of  reason- 
ing." The  first  definition  of  "  Intuition  "  (that  given  as  Sidgwick's 
in  the  text  above)  is  really,  though  not  professedly,  deduced  from  the 
second  or  fundamental  definition  ;  but  in  making  the  deduction  he 
assumes  a  proposition  which  is  false — namely,  that  if  reasoning  were 
required  in  determining  morality,  it  could  only  be  required  for  the 
determining  of  consequences. 

Rashdall  is  guilty  of  precisely  the  same  inconsistency  and  assump- 
tion of  what  is  false.  Rashdall's  first  definition  is  that  given  in 
our  text.  His  second  and  more  fundamental  definition  is  gathered 
from  a  passage  in  the  first  volume  of  his  work  on  "  Theory  of  Good  and 
Evil  "  (page  93),  where,  writing  of  certain  goods  like  pleasure,  he  says  : 
"  The  value  of  these  elements  in  human  life  is  determined  by  the 
Practical  Reason  intuitively,  immediately,  or  (if  we  like  to  say  so) 
a  priori."  And  in  the  note  to  this  passage  he  explains  that  by  a  priori 
he  means  that  "  the  judgment  is  immediate — not  obtained  by  inference 
or  deduction  from  something  else,  in  the  way  in  which  the  Utilitarian 
supposes  his  judgments  to  be  deductions  from  rules  got  by  generalisa- 
tion from  experience." 


5i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

signify  the  system  which  professes  an  immediate  know- 
ledge of  moral  truths  (whether  these  truths  be  par- 
ticular or  general,  and  whether  the  knowledge  of  them 
be  gained  through  the  senses  or  the  intellect)  as  opposed 
to  mediate  knowledge  or  knowledge  by  logical  inference 
from  premiss  to  conclusion. 

Of  "  Intuitionism  "  in  this  last  sense  two  forms  are 
distinguished  by  recent  writers  on  Ethics — the  theories 
of  Perceptional  Intuition  and  of  Common  Sense  Intui- 
tion. The  first  is  the  theory  that  all  men  can,  by  means 
of  direct  perception  and  without  reasoning  of  any  kind, 
pronounce  ordinarily  on  the  morality  of  particular  acts 
at  the  moment  of  action.  According  to  this  theory  there 
is  no  necessity  for  the  use  of  general  moral  principles  of 
any  kind  in  the  making  of  judgments,  since  Conscience, 
it  is  claimed,  is  able  to  perceive  whether  an  act  is  good 
or  bad  in  the  very  same  manner  as  vision  perceives  that 
a  body  is  white. 

The  second  theory  is  that  all  men  have  an  intui- 
tive knowledge,  not  of  the  morality  of  particular  acts, 
but  of  general  principles — at  least  of  the  simplest 
general  moral  principles,  such  as  that  the  good  is  to  be 
done,  and  that,  in  general,  murder,  stealing,  and  lying 
are  bad  and  ought  to  be  avoided.  These  two  theories 
we  shall  have  to  consider  separately. 

The  Theory  of  Perceptive  Intuition  is  held  by  Mansell 
and  McCosh,  and  apparently  also  by  Martineau  and  Hutche- 
son.  "  Whatever,"  writes  McCgsh  ("  Intuitions  of  the  Mind," 
pages  31-32),  "  be  their  distinctive  nature,  they  always,  as 
Intuitions,  primarily  contemplate  objects  as  individual.  .  .  . 
The  child  has  not  formed  to  itself  a  refined  idea  of  moral 
good,  but  contemplating  a  given  action  it  proclaims  it  to  be 
good  or  bad."  Again,  "  the  Conscience  is  of  the  nature  of  a 
cognitive  power.  It  is  analogous  ...  to  ...  sense.  .  .  . 
It  reveals  to  us  certain  quaUties  of  objects  ...  it  lets  us 
know  of  certain  voluntary  states  of  ourselves  or  others  that 
they  are  good  or  evil  "  (page  286). 

And  Mansell  writes  :  "  That  this  particular  act  of  my  own 
at  the  moment  of  being  committed  is  wrong  is  a  fact  pre- 
sented immediately  by  the  judgment  of  Conscience.    That 


ON  INTUITiONISM  5i7 

all  acts  of  the  same  kind,  whensoever  or  by  whomsoever 
committed,  are  necessarily  wrong  is  a  judgment  formed  by 
the  Reason.  .  .  .  The  former  as  the  presentative  condition 
of  moral  thought  must  be  allowed  to  possess  that  chrono- 
logical priority  which  in  other  cases  is  admitted  to  exist  in 
individual  facts  "  ("  Metaphysics,"  page  164).  Mansell  also 
claims  that  the  immediate  intuition  of  moral  quality  is  con- 
fined to  our  own  acts,  that  it  does  not  extend  to  the  acts  of 
others.  "  The  intuitive  perception  of  moral  qualities  cannot 
extend  beyond  our  own  actions,  in  which  alone  we  are 
directly  conscious  of  the  law  of  obligation,  and  of  a  voluntary 
obedience  or  disobedience  to  it  "  (page  168). 

Amongst  the  doubtful  upholders  of  this  theory  are  Martin- 
eau  and  Hutcheson.  Martineau  seems  to  maintain  it  in 
many  passages  of  his  "  Types  of  Ethical  Theory  " — for 
instance,  where  he  writes  (page  456)  :  "  Here  "  (that  is  in 
the  Moral  Sphere)  "  the  development  of  our  knowledge  is 
hot  downwards  from  the  ideal  essences  to  the  individuals 
taken  one  by  one,  but  upwards  from  simple  cases  of  alterna- 
tive to  the  full  content  of  Right,  inverting  Cudworth's  rule — 
that  knowledge  doth  not  begin  in  individuals  but  ends  in 
them."  x\nd  Martineau  himself  seems  to  class  Hutcheson 
with  the  Perceptional  Intuitionists  when  he  describes 
Hutcheson's  idea  of  goodness  as  a  "  perceptible  quality 
read  off  at  sight  in  the  conduct  of  others  "  ("  Types,"  II,,  54). 

Of  German  writers  the  most  pronounced  upholder  of  Per- 
ceptional Intuitionism  is  Herbart.  See  Jodl,  "  Geschichte 
dor  Ethik,"  II.,  205. 

Most  intuitionists,  however,  are  to  be  classed  as  Common 
Sense  Intuitionists.  They  maintain  that  we  know  immedi- 
ately not  the  morality  of  the  particular  act,  as,  for  instance, 
that  this  murder  in  these  particular  circumstances  is  bad, 
but  that  murder  in  general  is  bad.  Even  the  upholders  of 
the  Moral  Sense  theory  whom  we  should  naturally  expect 
to  uphold  Perceptional  Intuitionism  are,  perhaps  with  the 
doubtful  exception  of  Hutcheson  and  very  few  others,  all 
Common  Sense  Intuitionists.  Thus,  Reid  expressly  declares 
that  we  have  an  intuitive  knowledge  of  the  general  principles, 
and  that  our  knowledge  of  the  morality  of  individual  acts  is 
X  result  of  reasoning.  Locke  seems  also  to  hold  the  theory 
of  Common  Sense  Intuitionism  as  far  as  Morality  depends  on 
Divine  law.  There  are,  he  tells  us,  three  kinds  of  moral 
laws,  viz.,  civil  law.  Divine,  and  the  law  of  fashion  or  reputa- 
tion ;  but  the  Divine  law  is  "  the  only  true  touchstone  of 
moral  rectitude."  The  Divine  law  is  known  either  by  revela- 
tion or  the  light  of  nature,  and  this  latter  expression  we 


5i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

regard  as  meaning  "  by  intuition."  In  Locke's  theory, 
however,  there  are  two  manifest  inconsistencies.  One  is 
that  though  he  acknowledges  Divine  laws  of  morality,  he 
5'et  regards  good  and  evil  as  consisting  wholly  in  the  pleasure 
and  pain  that  follow  on  action.  The  other  is  that  whilst, 
as  we  have  said,  he  regards  good  and  evil  as  consisting  in 
consequences  he  yet  speaks  of  morality  as  being  known  by 
intuition.  Plainly  the  computation  of  consequences  is  the 
work -of  the  reasoning  faculty  and  not  of  intuition. 


(6)  Perceptional  Intuitionism — Criticism 

(i)  In  some  of  our  individual  acts  there  are  many 
moral  circumstances,  and  each  of  these  circumstances 
considered  morally  bears  a  special  relation  to  the 
ultimate  end,  and  these  relations  need  to  be  compared 
and  examined  before  we  can  know  the  true  morality  of 
the  individual  act.  This  comparison  and  examination 
requires  reasoning,  and  hence  the  morality  of  all  par- 
ticular actions  cannot  be  known  immediately  and 
intuitively.  ^ 

(2)  Our  knowledge  of  the  morality  of  all  particular 
acts  cannot  be  intuitive  because  we  know  from  experience 
that  in  determining  the  morality  of  many  of  our  acts 
we  must  use  our  Reason.  In  doubt  or  ignorance  men 
look  to  others  for  instruction,  and  ask  for  reasons  as  a 
necessary  means  to  making  up  their  minds  as  to  their 
duty  in  a  particular  case.  Indeed,  in  most  of  our 
actions  it  would  seem  that  some  reasoning  is  necessary, 
and  hence  we  conclude  that  normally  our  knowledge  of 
morality  is  due  not  to  intuition  but  to  inference. 

(3)  Things  known  by  intuition  are  easily  knowable. 
The  axioms  of  Euclid  are  known  without  difficulty. 
Colour  is  also  easily  knowable.  There  is  no  axiom  that 
cannot  be  seen  to  be  true  if  it  is  properly  stated,  and  no 
colour  that  cannot  be  perceived  if  the  conditions  arc 
suitable.  So,  also,  if  the  morality  of  all  particular  acts 
be  known  by  intuition,  the  morals  of  all  acts  must,  if 
the  circumstances  of  the  act  arc  fully  stated,  be  easily 


ON  INTUITIONISM  519 

accessible  to  knowledge.  But  that  this  is  not  the  case 
will  readily  be  conceded.  There  are  acts  of  which,  how- 
ever closely  they  be  examined,  we  are  incapable  of 
deciding  the  moral  quality  ;  and  our  inability  to  deter- 
mine the  moral  quality  of  these  acts  remains  even  though 
every  part  and  circumstance  of  the  act  is  known  to  us, 
and  even  though  the  conditions  of  observation  are  per- 
fect. Let  a  colour  be  suitably  observed  and  we  must 
discover  its  quality.  But  there  are  moral  cases  which 
still  remain  unsolved  although  there  is  no  difficulty  in 
observing  the  individual  facts  of  the  case. 

Hence,  the  morality  of  particular  acts  is  not  easily 
knowable,  and,  therefore,  we  conclude  that  our  know- 
ledge of  their  morality  is  not  intuitive. 

(4)  Where  intuitions  depend  on  cognitive  faculties,  like 
sense  or  intellect,  there  can  be  no  difference  of  opinion 
concerning  these  intuitions*  The  evident  truth  of  this 
statement  will  appear  from  examples.  To  take  the 
instances  of  colour  and  the  axioms  of  Euclid  (our  know- 
ledge of  both  of  which  is  admittedly  intuitive),  all  men 
under  suitable  conditions  and  with  normal  faculties  of 
sense  (in  the  case  of  colour)  and  intellect  (in  the  case 
of  Euclid)  will  be  in  agreement  about  a  colour  or  an 
axiom  which  is  presented  to  them.  The  same  should 
hold  for  the  morality  of  all  particular  acts  if  their 
morality  be  always  known  by  intuition.  Now,  it  is 
obvious  that  men  are  not  in  agreement  about  all  moral 
questions.  Men  hold  the  most  widely  divergent  views 
on  the  morality  of  certain  acts  even  though  they  under- 
stand the  full  circumstances  of  these  acts.  Hence,  we 
conclude  again,  the  morality  of  all  particular  acts  is 
not  known  by  intuition. 

To  this  last  argument  of  ours  Intuitionists  may  offer 
two  replies,  neither  of  which  we  can  regard  as  satis- 
factory.! 

•  We  suppose  a  case  in  which  the  object  is  presented  in  equal 
clearness  and  detail  to  all  men. 

f  Marti  neau's  reply  to  this  difficulty  we  hold  over  to  the  last 
section  of  this  chapter. 


520  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(l.)  The  first  reply  is  that  differences  of  opinion  on 
moral  matters  may  be  due  to  a  certain  moral  colour- 
blindness analogous  to  that  which  occurs  in  the  sphere 
of  vision  ;  for  we  know  that  there  is  such  a  thing  as 
colour-blindness,  that  what  one  man  sees  green  another 
man  sees  red,  and  nevertheless  vision  is  intuitive  ;  and 
if  vision  is  intuitive  in  spite  of  differences  of  opinion 
about  certain  colours,  moral  judgments  may  also  be 
intuitive  in  spite  of  differences  of  opinion. 

Of  this  reply  our  criticism  is  as  follows  :  If  a  man  is 
colour-blind,  say,  to  red,  he  can  never  see  red  in  any- 
thing. If  he  sees  it  in  even  one  object  he  cannot  be 
colour-blind  to  that  colour.  But  there  is  no  man  blind 
to  good  and  evil  in  such  a  way  as  never  to  perceive 
them — ^he  will  surely  see  the  good  and  evil  of  some 
acts.  Therefore,  no  man  is  colour-blind  to  good  and 
evil.*  If,  therefore,  there  are  moral  cases  on  which 
ethicians  hold  different  opinions  this  cannot  be  due 
to  anything  analogous  to  colour-blindness  f  in  the 
world  of  vision.  Our  argument,  therefore,  still  holds 
good — the  morality  of  all  particular  acts  cannot  be 
known  by  intuition  since  men  differ  in  their  judgments 
about  certain  moral  cases. 

(ii.)  The  second  reply  of  the  Intuitionists  to  our 
argument  regarding  differences  of  opinion  on  moral 
questions  is  that  the  perception  of  beauty  is  intuitive, 
and  yet  men  differ  in  their  opinions  about  beauty. 

Our  reply  is  that,  however  intuitive  the  perception  of 
beauty  may  be,  the  differences  of  men's  views  regarding 
beauty  are  not  analogous  to  differences  on  moral 
questions. 

For  the  differences  regarding  beauty  are  due  either 
to— 

(a)  Temperament,  on  which  aesthetic  pleasure  largely 
depends   (this  aesthetic  pleasure  being  the  criterion  of 

•  Goodness  and  badness  being  the  only  two  "  colours  "  (the  reader 
will  understand  the  analogy)  in  the  world  of  morality. 

t  We  admit,  however,  that  concerning  the  remote  conclusions,  sin 
may  induce  an  incapacity  for  seeing  morality. 


ON  INTUITIONISM  521 

beauty),  and  not  to  a  purely  cognitive  apt  like  that    of 
sense  or  intellect  ;    or 

{(i)  To  the  varying  degree  in  which  a  beautiful  object 
is  understood  by  the  beholder.*  A  fine  picture  may 
contain  many  things  discernible  only  to  the  skilful 
judge.  But  our  claim  is  that  where  an  object  is  pre- 
sented in  equal  clearness  and  detail  to  all,  intuitions 
must  be  all  in  agreement  concerning  that  object. 

Variation  of  opinion  regarding  beauty  is,  therefore, 
consistent  with  Intuition. 

But  the  perception  of  morality  is  (a)  not  due  to 
temperament  but  to  a  cognitive  f  faculty.  The  morality 
of  an  act  is  its  relation  to  the  final  end,  and  this  relation 
is  understood  by  the  cognitive  faculty  of  intellect  only. 
Again,  {li)  differences  regarding  the  morality  of  indi- 
vidual acts  remain  in  some  cases  even  amongst  those 
persons  before  whom  the  facts  of  the  case  have  been 
laid  in  the  fullest  manner  and  who  understand  these 
facts  completely. 

Differences  of  view,  therefore,  in  the  case  of  intuitive 
perception  of  beauty  are  not  parallel  with  those  about 
morality,  and  afford  no  argument  to  prove  that  the 
perception  of  morality  is  self-evident  or  intuitive. 

But  we  make  a  false  assumption  if  we  suppose,  as 
some  Intuitionists  do,  that  aesthetic  perception  is  always 
a  question  of  Intuition  merely.  For  the  perception  of 
beauty  sometimes  follows  as  a  result  of  reasoning  J 
from  premisses,  and  in  holding  these  premisses  there 
may  be  considerable  latitude  for  differences  of  opinion. 
In  every  art  there  are  different  aesthetic  schools  with 
different  principles,  and  even  the  premisses  from  which 

*  Perhaps,  also,  to  the  want  of  a  definition  of  what  beauty  is  in 
itself.  We  can  only  define  beauty  in  its  effect,  quod  visum  placet.  The 
good,  on  the  other  hand,  can  be  defined  exactly  in  itself. 

f  And  our  thesis  is  that  "  where  intuition  depends  on  cognitive 
faculties,"  etc. 

X  We  say  here  "  follows  as  a  result  of  reasoning."  We  do  not  say 
that  the  perception  of  beauty  is  itself  an  act  of  reasoning.  The  per- 
ception of  beauty  always  takes  place  in  the  act  of  beholding  the  object 
— that  is,  in  the  "  contemplation  "  of  it — but  it  may  follow  in  that 
act  as  a  result  of  previous  reasoning. 


522  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

these  schools  argue  may  not  be  themselves  intuitions, 
but  may  be  the  conchisions  drawn  from  previous  reason- 
ing. The  views  of  a  cultured  man  on  aesthetics  are 
generally  the  product  of  much  thought  and  study  and 
reasoning — things  w^hich  strongly  influence  both  tem- 
perament and  knowledge,  and  are,  therefore,  the  cause 
of  many  of  the  differences  which  exist  among  persons 
W'ho  perceive  beauty.  Differences,  then,  in  our  aesthetic 
perceptions  and  in  the  feelings  of  pleasure  with  which 
we  contemplate  objects  of  art  may  be  due  to  reasoning, 
and  so  far  they  rather  strengthen  than  weaken  our 
argument  that,  where  there  are  differences  of  view, 
these  views  must  be  the  result  of  reasoning  and  not 
of  intuition. 

These  four  arguments  contain  the  substance  of  pur 
case  against  Perceptional  Intuitionism. 

(c)  Common  Sense  Intuitionism 

A  more  widely  accepted  doctrine  than  that  of  Per- 
ceptional Intuitionism  is  the  system  of  Common  Sense 
Intuitionism  which  we  have  defined  as  the  theory  that 
at  least  the  broad  general  principles  of  morals  (for 
instance,  such  principles  as  that  "  taking  other  people's 
property,"  homicide,  and  lying  are  bad,  and  their 
opposites  good)  are  known  to  us  immediately  without 
the  necessity  of  reasoning. 

Now,  we  have  already  shown  that  certain  principles 
known  as  primary  principles  are  self-evident  or  intui- 
tively known  ;  and  hence  it  would  seem  at  first  sight 
as  if  there  could  be  no  essential  difference  between  our 
theory  and  that  which  we  are  now  about  to  criticise 
under  the  name  of  Common  Sense  Intuitionism.  But 
there  is  this  difference  between  the  Common  Sense 
Intuitionists'  theory  and  ours,  that  whereas,  according 
to  the  Common  Sense  Intuitionists,  all  general  moral 
principles  are  self-evident,  we  maintain,  on  the  other 
hand,  that  some  general  moral  principles  arc  not  self- 


ON  INTUITIONISM  523 

evident,  but  are  obtained  through  reasoning,  and  that 
even  of  those  principles  which  are  necessarily  known 
to  all  some  are  not  intuitions  in  the  strict  sense  of  the 
word — that  is,  they  are  not  technically  self-evident 
since  they  require  some  reasoning. 

The  school  of  Common  Sense  Intuitionists,  we  say, 
holds  that  all  general  moral  principles  are  self-evident. 
But  we  must  admit  that  in  the  writings  of  this  school 
the  expression  "  general  moral  principle  "  is  ill-defined. 
In  a  certain  sense  any  moral  proposition  may  be 
regarded  as  a  general  principle — for  instance,  the  pro- 
position that  "it  is  unlawful  for  any  man  to  give  his 
money  to  the  poor  when  his  own  children  require  it  " 
is  a  general  proposition  ;  yet  it  is  very  special  and 
limited  in  its  application,  and  we  do  not  find  Intui- 
tionists claiming  that  such  concrete  propositions  as 
these  are  intuitive.  By  general  propositions,  therefore, 
they  seem  rather  to  mean  very  general  propositions, 
principles  of  very  broad  application  and  simple  in  their 
character  and  in  the  meaning  of  their  terms. 

But,  then,  what  are  these  very  general  principles  ? 
Here,  again,  the  Common  Sense  Intuitionists  fail  us.* 
They  do  not  tell  us  what  those  principles  are,  nor  do 
they  give  us  any  principle  by  which  to  determine  them 
for  ourselves. 

The  least,  however,  that  we  think  could  be  claimed 
in  any  theory  of  pure  and  unmodified  Common  Sense 
Intuitionism  is  that  all  those  very  general  moral  prin- 
ciples are  self-evident  which  are  known  to  the  ordinary 

*  We  find  very  great  difficulty  in  deciding  whether  Sidgwick  and 
Prof.  Rashdall  should  be  counted  amongst  Common  Sense  Intuitionists. 
Sidgwick  and  Prof.  Rashdall  seem  to  accept  only  three  axioms  as 
intuitive — namely,  those  of  Prudence  (I  ought  to  promote  my  good  on 
the  whole)  ;  of  Benevolence  (I  ought  to  regard  the  good  of  society  as 
of  more  value  than  that  of  the  individual,  or,  as  Sidgwick  puts  it,  I 
ought  to  aim  at  good  generally,  and  not  at  any  particular  part  of  it)  ; 
of  Equity  (one  man's  good  is,  other  things  being  equal,  as  good  as 
another  man's).  If  this  system  is  one  of  Common  Sense  Intuitionism 
it  is  a  very  modified  form  of  that  theory,  and  we  do  not  think  that  a 
minute  examination  of  its  merits  is  necessary  after  the  criticisms  we 
have  given  of  other  forms  of  Intuitionism. 


524  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

man  and  are  accepted  by  him  as  manifestly  true — for 
instance,  that  lying,  stealing,  homicide,  immorality, 
want  of  benevolence  are  bad  and  to  be  avoided — and 
it  is  in  this  sense  that  we  propose  to  criticise  the  theory 
of  Common  Sense  Intuitionism. 

Of  this  theory  our  criticism  is  : — 

(i)  A  principle  may  be  general  and  known  to  all  and 
yet  not  be  self-evident  in  the  strict  sense.  Intuitionists 
should  at  least  make  the  distinction  which  we 
have  made  between  truths  that  are  strictly  self- 
evident  and  those  that  are  self-evident  in  a  loose  sense 
only. 

(2)  Some  of  those  principles  which  are  ordinarily 
accepted  by  men  are  not  only  not  self-evident  in  the 
strict  sense  of  the  term,  as  we  have  already  pointed 
out,  but  are  not  to  be  regarded  as  self-evident  in  any 
sense  since  they  were  quite  unknown  to  certain  degraded 
races,  and  consequently  they  must  require  reasoning  for 
their  perception.  Thus,  Aquinas  testifies  that  "  some 
peoples  did  not  know  it  was  wrong  to  steal  and  even  to 
commit  (certain)  unnatural  crimes,"  *  a  state  of  things 
which  he  regards  as  due  to  the  corrupt  lives  of  these 
people.  Yet  Common  Sense  Intuitionists  will  generally 
be  found  to  regard  the  wrongfulness  of  stealing  as  self- 
evident. 

(3)  Many  of  these  ordinarily  accepted  principles  admit 
of  proof,  as  the  Ethician  knows,  and,  therefore,  the  pre- 
sumption is  that  though  at  present  they  are  apparently 
accepted  without  proof,  they  were  originally  made 
known  through  reasoning,  without  which  it  is  possible 
that  they  would  never  have  come  into  human  con- 
sciousness. 

For  these  reasons  we  claim  that  whilst  some  of  the 
ordinarily  accepted  moral  principles  are  intuitive  others 
arc  not,  but  are  the  result  of  reasoning,  and  conse- 
quently the  theory  of  pure  Common  Sense  Intuitionism, 
of  which  the  least  claim  must  consistently  be  that  the 

•  "  S.  Thcol.,"  I.,  II.,  Q.  XCIV.,  Art.  6 


ON  INTUITIONISM  525 

ordinarily  accepted  moral  beliefs  are  intuitive,  is  false 
and  unfounded. 

Further  examination  of  this  theory  is  unnecessary. 
As  we  said,  there  are  some  principles  which  must  be 
regarded  as  self-evident,  and  hence  the  fundamental 
defect  of  Common  Sense  Intuitionism  is  that  it  has  not 
determined  the  principles  that  are  to  be  regarded  as 
self-evident  in  a  scientific  manner,  for  it  simply  regards 
as  self-evident  any  principles  which  it  sees  to  be  ad- 
mitted by  the  ordinary  man,  and  hence  it  has  erred  in 
its  enumeration  of  these  principles. 

We  now  proceed  to  discuss  some  special  forms  of 
Intuitionism — namely,  the  theories  of  "  ^Esthetic 
Morals  "  and  of  "  the  Moral  Impulses." 

(d)  Some  Special  Theories 

On  Esthetic  Morals. 

The  name  "  ^Esthetic  Morals  "  has  been  given  to  many 
and  widely  different  theories.  The  simple  definition  given 
below  from  ourselves — viz.,  the  theory  which  identifies 
beauty  with  goodness — represents  the  only  form  of  the 
theory  that  interests  us  here. 

Martineau  defines  ^Esthetic  Ethics  as  the  theory  which 
blends  in  thought  two  separate  aspects  of  the  good,  "  one 
identifying  right  with  benevolent  affection,  the  other  with 
'  Charien  '  and  '  Kalon  '  with  what  is  charming  and  lovely  in 
temper  and  affection."  This  definition  will  be  noticed  by  us 
only  in  so  far  as  it  coincides  with  our  own  definition. 

Amongst  German  aesthetic  theories  of  Morals  the  most 
prominent  are  those  of  Schiller  and  Herbart. 

Schiller's  ethical  views  are  the  direct  opposite  of  those  of 
Kant.  According  to  Kant,  that  act  alone  is  morally  good 
which  is  prompted  by  Reason  exclusively — which  excludes 
sense-motivation.  Schiller's  view  of  moral  goodness,  instead 
of  excluding  "  sense  "  and  "  nature,"  rather  emphasises  their 
importance.  The  moral  good  consists,  according  to  Schiller, 
rather  in  the  reconciliation  of  Reason  with  sense  than  in  the 
suppression  of  sense.  Now,  sense  and  Reason  stand  very  far 
apart,  and  would,  according  to  Schiller,  be  incapable  of  re- 
conciliation unless  through  some  mediating  condition  of  soul 
which  is  at  once  a  sensuous  and  a  rational  condition,  which 


526  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

perceives  its  object  immediately,  which  allows  to  the  senses 
a  real  but  yet  a  temperate  influence  in  human  action,  and 
this  condition  of  soul  is  given  in  aesthetic  feeling.  This  con- 
dition of  "the  beautiful  soul "  {die  schone  Seele)  is  also  the 
condition  of  moral  excellence  since  in  it  are  harmonised  the 
claims  of  sense  and  Reason. 

Herbart's  theory  is  known  as  ^Esthetic  Formalism,  and  is 
as  foUows  :  The  judgment  of  moral  approbation  and  blame, 
which  some  acts  excite,  is  an  intuitive  judgment.  The 
existence  of  such  judgments  is  a  matter  of  fact  and  of 
experience  which  there  is  no  denying,  and  on  this  fact  is 
built  our  whole  moral  existence.  These  judgments  are  all 
judgments  of  taste,  analogous  to  the  judgments  of  taste 
which  we  pass  on  music.  They  concern  certain  will-relations, 
which,  in  consequence  of  the  taste-judgments  which  these 
relations  excite,  we  call  "  morally  good  and  evil."  Taste  is 
an  irreducible  fact  of  our  psychical  constitution.  "  Taste 
in  Herbart's  sense,"  writes  Jodl  ("  Geschichte  der  Ethik," 
II.,  203),  "  is  an  important  original  fact  of  our  soul-life ; 
the  psychical  mechanism  requires  that  wherever  there  is  a 
complete  apprehension  of  relations  containing  a  number  of 
homogeneous  elements  mutually  modifying  and  interfusing 
with  one  another  (a  judgment  of)  praise  or  blame  necessarily 
arises  in  the  apprehending  subject."  Such  judgments  are, 
as  we  have  said,  excited  in  the  case  of  certain  will-relations, 
and  it  is  the  purpose  of  Ethics  to  discover  the  particular  will- 
relations  which  give  us  aesthetic  satisfaction  and  those  that 
excite  the  opposite.  But  since  the  sensibility  of  our  aesthetic 
nature  is  a  subjective  matter  and  not  objective,  it  follows 
that  Ethics  deals  not  with  objects  but  with  subjective  value- 
judgments,  and  consequently  that  Ethics  is  not  a  branch  of 
Metaphysics.  Hence  the  '  good  '  is  not  a  positive  reality.  It 
is  a  property  of  our  aesthetic  appreciation  {Werthschdizting). 
It  is  also  quite  distinct  from  pleasure  as  moral  evil  is  from 
pain. 

The  simple  relations  which  excite  in  us  aesthetic  pleasures 
Herbart  calls  "  ideas."    These  we  need  not  enumerate  here. 

Now,  these  sesthetic  theories  of  Schiller  and  Herbart 
lie  for  the  most  part  outside  the  discussion  which  we 
are  about  to  raise,  and  we  mention  them  here  simply 
because  they  represent  forms  of  Intuitive  Morals.  The 
particular  theory  which  we  are  about  to  examine  is 
rather  that  which  is  to  be  found  in  the  writings  of 
British  Moralists,  particularly  Shaftesbury  and  Hutche- 


ON  INTUITIONISM  527 

son — ^the  theory,  namely,  that  moral  good  is  a  par- 
ticular species  of  beauty  and  moral  evil  a  particular 
form  of  ugliness,  and  that  as  beauty  and  ugliness  are 
perceived  intuitively  so  also  Morals  are  perceived  in- 
tuitively— that  is,  without  reasoning. 

Whether  this  theory  is  consistently  adhered  to  in  the 
writings  of  Shaftesbury  and  Hutcheson  is  a  debated 
question  with  commentators.  We  believe,  however, 
that  their  works  supply  us  with  sufficient  ground  for 
classifying  them  as  ^Esthetic  Moralists. 

"  There  is  no  real  good,"  writes  Shaftesbury,*  "  besides 
the  enjoyment  of  beauty."  And  again — "  What  is  beautiful 
is  harmonious  and  proportionable,  what  is  harmonious  and 
proportionable  is  true,  and  what  is  at  once  beautiful  and 
true  is  of  consequence  agreeable  and  good."  | 

Hutcheson,  also,  is  usually  regarded  J  as  belonging  to 
this  school,  since  he  speaks  indifferently  of  beauty  and 
goodness — that  is,  uses  them  as  interchangeable  terms. 

"  But,"  he  writes,  "  to  regulate  the  highest  powers  of  our 
nature — our  affections  and  deliberate  designs  of  action  in 
important  affairs  there  is  implanted  in  us  by  nature  the 


*  "  Moralists,"  II.,  page  422. 

t  "  Miscellaneous  Reflections,"  III.,  page  183.  Martineau  con- 
siders that  though  there  are  sentences  in  Shaftesbury  that  are  open  to 
the  construction  of  Moral  ^Estheticism,  the  more  exact  statements  of 
his  doctrine  do  not  admit  of  this  construction.  He  even  says  that, 
"  taking  the  writings  of  our  Author  as  a  whole  we  cannot  justly  affirm 
that  he  merges  the  agathon  in  the  kalon,  but  the  increasing  tendency 
n  his  later  essays  to  accentuate  the  esthetic  aspect  of  morals  is  very 
observable."  The  presence  of  those  contradictory  statements  to  which 
Martineau  calls  attention,  and  which  seem  to  be  characteristic  of  all 
Intuitionist  writings,  is  sufficient  reason  for  warning  the  reader  that  in 
criticising  the  Intuitionist  theories  we  criticise  types  of  Intuitionism 
rather  than  forms  actually  and  persistently  maintained  by  Intuitionist 
writers. 

J  For  instance,  by  Martineau,  who  says  ("  Types  of  Ethical 
Theory,"  II.,  543) — "  I  am  afraid  that,  in  spite  of  some  contrary 
appearances,  we  must  treat  Hutcheson 's  doctrine  on  this  side  as  one 
of  moral  aesthetics  only,  which  essentially  reduces  perfect  character 
simply  to  a  work  of  high  art."  And  again,  in  assigning  reasons  for 
counting  Hutcheson's  theory  one  of  Moral  iEsthetics — "  He  (Hutcheson) 
speaks  of  the  moral  beauty  or  deformity  of  actions  as  synonymous 
with  their  rightness  or  wrongness  as  in  the  propositions — '  we  have 
a  sense  of  goodness  and  moral  beauty  in  actions  distinct  from  ad- 


528  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

noblest  and  most  divine  of  all  senses — that  conscience  by 
which  we  discern  what  is  graceful,  becoming,  beautiful  and 
honourable,  in  the  affections  of  the  soul,  in  our  conduct  of 
life,  our  words,  our  actions.  .  .  .  What  is  approved  by  this 
sense  we  count  right  and  beautiful,  and  call  it  virtue  ;  what 
is  condemned  we  call  base  and  deformed  and  vicious  "  ("On 
Human  Nature,"  I.,  i8). 

Now,  this  theory  that  goodness  is  only  a  species  of 
beauty  is  evidently  a  theory  of  Intuitionism.  For 
beauty,  as  we  shall  show  presently,  is  perceived  not 
by  reasoning,  but  immediately  and  directly  by  intuition, 
and  hence  it  will  be  necessary  to  show  that  beauty  is 
not  identical  with  goodness. 

Criticism — In  a  certain  sense  the  moral  good  is  always 
beautiful,  and  we  often  speak  of  the  moral  good  and 
the  beautiful  as  if  they  were  the  same  thing.  Thus, 
we  speak  of  a  man's  action  as  abominable  or  horrible 
when  we  mean  that  it  is  bad,  and  of  a  life  as  beautiful 
when  we  mean  that  it  is  good.  How  far  these  things 
may  be  said  with  truth  we  shall  see  presently  when 
we  have  compared  the  two  conceptions — beauty  and 
moral  goodness. 

But  now,  however  close  may  be  the  connection  be- 
tween these  two  conceptions — beauty  and  goodness — 
they  are  not  the  same.     For — 

(i)  In  the  first  place,  they  appertain  to  wholly  dis- 
tinct faculties  in  man.  Beauty,  as  Aquinas  points  out, 
appertains  to  the  knowing  faculty   {vis  cognoscitiva)  * 

vantage'  "  He  quotes  other  passages  in  which  Hutcheson  seems  to 
distinguish  the  Moral  Sense  and  the  Sense  of  Beauty,  but  it  is  Mar- 
tincau's  view  that  the  differences  drawn  by  Hutcheson  here  are  not 
so  much  differences  in  the  faculties  themselves  as  in  the  pleasures 
attached  to  them. 

It  should  be  noticed,  however,  that  British  aesthetic  moralists, 
besides  identifying  beauty  with  goodness,  also  give  to  their  theory  a 
Utilitarian  colour,  inasmuch  as  they  also  identify  what  is  beautiful 
and  good  with  benevolent  action.  In  Hutchcson's  writings,  indeed, 
this  second  element  is  the  more  prominent  and  the  principal  element, 
litnevolence  is,  according  to  Hutcheson,  the  object  of  the  Moral  Sense, 
the  only  thing  appreciated  by  tlie  Moral  Sense. 

•  "  S.  Thcol."  I.,  Q.  v.,  Art.  4,  ad  primain.  Aquinas'  theory  nctds 
to  be  explained  and  supplemented.  By  vis  cognoscitiva  he  docs  not 
mean  the  intellectual  faculty  merely.     The  perception  of  beauty  is 


ON  INTUITIONISM  529 

goodness  to  the  appetitive  faculty.  A  thing  is  called 
beautiful  because  the  contemplation  *  of  it  pleases  us 
{quae  visa  placent) — a  thing  is  called  good  because  it 
is  an  end  the  attainment  or  possession  of  which  pleases 
and  satisfies  an  appetite  [quae  appetitum  quietant)  ;  and 
it  is  morally  good  when  it  leads  to  the  satisfaction  of 
our  appetite  for  our  last  end.  Hence,  beauty  and 
moral  goodness,  since  they  appertain  to  different 
faculties,  are  not  the  same. 

(2)  Beauty  and  moral  goodness  both  depend  on,  and 
are  founded  on,  something  within  the  object,  but 
whereas  beauty  is  a  quality  of  the  object  regarded  in 
itself,  moral  goodness  is  a  relation  to  a  certain  extrinsic 
end — the  ultimiis  finis.  In  the  words  of  Aquinas — 
"  Pulchrum  et  bonum  in  subjecto  sunt  idem  quia  supra 
eandem  rem  fundantur,  scil,  supra  formam  {i.e.,  natu- 
ram).  .  .  .  Sed  .  .  .  dum  bonum  habet  rationem  finis, 
pulchrum  pertinet  ad  rationem  causae  formalis  "  ("  S. 
Theol."  I.,  Q.  v.,  Art.  4,  ad  pHmam). 

Therefore,  we  repeat  here  what  we  have  already  said 
when  discussing  the  general  theories  of  Perceptional  and 
Common  Sense  Intuitionism — we  cannot  know  that  an 
act  is  morally  good  by  merely  considering  the  act  in 
itself  without  relation  to  anything  else.  We  must 
determine  the  moral  goodness  of  an  act  by  considering 

indeed  possible  to  intellectual  beings  only,  but,  granted  the  presence 
of  intellect,  then  sense  and  imagination  can  share  in  that  perception, 
and  share  also  in  the  ajsthetic  pleasure.  A  truly  beautiful  object 
must  please  every  faculty  engaged  in  the  contemplation  of  it.  Thus 
in  the  case  of  music  the  tone  must  satisfy  the  ear,  whilst  the  melody 
must  satisfy  ear,  imagination,  and  intellect.  In  a  picture  the  colour- 
ing must  please  the  eye,  the  imagination  must  be  satisfied  with  the 
form  or  outline  of  figures,  and  the  intellect  with  the  unity  of  the  whole 
presentation.  In  so  far  as  any  one  of  these  faculties  is  offended,  the 
object  loses  in  beauty.  As  perceivable  both  by  sense  and  by  intellect, 
beauty  thus  appeals  to  our  whole  cognitive  nature.  Any  theory  that 
would  confine  the  knowledge  of  beauty  to  sense  on  the  one  hand  or  to 
intellect  on  the  other  is  one-sided  and  erroneous. 

*  With  this  doctrine  stated  in  our  text  it  may  be  interesting  to 
compare  Kant's  definition  of  beauty,  which,  with  some  qualifications 
is  the  same  as  that  of  Aquinas — beauty  is  the  object  of  a  satisfaction 
that  is  wholly  disinterested.  A  disinterested  satisfaction  is  the  same 
thing  as  the  satisfaction  of  contemplation,  as  opposed  to  that  oi 
attainment. 

Vol.  1—34 


530  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

its  relation  to  the  ultimate  end  [Summum  Bonmn).  On 
the  contrary,  we  perceive  the  beauty  of  an  object  by 
considering  the  object  in  itself,  in  its  form,  and  without 
relation  to  anything  else.  And  for  this  reason  it  is 
possible  to  perceive  the  moral  goodness  of  an  act  in 
reasoning,  whereas  the  perception  of  beauty  is,  as  we 
know  also  from  experience,  an  act  not  of  reasoning  but 
of  contemplation,  although  it  may  sometimes  require 
reasoning  as  a  necessary  antecedent.  Hence,  also,  it 
is  possible  to  prove  that  a  certain  action  is  good  or  evil 
to  one  who  does  not  already  know  its  moral  character. 
But  we  could  not  prove  that  any  object  is  beautiful, 
any  more  than  we  could  prove  that  a  thing  is  red  or 
sweet.  This,  also,  is  evident  to  each  man  from  ex- 
perience. 

Beauty  and  goodness  are,  therefore,  not  the  same. 
But,  as  we  said  in  the  beginning  of  this  section,  there  is 
a  sense  in  which  the  morally  good  is  always  beautiful — 
namely,  that  all  harmony  is  beautiful ;  and  a  good  act 
harmonises,  first,  with  the  nature  of  the  agent,  and, 
secondly,  with  the  scheme  of  the  universe,  since  all 
things  are  meant  to  tend  to  the  ultimate  end,  whereas 
a  bad  act  at  once  violates  the  nature  of  the  agent,  and 
contradicts  the  plan  of  the  Universe  in  not  tending  to 
the  ultimate  end.* 

Moral  Impulse  Theory. 

Martineau's  theory  of  Moral  Impulses  is  to  bo  reckoned 
among  the  most  prominent  of  recent   Intuitionist  Ethical 

*  In  discussing  the  theory  of  ^Esthetic  Morals  we  have  avoided 
all  reference  to  certain  highly  metaphysical  theories  of  modern  writers 
on  the  relation  of  the  "  good  "  to  the  "  beautiful  "  :  for  instance,  the 
theory  developed  by  some  modern  disciples  of  Schelling  that  the 
"  beautiful  "  and  the  "  good  "  are  identified  in  the  conception  of  the 
"  absolute,"  which,  according  to  these  writers,  is  not  only  an  object 
of  intellect,  but  is  also  known  to  us  by  imaginative  and  sensuous 
apprehension.  We  do  not  think  that  the  discussion  of  such  theories 
is  calculated  to  throw  much  light  on  the  problem  of  tiie  relation  of 
the  "  good  "  to  the  "  beautiful."  An  excellent  account  of  these 
theories  can  be  found  in  M.  Fouill6c's  "  Critique  des  Systtmes  de 
Morale  Contcraporains." 


ON  INTUITIONISM  531 

theories.  It  is  the  theory  that  in  man  there  is  a  scale  of 
inner  principles,  or  springs,  or  impulses  towards  certain  forms 
of  activity  ;  that  these  impulses  can  be  arranged  into  a  scale 
of  morally  higher  and  lower,  and  that  according  to  its  place 
in  this  scale  each  impulse  possesses  a  "  moral  worth  "  not  in 
itself,  but  in  its  relation  to  other  impulses  above  or  below  it ; 
that  the  moral  judgment  pronounces  exclusively  on  the  moral 
gradations  of  this  scale  ("  our  moral  judgments  are  all  pre- 
ferential "),  the  rule  of  morals  being  that  "  every  action  is 
right  which  in  the  presence  of  a  lower  principle  follows  a 
higher,  and  every  action  is  wrong  which  in  the  presence  of 
a  higher  principle  follows  a  lower,"  that  these  differences 
of  higher  and  lower  are  made  known  to  us  intuitively  by 
Conscience,  which  is  defined  "  the  sensibility  of  our  mind  to 
the  gradations  of  the  scale  "  or  the  "  critical  perception  we 
have  of  the  relative  authority  of  our  several  principles  of 
action."  This  power  of  Conscience  is,  according  to  Martineau, 
not  developed  to  the  same  extent  in  all  men,  for  the  "  extend- 
ing range  of  intuitive  perception  of  relative  worth  "  is  not 
the  same  in  all.  One  man  is  alive  to  only  a  certain  portion 
of  the  scale  of  impulses,  another  to  a  more  extended  portion, 
a  fact  which,  according  to  Martineau,  fully  explains  the 
apparent  differences  in  men's  moral  judgments.  For  the 
moral  judgments  of  different  men  are  never  really  opposed 
to  one  another,  since  when  one  man  says  that  a  particular 
act  is  right  and  another  that  it  is  wrong,  they  are  speaking 
of  very  different  things — that  is,  they  are  estimating  the  value 
of  a  certain  spring  of  action  relatively  to  different  portions 
of  the  moral  scale.  If  goodness  consists  in  choosing  the 
higher  in  preference  to  the  lower,  and  badness  in  the  opposite 
course,  then  the  following  of  a  particular  impulse  may  be 
good  if  our  comparison  of  that  impulse  be  with  others  lower 
still,  bad  if  our  comparison  be  with  higher  impulses.  Hence 
the  apparent  differences  of  judgments.  Our  moral  judgments, 
according  to  Martineau,  never  really  contradict  one  another, 
"  However  limited  the  range  of  our  moral  consciousness  it 
would  lead  us  all  to  the  same  verdicts,  had  we  all  the  same 
segment  of  the  series  under  our  cognisance."  Only  he  who 
is  alive  to  all  the  impulses  is  capable  of  a  perfect  moral  judg- 
ment. "  The  whole  scale  of  inner  impulses  is  open  to  survey 
only  to  the  ripest  mind,  and  to  be  perfect  in  its  appreciation 
is  to  have  exhausted  the  permutations  of  human  experience." 

This  rough  sketch  of  Martineau's  theory  may,  for  our 
present  purposes,  be  reduced  to  the  single  proposition 
that  the  relative  moral  value  of  the  inner  impulses,  the 


532  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

gradation  of  which  constitutes  the  subject-matter  of  all 
moral  Judgments,  is  known  intuitively  by  our  con- 
sciences.* 

Criticism — (i)  The  first  point  of  our  criticism  is  that 
this  theory  is  open  to  all  the  objections  we  have  brought 
against  the  extreme  forms  of  Intuition.  Thus,  if  all 
moral  judgment  is  an  estimate  of  the  relative  value  of 
our  inner  impulses,  and  if  this  relative  value  is  known 
to  us  intuitively,  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  we  could  ever 
be  under  the  necessity  (a  necessity  which  we  know 
from  experience  that  we  often  are  under)  of  reasoning 
and  argument  in  coming  to  our  moral  decisions,  or 
why  we  should  sometimes  fail  to  come  to  any  decision 
in  regard  to  certain  particular  moral  questions.  Again, 
if  our  moral  judgments  concerning  the  springs  of  action 
are  intuitive,  why  should  men's  judgments  differ  ? 
Martineau's  reply — that  our  judgments  never  really 
differ — is,  to  our  mind,  sheer  nonsense.  Take  the  case 
of  the  judgments  of  two  men — one  that  it  is  lawful  to 
tell  a  lie  to  save  one's  own  life,  the  other  that  it  is  not 
lawful  to  tell  a  lie  even  to  save  one's  own  life.  Between 
these  judgments  there  is  a  genuine  difference  of  view, 
and  they  really  contradict  each  other.  Yet,  may  not 
that  difference  of  view  remain  even  though  the  two  men 
be  conscious  of  equal  portions  of  or  even  of  the  whole 
of  the  scale  of  impulses  ?  Or  may  not  two  men,  each 
of  whom  has  a  perfect  idea  of  the  relative  value  of 
selfishness  and  benevolence  and  the  other  impulses,  still 
differ  in  their  views  as  to  whether  a  person  is  bound 

*  According  to  Martineau,  although  Conscience  judges  only  of  the 
moral  value  of  the  springs  of  action  without  reference  to  the  conse- 
quences of  action,  still  there  is  room  for  the  computation  of  pleasures 
and  pains  in  two  ways.  "  First,  the  computation  is  already  more  or 
less  involved  in  the  preference  of  this  or  that  spring  of  action,  for  in 
proportion  as  the  springs  of  action  are  self-conscious  they  conltinplate 
their  own  eilects,  and  judgment  upon  them  is  included  in  our  judgment 
of  the  disposition.  Secondly,  when  the  principle  of  action  has  been 
selected  to  the  exclusion  of  all  competitors  ;  because,  under  the  given 
external  conditions  the  very  same  principle  may  express  and  satisfy 
itself  in  various  methods.  .  .  .  The  choice  of  means  by  whicli  to 
carry  out  the  workings  of  a  spring  of  conduct  can  be  mauc  only  by 
cun.sideration  of  consequences." 


ON  INTUITIONISM  533 

to  restitution  for  the  burning  of  one  man's  house  by 
mistake  when  the  burning  of  another  man's  house  was 
actually  intended — a  question  which  is  actually  debated 
amongst  moralists  and  on  which  opinions  are  divided. 
We  think  that  Martineau  has  no  ground  for  his  view — a 
view  which  he  states,  but  does  not  attempt  to  prove, 
that  if  all  men  took  cognisance  of  the  same  portion 
of  the  scale  of  impulses  there  would  be  no  room  for 
differences  in  our  moral  opinions. 

(2)  This  theory  of  Moral  Impulses  does  not  explain 
the  moral  character  of  all  our  acts,  for,  according  to  this 
theory,  badness  and  goodness  could  not  attach  to  the 
exercise  of  a  single  impulse  without  reference  to  others, 
but  arise  only  when  one  impulse  is  preferred  to  another 
which  lies  higher  or  lower  in  the  scale  than  itself.  Now, 
we  maintain  that,  whether  the  impulse  involved  in  the 
speaking  of  the  truth  * — to  take  this  single  example — be 
higher  or  lower  than  other  impulses,  the  telling  of  a  lie 
is  a  bad  act,  and  its  badness  is  not  constituted  by  any 
relation  to  other  impulses,  it  is  bad  because  a  lie  vio- 
lates the  natural  end  of  the  faculty  of  speech.  Many 
other  unnatural  crimes  consist,  as  we  saw  in  our  chapter 
on  the  Moral  Criterion,  like  lying,  in  the  use  of  a  single 
faculty  or  impulse  in  such  a  way  as  to  avoid  the  realisa- 
tion of  its  natural  end.  These  cases  are  not  covered  by 
the  theory  that  badness  and  goodness  depend  upon  an 
order  of  impulses. 

(3)  Again,  the  difficulty  might  be  raised  how  the 
theor}^  of  Impulses  is  to  decide  where,  in  the  scale  of 
impulses,  any  particular  impulse  stands  ;  where,  for 
instance,  the  impulses  of  justice  and  benevolence  stand 
in  relation  to  one  another ;  whether  benevolence  is 
higher,  and  whether,  as  a  consequence,  it  is  lawful  to 
steal  from  a  rich  man  in  order  to  help  the  poor — the 
motive  in  the  case  being  that  of  benevolence  and  the 

*  Of  the  impulses  concerned  with  Veracity,  Martineau  speaks  very 
hesitatingly.  He  does  not  seem  to  contemplate  an  impulse  to  veracity 
itself. 


534  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

comparison  being  one  of  benevolence  and  justice.  We 
submit  that  no  rule  of  preference  between  these  im- 
pulses could  be  given  on  Martineau's  theory  ;  *  and 
even  if  it  could  be  given  the  question  of  the  prefer- 
ability  of  certain  impulses  to  certain  others  could  not 
enter  into  our  decision.  For  injustice  is  bad  whether 
it  be  done  from  a  motive  of  benevolence  or  not,  or 
whether  the  impulse  of  justice  stands  lower  or  higher 
in  the  scale  than  that  of  benevolence.  This  theory, 
therefore,  cannot  account  for  the  morality  of  all  our 
acts.  And  hence  it  is  not  the  ultimate  account  of  moral 
good  and  evil. 

(4)  We  submit  that  this  theory  makes  unreasonable 
demands  on  human  nature  in  expecting  every  man 
always  to  choose  a  higher  impulse  in  presence  of  a 
lower.  If  it  is  wrong  to  follow  a  lower  impulse  in 
presence  of  a  higher,  we  do  not  know  on  what  principle 
a  man  could  lawfully  smoke  cigars  and  drink  brandy 
after  dinner  when  by  refraining  from  these  things  he 
could  afford  to  give  more  money  to  the  poor.  Yet  we 
believe  that  Common  Sense  and  Reason  would  recognise 
no  obligation,  generally  speaking,  to  give  up  these 
luxuries. 

(5)  Finally,  there  is  the  dilhculty  of  discerning  not, 
as  in  a  former  difficulty,  the  order  of  the  impulses,  but 
what  are  the  impulses  concerned  in  any  particular  act, 
and  of  deducing  from  these  the  moral  value  of  conduct. 
This  difficulty  Martineau  makes  light  of,  saying  that 
though  it  will  be  fatal  to  his  doctrine  if  the  difficulty 
cannot  be  answered,  yet  it  really  can  be  answered,  or 
rather  the  difficulty  does  not  really  exist  for  the  Ethician. 
The  main  point  of  the  difficulty,  according  to  Martineau, 
is  that,  in  some  cases,  the  impulse  to  action  is  complex — 

•  In  our  own  theory  of  the  good,  as  the  reader  will  remember,  we 
make  comparison  of  some  faculties  reckoning  one  higher  than  another. 
Intel Icct,  lor  instance,  we  regard  as  higher  than  sense.  Tliis  qurslion 
of  the  relative  onler  of  the  faculties  is  necessary  in  our  system  for  the 
solution  of  a  few  questions  only,  like  that  of  the  immorality  of  drunken- 
ness. In  Martineau's  system  the  order  of  the  impulses  is  made  the 
universal  test.    As  such  it  fails. 


ON  INTUITIONISM  535 

and  it  is  difficult  to  analyse  the  complex  motive  into 
its  several  components.  But,  then,  according  to  Mar- 
tineau,  it  is  not  necessary  to  analyse  the  complex 
motive  into  its  components,  for  we  can  know  the  value 
of  a  complex  impulse  relatively  to  other  impulses  with- 
out analysing  it  into  its  components.  Hence,  the  diffi- 
culty of  analysing  the  components  does  not  exist  foi 
the  Ethician.  All  the  difficulties  charged  upon  the 
composition  of  motives  appear  to  him  (Martineau)  as 
a  mere  "  nightmare  of  unreal  psychology." 

Now,  we  do  not  agree  with  Martineau  that  this  diffi- 
culty is  fanciful  and  unreal,  or  that  it  all  turns  on  the 
question  whether  it  is  necessary  to  analyse  our  com- 
plex motives  in  forming  a  moral  judgment.  We  believe 
that  even  the  trained  psychologist  and,  a  fortiori,  the 
ordinary  man  would  find  it  exceedingly  difficult  to 
know  what  impulse,  complex  or  simple,  urges  him  to 
the  doing  of  any  particular  act.  A  man  can  easily 
know  the  end  *  that  he  wishes  to  gain  in  any  act,  and 
consequently,  if  he  knows  that  all  his  ends  are  good, 
he  knows  also  that  his  act  is  good.  But  the  inner 
impulses  that  urge  us  to  a  particular  end  are  generally 
unknown  to  us,  and  for  the  most  part  they  do  not  enter 
into  our  consciousness  in  any  way.  Consequently,  if 
the  morality  of  the  end  sought  or  of  the  act  of  seeking 
those  ends  is  to  be  determined  by  our  judgment  as  to 
the  relative  value  of  inner  impulses,  the  moral  judgment 
would  be  for  the  most  part  impossible. 

But  it  may  be  said  that  it  is  not  necessary  for  us  to 
bring  these  impulses  directly  into  consciousness,  that 
we  can  judge  of  the  value  of  the  impulses  prompting 
us  to  an  act  from  the  value  of  the  acts  which  these 
impulses  give  rise  to.  But  such  an  admission  would 
in\olve  the  rejection  of  the  Moral  Impulse  theory  (which 

*  We  speak  here  as  if  our  impulses  were  different  from  our  mere 
natural  desires  for  certain  ends.  If  in  Martineau's  theory  these  two 
are  the  same,  then  there  is  nothing  distinctive  about  his  theory.  It  is 
pure  Anstotelianism,  which  makes  all  morality  depend  on  "  ends." 
It  the  two  are  distinct,  the  above  criticism  holds. 


536  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

supposes  that  our  preferential  judgment  of  the  value  of 
the  impulses  is  first,  and  that  this  judgment  is  the 
criterion  whereby  we  value  acts),  and  it  would  mean 
substituting  for  the  Moral  Impulse  theory  the  crudest 
of  all  Intuitionist  systems — namely,  the  theory  of  Per- 
ceptional Intuitionism — that  the  human  mind  reads  off 
the  moral  goodness  of  each  particular  act  as  it  comes 
before  us,  and  from  that  determines  the  value  of  the 
impulses  involved  in  the  act. 

For  these  reasons  we  reject  the  Intuitive  theory  of 
the  Moral  Impulses. 


> 


CHAPTER  XVI 

ON  SYNDERESIS 

Synderesis  is  the  name  given  to  the  group  of  primaryj 
moral  principles  which  belong  naturally  to  the  human 
mind.     The   Scholastics   define   it    "  habitus   primorum 
principiorum. "     St.  John  Damascene  calls  it  a  "  naturale 
judicatorium." 

Now,  when  we  say  that  certain  principles  are  natural 
we  do  not  mean  that  they  are  innate,  but  only  that 
without  reasoning  the  mind  comes  quickly  and  easily 
to  acquire  them,  and  cannot  help  doing  so.  What 
these  principles  are  we  have  already  seen  in  our  chapter 
on  Intuitionism.  Of  these  principles  some,  we  saw,  are 
intuitions  in  the  strict  sense — that  is,  the  mind  assents 
to  them  at  once  without  reasoning.  Certain  other 
principles  are,  practically  speaking,  intuitions.  For, 
though  technically  they  are  inferences  and  not  intui- 
tions, still  so  easily  are  they  acquired  and  so  neces- 
sarily, that  they  may  be,  and  are  generally  regarded  as, 
self-evident  truths.  The  number  of  these  primary  self- 
evident  principles  it  would  be  difficult  to  state,  and  the 
exact  formula  of  each  it  would  not  be  easy  to  determine. 
But  we  can  say  with  certainty  that  all  grown  people 
who  are  capable  of  thinking  at  all  believe  in  the  good- 
ness of  honesty,  bravery,  kindness,  filial  pity,  the  care 
for  offspring,  marriage,  and  in  the  evil  of  indiscriminate 
murder,  etc.  It  is  true,  indeed,  that  many  peoples  did 
not  regard  virtues  like  honesty  and  piety  as  so  strictly 
binding  that  they  could  not  be  set  aside  under  certain 
exceptional  circumstances.  But  Reason  must  recognise 
the  general  necessity  of  cultivating  these  virtues,^  and 
it  is  for  moralists  and  those  who  are  capable  of  judging 
of  such  things  to  say  whether  to  any  particular  law  there 

537 


538  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

may  in  reality  be  an  exception.  In  other  words,  it  is 
for  the  moralist  to  determine  scientifically  the  formula 
that  will  express,  the  law  truly  and  exactly.  These 
self-evident  moral  principles  constitute  what  moralists 
speak  of  as  Synderesis,*.  about  which  many  interesting 
questions  arise,  some  of  which  will  be  considered  in  the 
present  chapter. 

From  the  self-evident  principles,  taken  in  their 
strictest  sense,  it  is  possible,  as  we  said,  to  derive 
certain   proximate    simple    conclusions   which    all    men 

*  Various  attempts  have  been  made  by  modem  ethicians  to  reduce 
all  moral  principles  to  a  single  principle  inclusive  of  all  the  others.  The 
more  important  amongst  these  principles  may  be  divided  into  the 
following  six  classes,  according  as  they  are  founded  :  (i)  On  the  con- 
ception of  individual  pleasure  ;  (2)  on  the  idea  of  individual  liberty  ; 
(3)  on  the  relation  of  the  inner  impulses  to  man  ;  (4)  on  the  idea  of 
life  ;  (5)  on  the  idea  of  the  common  good  ;  (6)  on  the  idea  of  personality, 
whether  individual  or  general. 

(i)  Under  the  first  we  have  the  principle  of  Hobbes — that  the 
"  good  "  is  that  which  each  man  desires.  This  principle  we  have 
criticised  in  our  chapter  on  The  Good.  (2)  Under  the  second  we  have 
Fichte's  principle,  "  Be  free,"  Cousin's  "  Ens  liberum  maneat 
liberum,"  and  similar  principles  of  the  Transcendental  School,  an 
examination  of  which  will  be  found  in  the  latter  part  of  our  chapter 
on  Liberty,  where  it  is  shown  that  Liberty  is  not  morality  but  only 
its  pre-condition.  (3)  Under  the  third  we  have  the  principle  "  Never 
to  choose  a  lower  in  the  presence  of  a  higher  pleasure."  This  principle 
is  examined  in  our  chapter  on  Intuitionism.  (4)  Under  the  fourth  we 
have  the  innumerable  principles  of  Biological  Ethics — e.g.,  Thomasius' 
principle,  "  Do  that  which  will  make  life  long  and  happy  "  ;  Leslie 
Stephen's  two  principles,  "  Be  prudent  "  and  "  Be  virtuous,"  both 
ultimately  grounded  on  the  idea  of  life  ;  also  Spencer's,  "  Seek  the 
maximum  of  life,"  for  which  see  chapter  on  Biological  Evolution. 
(5)  Under  the  fifth  we  have  the  several  principles  of  Sociology — v.g., 
"  Seek  the  greatest  good  of  society  "  (Mill),  or  "  Homini  quantum  in 
ipso  est  colendam  ct  scrvandam  esse  societatem  "  (Grotius  and  Puffen- 
dorf),  or  "  Neminen  laede — suum  cuique  "  (Leibnitz).  All  that  we 
have  said  in  the  chapter  on  Utilitarianism  applies  here.  (6)  Under 
the  heading  of  personality  we  have  the  three  principles — (a)  of  indi- 
vidual personality  (Kant),  "  Treat  every  man  as  person  ;  (b)  of  micro- 
cosmic  personality  (Dr.  Lipps),  "  Realise  the  whole  world  in  yourself  "  ; 
(c)  of  universal  personality  (Hegel),  "  Reali.sc  the  personality  of 
Society."  These  principles  are  examined  in  our  chapters  on  Univer.sal- 
ism  and  on  Rights. 

The  reader  will  have  no  difficulty  in  recognising  from  what  has  been 
said  in  the  foregoing  chapters  that  many  of  these  principles  are  false, 
whilst  others  fail  to  include  the  whole  moral  law  (and  therefore  are  not 
to  be  regarded  as  primary  principles  in  the  sense  intended  by  the 
ethicians  here  mentioned)  being  principles  only  of  certain  departments 
of  morals.  Further  criticism  of  these  so-called  primary  principles,  we 
think,  will  not  be  necessary  at  this  point, 


ON  SYNDERESIS  539 

must  know.  Other  conclusions  are  not  so  evident, 
and  to  bring  home  their  truth  with  unmistakable  clear- 
ness to  the  ordinary  mind  we  have  to  reason  them  out 
step  after  step,  as  we  would  a  difficult  proposition  in 
geometry.  These  propositions  are  called  remote  con- 
clusions. Though  they  are  quite  as  true  as  the  proxi- 
mate, they  are  not,  as  we  said,  so  evident,  and  conse- 
quently it  is  possible  for  the  human  mind  to  lose  the 
consciousness  of  them  or  even  never  to  come  to  a  know- 
ledge of  them.  But  neither  the  first  principles  them- 
selves nor  the  proximate  and  immediate  conclusions 
from  them  can  ever  be  lost  to  consciousness. 

We  now  proceed  to  discuss  two  important  questions 
on  the  primary  moral  principles.  The  first — What  is 
the  origin  of  our  general  moral  beliefs  ?  or — How  do 
we  come  as  children  to  the  understanding  of  general 
moral  principles  ?  The  second  is — Can  belief  in  the 
moral  principles  decay,  or,  as  it  is  usually  put,  can 
Conscience  develop  and  decay  ? 

(a)  On  the  origin  of  a  child's  moral  beliefs. 

The  expression  "  origin  of  our  moral  beliefs  "  may 
mean  either  the  logical  grounds  on  which  educated  men 
maintain  their  beliefs  ;  or  the  original  sources  whence  in 
past  ages  men  received  their  moral  ideas  ;  or,  finally,  it 
may  mean  the  actual  beginnings  of  these  beliefs  in  the 
child's  mind  to-day.  It  is  this  last  question  that  we  are 
now  to  occupy  ourselves  with.  What,  we  ask,  is  the 
source  of  a  child's  moral  ideas  ?  Do  they  come  through 
the  exercise  of  his  own  Reason  without  help  from  out- 
side ?  Or  are  they  gained  by  a  process  of  reasoning 
helped  on  by  instruction  ?  Or  are  they  wholly  from 
tradition  ?  * 

At  the  outset  we  wish  the  reader  to  understand  that 
this  is  mainly  an  historical  question.     We  have  nothing 

*  The  question  of  the  possibility  of  inheriting  these  beliefs  and  of 
their  origin  in  past  ages  has  already  been  fully  treated  in  our  chapter 
on  Evolutionist  Ethics. 


540  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

at  present  to  do  with  the  philosophy  of  duty  or  of  the 
good — i.e.,  with  the  question  of  the  objective  founda- 
tion of  moral  truths,  or  the  reason  why  we  ought  to 
accept  them.  This  we  have  fully  explained  in  an  earlier 
chapter.  The  question  how  a  child  comes  in  the  first 
instance  to  believe  that  two  sides  of  a  triangle  are 
greater  than  a  third  (we  take  it  for  granted  that  such  a 
proposition  has  only  to  be  put  before  the  thinking 
child  in  order  to  command  instantaneous  acceptance) 
has  nothing  to  do  with  the  question — Why  do  you,  a 
mathematician,  accept  it,  or  why  ought  you  to  do  so  ? 
So  our  present  question  is,  not  what  is  the  right  ground 
of  our  moral  beliefs,  but  how  do  children  generally 
come  by  their  moral  beliefs  ?  Now,  a  child  may  accept 
mathematical  truths  on  the  word  of  his  master  ;  yet 
no  one  would,  on  that  account,  say  that  the  proper 
ground  of  Mathematics  is  tradition.  Why  ?  Because 
mathematical  propositions  can  be  proved  on  mathe- 
matical grounds.  So  also  with  Morals.  Once  we  have 
proved  the  realit}'  of  moral  distinctions  we  have  im- 
plicitly shown  that  the  ground  of  our  moral  beliefs  is 
not  mere  tradition,  that  Ethics  is  based  upon  ethical 
grounds,  as  Mathematics  is  upon  mathematical  grounds. 
But  our  present  enquiry  has  nothing  to  do  with  the 
question  of  the  ultimate  grounds  of  moral  belief.  It 
is  a  question  of  history  only,  but  it  is  of  great  interest 
to  the  ethician. 

At  first  sight  it  would  seem  that  the  beliefs  of  children 
depend  wholly  on  traditions — that  is,  on  the  teaching 
of  parents  and  master.  Children  in  civilised  countries, 
long  before  they  are  able  to  reason  or  to  express  their 
thoughts  with  an}'  clearness,  have  already  been  in- 
structed in  moral  truths — that  is,  they  have  in  the  lirst 
instance  accepted  these  truths  on  the  ground  of  tradi- 
tion only.  Even  savage  children,  from  their  very 
earliest  years,  are  made  familiar  with  the  particular 
religious  and  moral  persuasions  of  their  tribe,  so  that 
from  the  beginning  their  moral  beliefs  are  developed 


ON  SYNDERESIS  541 

under  pressure,   if   we  might   say   so,   of  religious  and 
political  training. 

Still,  in  spite  of  this  fact,  we  maintain  that  the  beliefs 
of  children  do  not  depend  wholly  on  tradition.  We 
claim  that  though  a  child  begins  with  tradition,  yet  at 
the  age  of  ten  or  twelve  he  has  already  come  into  posses- 
sion of  certain  moral  beliefs  which  he  holds  with  a  strong 
intellectual  conviction,  not  on  the  strength  of  mere 
human  testimony,  but  on  account  of  their  own  intrinsic 
evidence.  In  other  words,  we  take  it  for  granted  that 
at  ten  or  twelve  children  no  longer  require  the  authority 
of  their  parents  in  the  case  of  some  moral  principles, 
and  that  they  adhere  to  these  principles  or  propositions 
on  account  of  the  insight  they  now  possess  into  the 
intrinsic  truth  of  these  propositions.  These  propositions 
may  not  be  very  many.  But  a  boy  of  twelve  (we. say 
"  twelve,"  though  we  believe  that  the  transition  from 
tradition  to  belief  on  intrinsic  grounds  occurs  at  a  much 
earlier  period)  believes  on  intrinsic  evidence  such  truths 
as  that  he  ought  to  honour  his  parents,  that  they  should 
care  for  him,  that  he  has  rights  against  other  men. 
Some  beliefs  he  still  holds  on  the  ground  of  authority 
alone.  If  asked  why  he  believes  that  America  exists 
or  that  planets  move,  or  that  absolute  monarchy  is  not 
good,  he  will  answer  "  because  so  he  has  been  told." 
But  if  asked  why  he  believes  that  murder  is  bad,  or, 
better  still,  if  an  argument  is  put  forward  in  his  presence 
to  show  that  murder  is  good,  it  will  be  found  that  in 
answering  he  does  not  appeal  to  any  authority  for  his 
belief,  but  will  refer  to  some  objective  ground  and  argue 
the  case  out  on  its  merits,  thereby  showing  that  he  is 
conscious  of  the  intrinsic  unreasonableness  of  murder, 
and  that  he  no  longer  beheves  on  faith  alone.  The 
ground  which  he  assigns  may  be  far  from  satisfactory, 
but  it  is  evident  from  his  attitude  that  now  he  is  be- 
lieving on  grounds  intrinsic  to  the  truth  itself,  although 
as  yet  he  may  not  be  able  to  express  these  grounds 
coherently.     Thus,    between   his   moral   belief   and    his 


542  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

belief  in  facts  into  which  he  has  as  yet  no  personal 
insight,  there  is  the  very  marked  distinction  that  the 
one  class  of  truth  appeals  to  his  own  inner  convictions 
from  their  inner  evidence,  the  other  only  on  the  ground 
of  an  extraneous  authority.  The  moral  world,  there- 
fore, has  begun  to  appeal  to  such  a  child  for  its  own 
sake,  and  he  will  judge  of  it  from  what  he  feels  and 
perceives,  and  will  talk  of  it  as  a  thing  that  he  is  familiar 
with,  and  will  think  for  himself  concerning  the  reason- 
ableness of  the  moral  laws,  and  will  even  question  the 
judgment  of  other  people  about  them,  which  shows  that 
some  at  least  of  his  judgments  on  moral  matters  are 
now  received  at  first  hand,  and  not  on  mere  authority. 

A  child's  judgments  about  remote  conclusions  may, 
many  of  them,  be  wrong.  It  would  be  strange  if  some 
were  not.  If  a  boy  can  form  a  wrong  judgment  about 
many  simple  truths  of  Physics  it  is  impossible  that  he 
should  not  sometimes  go  wrong  in  Morals.  But  in 
general,  on  the  broad  moral  principles,  his  judgment  is 
perfectly  trustworthy.  No  boy,  for  instance,  could 
think  that  murder,  lying,  cruelty,  and  robbery  are  the 
right  things,  and  ought  to  be  done.  Such  a  proposition 
he  could  not  entertain  for  a  moment,  even  if  he  tried. 
But  his  whole  soul  goes  out  to  the  thought  of  the  good- 
ness of  truth,  of  respect  for  parents,  of  benevolence, 
and  of  honour.  It  goes  out  just  as  easily  and  as 
naturally  as  the  flower  opens  up  to  the  sunlight,  from 
which  fact  we  draw  the  conclusion  that  morality  appeals 
to  him  to  a  large  extent  on  the  ground  of  its  own  ob- 
jective evidence,  and  that,  therefore,  his  assent  to 
morals  is  not  based  on  tradition  alone. 

We  are  led  also  to  another  conclusion — namely,  that, 
since  in  the  sphere  of  morals  authority  ceases  at  an 
early  age  to  be  necessary  to  a  child's  belief,  and  since 
the  first  principles  of  the  moral  law  come  quickly  to 
be  believed  on  the  ground  of  their  own  inner  credibility, 
it  seems  evident  that,  even  were  no  instruction  given, 
the  unaided  Reason  must  succeed  in  time  in  construct- 


ON  SYNDERESIS  543 

ing  for  itself  a  good  deal  of  the  moral  law,  although  in 
an  unsatisfactory  way  and  in  the  rough,  and  at  a  com- 
paratively late  period  in  a  man's  career.  To  construct 
the  natural  moral  law  with  any  perfection  needs  ex- 
perience and  a  ripened  Reason.  But  granted  a  mind 
that  can  normally  think,  and  granted  that  it  has  some 
experience,  there  is  no  doubt  that  even  without  instruc- 
tion it  must  arrive  at  length  at  some  rough  idea  of  the 
moral  system.  What,  therefore,  is  the  effect  of  instruc- 
tion on  the  young  mind  in  the  department  of  morals  ? 
Just  this — aided  by  instruction  the  moral  ideas  come 
to  it  all  the  sooner,  and  aided  by  instruction  they  are 
necessarily  cleaner  cut  and  truer.  Instruction  in 
morality  is  like  the  plan  of  a  city,  which  puts  before 
us  boldly  and  definitely  at  one  glance  the  lie  of  every 
part,  and  its  relation  to  the  whole.  In  that  one  view 
we  see  the  city  as  a  whole,  and  also  the  direction  of 
every  passage  and  turn.  Without  such  a  plan  we  might, 
indeed,  come  some  day  to  know  the  city,  but  only  after 
much  trying  research  and  many  failures.  It  is  so  with 
morals — with  this  addendum,  that  in  morals  the  failures 
of  research-time  mean  disaster  to  the  individual.  In- 
struction, therefore,  is  necessary  for  the  welfare  of  the 
child.  But,  if  it  is  necessary  for  the  child,  much  more 
is  it  necessary  for  the  progress  of  the  world  at  large. 
For,  though  it  is  true  that  unaided  Reason  will  arrive 
after  much  thinking  at  some  fair  idea  of  the  truths  of 
Ethics,  yet  it  is  also  true  that  our  moral  system  could 
not  develop,  that  the  fabric  of  morals  could  not  grow, 
did  not  each  age  hand  down  the  results  of  its  reasoning 
and  its  experience  to  the  age  that  immediately  succeeds 
it.  Moral  science  is  not  more  easily  constructed  than 
many  branches  of  Physics,  and  if  in  the  sphere  of  Physics 
each  age  did  not  build  upon  that  which  preceded  it,  the 
edifice  of  science  could  not  be  reared.  In  the  same  way 
instruction  and  tradition  are  necessary  to  moral  science. 
Having  seen,  now,  that  the  moral  beliefs  of  children 
are  not  dependent  wholly  upon  tradition,  it  will  be  in- 


544  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

teresting  to  enquire,  from  what  we  know  of  the  child 
mind,  what  would  be  the  meaning  of  the  conceptions 
"  good  "  and  "  duty  "  if,  these  ideas  being  once  sup- 
plied to  the  child,  they  were  allowed  to  develop  in  his 
mind  without  further  instruction.  What,  for  instance, 
would  a  child  understand  by  "  good  "  and  "  duty " 
who  was  told  that  it  was  a  good  thing  and  a  duty  to 
be  honourable  and  kind  ?  That  most  children  from 
the  very  beginning  regard  evil  as  directly  and  im- 
mediately an  offence  against  God,  and  the  moral  law 
as  His  command,  is  only  natural,  since  that  is  how  they 
have  been  trained  to  think.  That  training  is,  we  main- 
tain, justifiable  both  on  logical  and  on  moral  grounds. 
It  is  justifiable  on  logical  grounds  because,  as  we  showed 
in  the  earlier  chapters  of  this  work,  goodness  and  dut}?^ 
are  in  their  last  analysis  founded  upon  God  as  supreme 
cause  and  ruler,  and,  therefore,  evil  is  trul}^  a  violation 
of  God's  will.  Secondly,  this  religious  interpretation  of 
morality  is  morally  necessary,  because  it  is  the  con- 
ception of  a  personal  relation  obtaining  between  child 
and  Supreme  Being  that  appeals  more  than  anything 
else  to  his  mind  and  heart,  and  fires  him  with  a  love  of 
the  "  good."  But  what  now  of  the  untrained  child,  or 
the  child  who  has  merely  received  the  suggestion  that 
certain  acts  are  bad  and  others  good  ?  What  in  his 
mind  will  be  the  meaning  of  the  two  ideas  "  good  " 
and  "  duty "  ?  Naturally  much  will  depend  on  the 
child  himself.  Some  children  never  think.  But  some 
do  think,  and,  granted  that  the  child  has  come  into  the 
possession  of  a  language — in  other  words,  that  he  is 
normal  and  possesses  the  means  of  thinking — we  main- 
tain that  his  mind  will,  if  allowed  to  develop,  follow  a 
very  definite  course.  It  will  be  found  to  pass  through 
two  distinct  stages — (i)  The  stage  at  which  evil  is 
regarded   as   a   violation   of   the  law  of  nature.*   and 

•  A  child  will  not  formally  think  of  such  a  thing  as  nature.     But, 

iust  as  a  psychologist  experimenting  upon  the  ordinary  subject  gets 
lim  to  describe  his  experiences,  and  then  makes  use  of  thsee  experiences, 
cataloguing  them  according  to  the  methods  and  terminology  of  his 


ON  SYNDERESIS  545 

(2)  the  stage  at  which  evil  is  regarded  as  breaking  in 
upon  the  plans  of  Him  who  made  nature  what  it  is. 

First — Badness  to  a  child,  who  has  not  yet  been  told 
that  evil  is  an  offence  against  God,  is  simply  this — 
that  an  order  has  been  broken  in  on,  and  disorder  has 
succeeded  in  its  place.  The  child  feels,  when  he  has 
done  certain  acts,  that  there  is  something  wrong  with 
himself — that  he  is  not  what  he  should  be.  He  steals, 
and  he  feels  that  there  is  a  disturbance  of  the  proper 
and  natural  distribution  of  things  around  him,  A 
drunken  man  is  to  him  a  monster — something  that 
falls  short  of  the  standard  of  nature.  Disarrangement, 
deformity,  disorder,  have  in  these  cases  replaced  ar- 
rangement, harmony,  and  design.  Evil,  therefore,  is 
regarded  as  a  violation  of  nature,  and  by  nature  a 
child  means  the  natural  plan  of  things.  This  is  the 
first  step.  Secondly,  a  child's  mind,  particularly  if  it 
receives  the  least  help  in  its  work,  will  very  easily  travel 
up  to  the  thought  of  One  who  planned  the  world  and 
made  it.  We  say  "  particularly  if,  etc.,"  for  even 
without  help  a  child  must  soon  begin  to  wonder  what 
is  the  cause  of  the  world,  and  even  to  assert  that  it 
must  have  a  cause.  But  if  once  the  idea  of  a  first 
cause  be  suggested  to  him,  the  child's  thought  rises 
immediately^  to  it,  as  to  something  that  satisfies  all  the 
necessities  of  his  mind,  and  when  he  accepts  that  belief 
in  a  First  Cause,  he  accepts  it,  not  indeed  because  it 
has  been  suggested,  but  because  it  is  reasonable,  because 
his  whole  being  goes  out  to  such  a  thought  as  giving 
everything  around  him  meaning  and  completeness  ;  in 
other  words,  the  existence  of  a  First  Being  explains 
everything  that  he  can  think.  We  are  not  now  defend- 
ing the  logic  of  his  thought.  We  maintain,  indeed, 
that   it   is    absolutely   logical.     But    logical    or   not,    a 

science,  so,  though  the  child  will  not  formally  mention  nature,  he  will 
speak  equivalently  of  it,  and  it  will  be  for  the  prudent  investigator 
to  extract  from  these  equivalent  expressions  their  genume  Ethical 
significance.  In  this  sense  we  claim  that  a  child  regards  evil-doing 
as  unnatural. 
Vol.  1—35 


546  THE   SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

child's  mind  travels  up  to  that  thought  of  a  first  cause 
of  the  world  as  easily  as  it  does  to  the  thought  of  the 
maker  of  a  watch  or  of  a  house.  One  of  his  first  ques- 
tions is  how  he  himself  came  to  be,  and  how  his  parents 
came  to  be,  and  how  all  things  came  to  be,  and  at  the 
thought  of  a  "  First  "  who  made  all,  his  mind  is  at  rest. 
And  so  he  easily  gets  to  the  thought  of  sin.  First,  a 
bad  act  is  a  violation  of  nature — that  is,  it  violates  the 
original  plan  of  the  world  ;  secondly,  it  is  a  disarrange- 
ment of  God's  plan,  a  disarrangement  that  displeases 
God,  a  disarrangement  that  can  only  be  set  right  by 
God.  How  far  that  idea  would  carry  a  child  we  do  not 
know.  He  might  even  think  that  to  prevent  a  tree 
from  flowering  or  to  break  down  its  branches  (these 
things  being  in  some  sense  against  nature)  was  sin. 
We  have  no  doubt  that  a  child  would  at  first  get  many 
erroneous  ideas  of  his  duty.  But  still  we  believe  that 
his  ideas  will  run  in  some  direction  such  as  that  which 
we  have  indicated.* 

Thus,  even  in  the  mind  of  the  child,  we  find  in  some 
sense  the  rough  outline  of  the  whole  philosophy  of 
morals.  Evil  is  to  him  a  disarrangement  of  the  original 
plan  of  things  and  a  violation  of  nature,  and  conse- 
quently an  offence  against  God.  And,  as  we  have  seen, 
the  philosophical  account  of  evil  is  no  other  than  this. 
Evil  is  a  violation  of  the  natural  order.  But  it  is  also 
an  offence  against  God,  and  it  is  as  an  offence  against 
God  that  evil  comes  home  to  us  most  intensely,  and  this 
is  the  natural  form  that  the  idea  of  evil  and  of  the 
violation  of  Duty  assumes  in  the  mind  of  a  child. 

With  what  rapidity,  when  once  these  ideas  of  good- 
ness and  duty  are  possessed,  the  proportions  of  the 
moral  fabric  begin  to  form  will  be  readily  understood. 

*  Parents  might  instruct  a  child  to  do  certain  things  because  such 
is  their  wish,  but  unless  there  was  something  in  the  natural  relation  of 
parent  to  child  which  appeals  to  the  child's  mind  it  could  not  know- 
that  it  was  its  duty  to  pay  heed  to  the  word  of  its  parents.  The  mcie 
wish  of  the  parent  could  not  of  itself  generate  a  belief  that  that  wisli 
has  the  force  of  a  law,  and  that  it  ought  to  be  obeyed. 


ON  SYNDERESIS  547 

That  lies  and  murder  and  disrespect  of  parents  are 
unnatural  can  then  be  seen  by  the  youngest  mind. 
Particularly  easy  will  be  the  formation  of  such  judg- 
ments by  those  who  are  not  left  to  their  own  resources, 
who  have  a  few  of  the  moral  truths  put  ready-made 
before  them  for  their  acceptance.  But  when  these 
judgments  have  been  formed  the  child  will  still  require 
the  thought  of  the  higher  sanction  and  the  personal 
love  of  the  first  Creator  if  his  love  of  the  good  is  to  be 
an  actuating  principle  with  him,  and  if  the  fabric  of  his 
moral  beliefs  is  to  have  permanence  and  stability. 

{b)  Can  conscience  develop  and  decay  ? 

"  Can  conscience  develop  ?  "  is  a  question  which  we 
shall  find  no  difficulty  in  answering.  Since  conscience 
is  nothing  more  than  the  practical  Reason  *  it  can  be 
educated  and  developed  in  two  ways — (i)  By  the 
attainment  of  new  truths,  (2)  by  increase  of  power 
— i.e.,  of  energy  and  acuteness — in  the  reasoning  faculty 
itself.  These  things  require  no  elucidation ;  for  the 
moral  faculty  is  exactl}^  on  a  par  with  the  mathematical 
or  the  commercial  Reason,  both  of  which  can  grow  in 
the  two  ways  mentioned — i.e.,  objectively,  by  en- 
larging the  sphere  of  knowledge,  and  subjectively, 
by  developing  one's  inner  power  of  observation  and 
thought. 

But  a  question  of  much  more  practical  importance 
for  ethicians,  and  of  much  greater  difficulty  as  well, 
is  the  reverse  of  that  just  put — namel}',  (i)  Can  Con- 
science decay,  and  if  so  (2)  can  it  be  lost  altogether  ? — 
i.e.,  can  Reason  become  partially  blinded  on  moral 
matters,  and  if  so  can  it  wholly  lose  sight  of  morality  ? 

(i)  We  answer,  first,  that  Conscience  can  decay  in 
two  ways — (a)  By  the  weakening  of  the  general  facultj'- 
of  Reason  itself,  {(i)  by  loss  of  perceptive  power  within 
the  special  sphere  of  morals,     (a)  Of  the  Inst  there  is 

*  JNIore  strictly,  an  act  of  the  practical  Reason, 


548  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

very  little  necessity  to  speak  here.  If  the  general 
faculty  of  Reason  becomes  impaired  our  power  of 
moral  judgment,  like  that  of  the  mathematical  judg- 
ment, must  be  to  some  extent  adversely  affected.  We 
can  no  more  trust  the  judgment  of  a  madman  on  moral 
matters  than  we  can  trust  his  memory  or  his  imagina- 
tion on  the  facts  of  sense.  But  we  must  speak  more 
at  length  of  the  possibility  of  decay  in  Conscience  itself, 
or  of  Reason  within  the  special  department  of  morals. 
(fS)  May  it  happen  that  whilst  in  every  other  depart- 
ment the  Reason  retains  its  strength  and  balance,  yet 
in  the  particular  department  of  morals,  of  moral  good 
and  evil,  the  Reason  may  become  blurred  and  untrust- 
worthy ?  That  Conscience  does  decay  to  some  extent 
is  a  fact  to  which  no  observer  of  men  can  close  his 
eyes.  There  are  men  in  whom  the  moral  faculty  has 
become  so  irresponsive  that  they  fail  to  see  many  truths 
that  once  were  clear  to  their  minds,  and  obvious,  and 
unmistakable.  And  this  has  come  about,  not  because 
of  any  explicit  or  formal  process  of  reasoning  that  they 
have  gone  through,  but  simply  because  Conscience  has 
lost  its  edge,  because  it  has  been  blunted  by  one  or  more 
of  the  thousand  and  one  influences  that  are  wont  to 
affect  the  practical  Reason.  The  first  of  these  influ- 
ences is  the  constant  misuse  of  Conscience  ;  the  second 
is  the  influence  of  desire  upon  thought.  By  the  misuse 
of  Conscience  we  mean  the  use  of  Conscience  against 
one's  better  judgment.  We  rarely  do  evil  without 
excusing  ourselves  in  some  way,  and  making  up  our 
minds  that  what  w^e  do  is  lawful — that  it  is  well  not  to 
be  too  strict — that  to  err  is  human — that  sin  must  be 
condoned,  etc.  All  this  is  against  our  better  judgment. 
The  still  small  voice  warns  us  that  we  are  in  the  wrong. 
But  the  still  small  voice  being  constantly  unheeded 
soon  goes  below  the  threshold  of  our  moral  consciousness, 
und  ceases  to  be  heard.  Then,  secondly,  there  is  the 
general  effect  of  desire  on  Conscience  and  on  the  Reason 
generally.    Prejudice  und  desire  ure  capable  of  warping 


On  synderesis  549 

the  judgment  not  only  in  morals  but  in  every  kind  of 
belief.  Scientists  often  err  unconsciously  in  their  ac- 
count of  the  laws  of  nature,  because  of  some  hobby  or 
fancy  for  which  they  wish  to  find  support  in  the  facts 
of  nature.  In  politics,  too,  our  views  are  influenced 
very  much  by  our  prejudices  arising  out  of  environment, 
or  by  the  prevailing  fashions  of  thought  and  speech. 
And  just  as  our  political  and  scientific  views,  so  also 
our  moral  judgments  are  affected  by  our  own  desires 
or  passions,  and  particularly  by  the  views  of  that  society 
in  which  we  live.  And  we  are  affected  in  varying 
degrees  according  as  our  character  is  weaker  or  stronger, 
compromising  or  independent.  Conscience,  therefore, 
may  decay,  and  even  well-reasoned  judgments  be  re- 
versed through  a  variety  of  causes  of  which  the  cases 
just  given  are  only  a  few  prominent  instances. 

(2)  But  though  Conscience  may  decay  there  is  still  a 
limit  to  the  reversibility  or  variability  of  our  moral 
judgments.  Our  views  on  Political  Philosophy  may 
change,  so  far  as  to  make  us  think  that  that  particular 
system  of  taxation  is  the  better  one  which  suits  our 
own  business  and  requirements.  But  we  cannot  imagine 
a  thinking  man  genuinely  believing  that  there  should  be 
no  such  thing  as  government  or  "  law  and  order  "  at 
all.  So  in  morals,  a  man  could  never  come  to  believe 
that  indiscriminate  murder  and  the  complete  neglect  of 
children  were  lawful,  or  that  the  natural  was  the  thing 
to  be  avoided,  and  the  unnatural  to  be  done.  No,  the 
first  principles  of  Ethics  and  what  has  been  called  their 
proximate  conclusions  can  never  vanish  from  our  minds, 
however  much  an  evil  life  or  prejudice  or  passion  may 
affect  us.  We  can  imagine  a  man  holding  that  in  cer- 
tain very  exaggerated  circumstances  even  murder  would 
be  lawful,  though  to  the  cold,  unprejudiced,  developed 
Reason  it  could  never  seem  so.  But  no  developed  mind 
could  ever  believe  that  wanton  murder  was  the  good 
thing  and  to  be  done,  and  its  opposite  the  bad  thing 
and  to  be  avoided.     Hence,  whilst  the  faculty  of  Con- 


550  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

science  is  quite  capable  of  partial  decadence  it  can  never 
be  wholly  lost.  A  man  can  never  despoil  himself  of  his 
first  principles  or  of  a  knowledge  of  his  main  duties,  and 
as  long  as  these  remain  they  will  not  only  keep  up  a 
claim  on  their  own  account,  but  will  also  act  as  an  in- 
centive in  bringing  back '  to  his  mind  even  those  dis- 
carded truths  which  crime  and  passion  have  obliterated. 


(c)  Un-Ethical  Man 

We  turn  now  from  the  consideration  of  the  question 
of  development  and  decadence  in  the  moral  perceptions 
of  civilised  men  to  the  kindred  question  of  "  Un-Ethical 
man  " — a  field  of  enquiry  which  many  philosophers  have 
used,  notably  M.  Ree  and  M.  Levy-Bruhl — to  show  that 
morals  beliefs  are  not  a  natural  possession,  that  once 
there  was  no  such  thing  as  Conscience  or  a  conscious- 
ness of  moral  distinctions,  that  these  beliefs  are,  there- 
fore, an  artificial  product,  and  as  such  have  no  moral 
binding  power.  If,  as  is  contended,  it  can  be  shown 
that  the  savage  races  evince  in  their  general  mode  of 
conduct  less  and  less  consciousness  of  moral  distinctions 
as  they  go  down  in  the  scale  of  human  beings,  and  if 
those  men  who  have  never  lived  in  society — namely, 
the  solitaries  or  wild  men  of  the  woods,  of  whom  there 
have  been  many — show  no  knowledge  whatever  of 
moral  law,  then  it  would  seem  to  follow  that  the  moral 
laws  are  not  natural — that  they  are  only  a  development 
of  human  custom,   and   a  by-product   of  civilisation.* 

We  shall  therefore  treat : — 

I.  Of  the  moral  beliefs  of  savage  races. 

II.  Of  the  beliefs  of  the  "  homo  sapiens  ferns." 

•  The  reader  will  sec  that  though  of  these  two  hypothetical  pro- 
positions "  if  morals  are  natural  no  race  can  be  completely  ignorant 
of  them,"  and,  "  if  any  races  arc  comjiletely  ignorant  of  the  moral 
law  it  cannot  be  natural  "  the  second  is  deducible  from  the  first, 
still  Ihey  arc  (juitc  distinct  propositions.  It  is  the  second  that  is 
criticised  and  rejected  in  the  text  above. 


ON  SYNDERESIS  551 


I.  Of  the  Moral  Beliefs  of  Savages 

From  Qarwin's  time  anthropologists  have  been  at 
pains  to  show  that  races  exist  which  are  so  far  removed 
from  civilised  men  as  to  exhibit  no  trace  of  morality 
in  act  or  in  belief  beyond  what  is  to  be  found  in  the 
higher  animals.  Lord  Avebiiry  writes  :  "  While  even 
the  lowest  savages  have  many  material  and  intellectual 
attainments  they  are,  it  seems  to  me,  almost  entirely 
wanting  in  moral  feeling."  He  remarks,  however,  that 
"  the  contrary  opinion  has  been  expressed  by  many 
eminent  authorities."  *  Whether,  if  Lord  Avebury's 
account  be  true,  the  Darwinian  theory  on  the  origin  of 
man  must  also  be  true  it  is  not  for  us  to  determine. 
But  it  is  within  our  province  to  determine  whether  if 
Lord  Avebury's  view  be  true — the  view,  namely,  that 
some  men  have  no  moral  beliefs — it  would  follow  that 
the  laws  of  morals  themselves  objectively  taken  cannot 
be  natural,  but  are  simply  the  result  of  custom  or  other 
artificial  and  non-moral  ground.  On  this  point  we 
maintain  the  following  :  That  even  though  all  savage 
races  were  wanting  in  moral  beliefs,  and  had  never 
heard  of  a  difference  between  good  and  evil,  the  Moral 
Laws  themselves  might  still  be  natural.  If  the  validity 
of  Mathematics,  Physics,  and  Psychology  does  not 
depend  on  the  attainments  of  the  savage  in  these 
branches  of  enquiry,  if  the  laws  of  all  three  sciences 
would  remain,  even  though  savages  knew  nothing  about 
numbers  or  the  laws  of  bodies,  or  had  never  performed 
any  act  of  introspection,  and  did  not  know  what  the 
mind  was,  or  what  was  its  structure,  it  is  hard  to  see 
how  lh(3  laws  of  morals  might  not  still  be  natural  even 
though  savages  did  not  know  of  them,  or  why  the 
validity  of  this  Science  of  Morality  should  have  any 
dependence  whatsoever  on  the  practices,  or  the  beliefs, 
or  the  want  of  beliefs,  of  the  savage  races. 

*  "  Origin  of  Civilisation,"  page  414. 


552  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

S.tiU  the  savage  is  always  interesting,  and  conse- 
quently we  shall  now  briefly  tell  the  reader  what  we 
hold  on  the  view  of  Lord  Avebury,  quoted  above — a 
view  which,  we  think  we  can  safely  say,  is  far  from 
possessing  the  authority  which  formerly  it  obtained 
amongst  men  of  learning.  But  before  doing  so  it  will  be 
well  to  make  one  or  two  introductory  remarks.  One  is 
that  a  great  many  people  think  that  we  are  inclined  to 
make  too  much  of  the  savage,  that  the  differences 
between  him  and  the  ordinary  uneducated  civilised  man 
are  only  skin-deep,  and  that  if  we  knew  him  intimately 
we  should  find  that  he  was  a  very  ordinary  being,  and 
in  most  things  very  like  ourselves.  This,  at  all  events, 
was  the  conclusion  come  to  by  Dr.  Livingstone,  who 
had  better  opportunities  for  observing  savages  than 
most  men  have  had.  He  found  savages  he  said, 
"  strange  mixtures  of  good  and  evil,  as  men  are  every- 
where else."  Our  second  remark  is  that,  judging  by 
what  we  know  of  the  necessity  of  certain  of  the  moral 
laws  for  individual  and  racial  existence,  the  conception 
of  a  race  wholly  without  morality,  and  yet  continuing 
for  centuries  to  exist,  is  quite  impossible — almost  as 
impossible  as  that  of  a  race  of  men  without  heart  or 
lungs,  and  yet  continuing  to  live.  As  Dr.  E.  Tjdor 
writes  :  "  Without  a  code  of  morals  the  very  existence 
of  the  rudest  tribe  would  be  impossible."  *  This  argu- 
ment, however,  is  purely  a  priori. 

But  let  us  look  now  at  the  historical  question  proper. 
Recent  anthropologists  have  so  clearly  proved  the 
presence  of  moral  beliefs  in  races  once  regarded  as 
practically  without  moral  beliefs  that  we  are  forced  to 
the  conclusion  that  early  travellers  who  failed  to  notice 
the  presence  of  these  beliefs  must  have  taken  very  little 
trouble  indeed  to  discover  them,  and  that  their  observa- 
tions must  have  been  hurried,  superficial,  and  mis- 
directed. Take  the  case  of  marriage.  According  to 
some  travellers  certain  savage  races  know  nothing  of 

•  "  Primitive  Culture,"  II.,  360. 


ON  SYNDERESIS    -  553 

marriage  laws.  Yet  Ratzel  writes  :*  "  Where  marriage 
has  been  supposed  to  be  absent,  even  among  the  most 
promiscuous  nomads  of  the  forest  and  desert,  its 
existence  has  sooner  or  later  been  in  every  case  estab- 
lished." Other  writers  have  asserted  that  certain 
savages  were  wholly  without  political  organisation. 
Yet  Ratzel  writes  if  "  No  race  is  without  political 
organisation.  .  .  .  What  sociologists  call  individualism 
has  never  been  found  anywhere  in  the  world  as  a  feature 
of  any  race." 

And  these  general  testimonies  are  supported  by 
others  regarding  the  moral  practices  of  particular  races 
of  savages.  J  A  few  such  testimonies  will  suffice  for 
our  purpose.  Of  the  moral  practices  of  Australian 
SAVAGES  who,  according  to  Wake,  §  are  amongst  the 
lowest  of  all  ancient  peoples,  we  have  an  abundance 
of  favourable  testimony.  Ratzel  gives  convincing  proof 
of  the  perfection  of  their  family  life,  the  mutual  love  of 
children  and  parent,  their  respect  for  women  (so  far 
as  that  is  possible  in  the  case  of  a  polygynous  ||  race), 
and  for  the  marriage  vows,  any  violation  of  which  was 
visited  often  with  death.     Marriages  of  relations  they 


*  "  Volkerkunde  "  (Engl.  Transl.),  I.,  114.  Even  Lord  Avcbury 
seems  most  undecided  about  drawing  from  the  testimonies  of  travellers 
the  conclusion  that  savage  races  have  no  morality.  He  throws  cold 
water  on  many  of  their  pronouncements — v.g.,  on  that  testimony  of 
Casalis  in  regard  to  the  Basuto  people,  which  is  given  later  in  this 
chapter.  On  questions  of  justice  he  seems  to  think  in  one  place  that 
the  most  sweeping  conclusion  open  to  him  is  that  property  is  not  so 
safe  amongst  savages  as  amongst  civilised  men. 

f  "  Volkerkunde,"  I.,  129. 

I  We  might,  in  order  to  prove  our  point,  here  draw  up  in  opposition 
to  the  testimonies  adduced  by  P.  Kee  in  his  "  Entstehung  des 
Gewissens  "  and  by  Lord  Avebury,  another  list  of  counter-testimonies 
taken  from  ethicians  like  Flugel,  Westermarck,  Elsenhans,  and 
Cathrein  ;  but  the  testimonies  in  the  text  are  taken  rather  from  men 
like  Ratzel,  Prescott,  Livingstone,  P.  W.  Schmidt,  E.  H.  Man,  whose 
accounts  are  written  from  the  standpoint  of  pure  history,  and  without 
any  reference  to  the  bearing  of  their  testimony  on  Ethical  theory. 

§  In  his  work  on  the  "  Evolution  of  Morality." 

II  It  should  be  remembered  that  Polyg  .-ny  is  not  opposed  to  the 
primary  moral  principles,  but  only  to  the  secondary  principles  of  the 
Natural  Law.  It  could,  therefore,  apart  from  positive  legislation  to 
the  contrary,  be  allowed  in  certain  circumstances. 


554  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

strictly  forbade.  "  The  least  trace,"  *  writes  Ratzel, 
"  of  blood  relationship  is  a  bar  to  marriage."  Often 
marriages  were  forbidden  within  a  particular  clan.j 
Homicide  was  punished  with  banishment.  "If  a 
native,"  writes  Ratzel,  "  murdered  a  member  of  another 
tribe  his  life  was  forfeited  to  that  tribe."  % 

Needless  to  say,  the  homely  virtues  of  these  people 
did  not  long  remain  after  the  arrival  of  the  European. 
All  that  was  good  in  them,  as  in  the  case  of  other  savage 
tribes,  was  turned  to  evil  by  the  greed,  cruelty,  and  dis- 
solute behaviour  of  civilised  men. 

The  African  savage  has  long  been  held  up  before 
our  imagination  as  little  better  than  the  brute,  without 
religion  and  without  morals.  Lord  Avebury  quotes 
Burton's  testimony :  "  Conscience  does  not  exist  in 
Eastern  Africa.  There  robbery  constitutes  an  honour- 
able man."  This  view,  however,  of  the  African  savage 
has  not  been  upheld  by  investigation.  Instead  of  the 
complete  want  of  religion  ascribed  to  them  we  have 
Waitz's  §  testimony  that  the  religion  of  some  of  these 
tribes  was  almost  monotheism.  And  instead  of  utter 
immorality  we  have  Livingstone's  testimony  :  "  After 
long  observation  I  come  to  the  conclusion  that  they 
are  just  a  strange  mixture  of  good  and  evil  as  men  are 
everywhere."  Ratzel  gives  extraordinary  instances  of 
the  delicate  sense  of  honour  of  many  of  these  tribes, 

*  "  Volkerkunde,"  I.,  368  (Engl.  Transl.).  Affinity,  however,  not 
only  was  no  bar  to  marriage,  l)ut  it  was  even  in  some  cases  supposed 
to  confer  some  marital  rights  which  were  certainly  not  in  accordance 
with  the  natural  law.  Whether  these  supposed  rights  were  publicly 
admitted  or  whether  they  were  simply  an  evil  practice,  we  have  not 
been  able  to  determine  with  any  certainty.  We  believe  that  they 
were  only  an  evil  practice,  but  common. 

t  This  custom,  known  as  Exogamy,  was  a  marked  characteristic  of 
many  African  tribes,  who  in  this  matter  present  a  strange  contrast  to 
the  customs  of  the  Inca  tribes  of  Peru,  who  make  it  a  law  that  marriages 
should  take  place  only  within  the  clan.     See  Vol.  11.,  451. 

J  "  Yolk,"  page  379.  An  interesting  study  in  regard  to  their 
religious  beliefs  will  be  found  in  Vol.  11.,  page  34,  where  it  is  shown, 
in  spite  of  Messrs  Spencer  and  Gillen  that  the  North  Central  Australians, 
th(-ugh  now  ai)paiently  without  religion,  were  once  po.ssessed  of  a  pure 
religion,  most  i  robably  one  of  pure  monotl  eisni. 

§  "  Anthropologic  der  Naturv61ker." 


ON  SYNDERESIS  555 

and  shows  *  that,  foreign  influences  apart,  the  more 
primitive  they  are  in  their  manners  the  purer  are  they 
in  their  practices.  The  love  of  mothers  for  their  children 
is  most  tender.  Livingstone  relates  how,  at  the  slave 
markets,  no  mother  could  be  found  to  sell  her  children 
to  the  Arabs.  Even  grown-up  negroes  are  exceedingly 
attached  to  their  parents,  f  No  doubt  these  African 
negroes  have  many  vices,  just  as  civilised  men  have  (it 
is  one  of  the  advantages  of  civilisation  that  it  can  hide 
its  vices).  But,  considering  the  abnormal  conditions 
under  which  they  have  lived,  their  extreme  desire  for 
pleasure,  the  lightness  of  their  imaginations,  J  and  the 
warmth  of  their  temperament,  their  vices  were  com- 
paratively few.  Ratzel  writes :  "  Divorce  is  rare 
amongst  (those)  tribes  which  lead  a  simple  life  undis- 
turbed ;  nor  is  adultery  so  frequent  as  among  those 
who  have  accumulated  capital,  possess  numerous  slaves, 
and  have  come  into  closer  contact  with  Arabs  or  Euro- 
peans." §  That  stealing  was  regarded  as  a  crime  is 
evident  from  the  punishments  that  followed.  It  was 
regarded  by  them  as  worthy  of  a  second  death.  In 
the  case  of  many  tribes  perjury  was  punished  with 
death. 

Of  these  African  races  we  shall  mention  three  in 
particular :  (a)  The  Hottentots,  as  can  be  proved 
by  an  abundance  of  testimonies,  honoured  marriage 
and  married  early.  The  giving  away  of  the  daughter 
was  the  strict  right  of  her  parents,  and  marriages 
between  relations  were  strictly  forbidden. ||  Murder, 
stealing,  and  marital  infidelity  w'ere  severely  punished. 
Apart  from  certain  cases  to  be  considered  later — cases, 
namely,  in  which  the  savage  mistook  the  law  of  nature — 

*  "  Yolk.,"  II.,  325. 

I  The  practice  of  abandoning  parents  when  they  become  helpless, 
which  was  not  uncommon  with  these  people,  is  explained,  p.  565. 

J  Negroes  will  often  laugh  a  whole  day  at  the  silliest  joke  or  the 
most  trilling  mishap. 
§  "  Volk.,"  II..  383. 

II  Katzel  Volk.,  II.,  291.  For  a  fuller  discussion  of  their  religious 
and  other  moral  principles  see  Vol.  li.,  pages  37,  409,  460. 


556  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

these  Hottentots  were  remarkable  for  the  love  of  parent 
and  child.  The  girls  especially  seem  to  have  been 
brought  up  most  carefully.  From  Europeans  these 
poor  people  have  not  learned  much  that  has  helped  the 
purity  of  their  morals. 

(b)  The  Bushmen  have  commonly  been  regarded  as 
the  lowest  of  all  savages.  The  wonder  is  that  they 
have  any  morality  at  all,  considering  the  conditions  of 
their  life  and  their  long  and  hopeless  struggle  against 
adversity.  Yet  of  their  moral  beliefs  there  cannot  be 
the  least  doubt.  They  enter  the  married  state  young 
and  with  much  ceremony,  and  usually  with  public 
assurances  (which  are  regarded  as  necessary)  of  their 
love  for  one  another.*  Marital  infidelity  is  severely 
punished  by  them.  Still,  being  polygynous,  the  status 
of  women  is  low. 

(c)  The  Dwarf  Races  of  Central  Africa  were 
formerly  believed  to  be  without  morality,  but  through 
the  investigations  of  M.  Le  Roy  who  lived  amongst 
them  for  many  years,  as  well  as  through  recent  studies 
into  the  lives  of  the  Pygmy  races  generally,  and  in 
particular  Mr.  Man's  examination  f  of  the  habits  and 
beliefs  of  the  Andaman  Islanders,  reliable  information 
is  now  to  hand  which  is  completely  at  variance  with  the 
older  theories.  These  Pygmy  races  have  been  shown 
to  be  possessed  of  a  religion  of  pure  monotheism,  their 
marriage  system  is  one  of  strict  monogyny,  and  in  spite 
of  much  licentiousness  in  practice,  their  beliefs  and 
laws  are  found  to  be  comparable  to  those  of  the  most 
civilised  races.  Wessmann  (whom  Ratzel  regards  as 
the  most  trustworthy  authority  on  the  Central  Africans) 
praises  the  "  timidly  modest,  almost  girlishly  shy, 
demeanour  of  the  Batuas  in  the  Basonge  country  "  and 
Ratzel  speaks  of  them  as  a  race  "  whose  existence  is 
thoroughly  justified  on  natural,  and  above  all  on  social 
grounds." 

»  Kat/.fl,  II.,  274. 
For  ail  iiccouiii  of  these  investigations  see  Vol.  1 1.,  pages  37,  ^^5,  408. 


ON  SYNDERESIS  557 

The  North  American  Indians  are  remarkable  for 
their  high  moral  code.  Their  truthfulness,  honour  and 
kindness  are  proverbial.  Robbery,  at  least  from  one 
of  the  same  tribe,  is  quite  unknown  amongst  them. 
P.  de  Smet,  S.J.,  in  his  "  Voyages  dans  I'Amerique 
Septentrionale,"  gives  proof  of  their  high  moral  per- 
ceptions. They  punished  severely  robbery,  marital 
infidelity,  murder,  and  lying.  They  did  not  favour, 
though  they  allowed,  polygyny.  Their  respect  for 
marriage  was  remarkable.  Friendships  between  young 
men  and  young  women  were  allowed  only  with  a  view 
to  marriage.  Disrespect  to  parents  was  punished 
severely.  Crimes  committed  in  drunkenness  were  not 
punished,  which  of  itself  may  be  regarded  as  proof  of 
the  clearness  of  their  moral  views.  Ratzel  mentions 
the  absurd  opinion  advocated  by  some  travellers,  that 
the  purity  of  the  Indian  is  due  to  his  indolence — an 
opinion  which  is  valueless  except  as  a  testimony  to 
their  purity. 

The  great  fault  of  the  Indian  mind  is  the  intensity  of 
its  hate.  In  the  matter  of  punishments  the  Indian 
seems  to  have  known  no  bounds.  Such  faults,  how- 
ever, are  quite  compatible  with  the  possession  of 
high  moral  perceptions  on  the  sacredness  of  the  moral 
law. 

The  Peruvians,  though  barbarous,  had  a  very  high 
morality.  Their  form  of  government  under  territorial 
viceroys,  with  one  principal  Inca  or  chief,  was  a  despotic 
monarchy  of  a  very  perfect  kind.  "  Their  laws,"  writes 
Prescott,  "  were  few  and  exceedingly  severe.  They 
related  almost  wholly  to  criminal  matters.  .  .  . 
The  crimes  of  theft,  adultery,  and  murder  were  all 
capital." 

The  FuEGiANS,  or  inhabitants  of  Terra  del  Fuego, 
who  were  once  regarded  as  completely  Un-Ethical, 
have  proved  a  great  disappointment  to  the  positivist 
ethicians.  It  has  been  shown  that,  in  spite  of  their 
hard  and  unhappy  lives  and  the  abnormal  conditions 


558  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

of  their  ^vretched  country,  this  people  has  still  its  moral 
code  dealing  with  such  crimes  as  stealing,  lying,  marital 
infidelity,  and  homicide.  Of  them  Ratzel  writes :  * 
"  Hardly  any  race  has  been  so  much  under-estimated 
as  the  Fuegians  in  respect  of  intellectual  capacity. 
Their  whole  life  is  so  wretched  that  it  would  seem 
useless  to  speak  of  any  spark  of  higher  intuition.  Yet 
it  would  better  correspond  with  the  facts  to  lay  special 
emphasis  on  the  way  in  which,  in  spite  of  all  this,  the 
rites  of  the  dead  are  here  as  faithfully  observed  and  as 
thoroughly  performed  as  among  opulent  nations.  .  .  . 
They  distinguish  between  good  and  evil  spirits,"  etc. 
Also — "  Many  customs  point  to  the  fear  of  punishment 
(for  crime)  by  higher  powers — for  instance,  various 
rules  for  food  and  abstinence."  These  can  scarcely 
be  described  as  the  customs  of  a  people  not  knowing 
good  and  evil. 

The  Hyperboreans. — "  By  far  the  greater  number 
of  testimonies,"  writes  Ratzel,  "  to  the  character  of  the 
Hyperboreans  are  favourable.  Honourable,  good,  in- 
offensive, is  the  praise  given  by  the  Russians  to  nearly 
all  the  inhabitants  of  Northern  Asia.  It  is  doubly 
strong  if  we  consider  the  mass  of  wickedness  with 
which  for  some  decades  the  deportation  of  criminals 
from  Russia  has  been  leavening  the  whole  region."  f 

The  general  impression  left  at  all  events  on  us  (who 
are  no  specialists  on  the  subject  of  Anthropology)  by 
our  reading  of  the  ways  and  habits  of  savage  peoples 
is,  not  that  they  did  not  know  of  a  moral  law  or  of 
moral  distinctions,  but  rather  that,  unless  we  hold  that 
their  moral  views  have  come  down  to  them  from  a 
former  period  of  civilisation,  it  would  be  impossible  to 
account  for  their  beliefs,  so  correct  and  so  decisive,  so 
unalterable,  and  particularly  so  universal  is  their  know- 
ledge of  the  laws  of  nature — for  instance,  of  marriage, 
of  truthfulness,  of  property,  and  of  the    right  of  men 

•"  V61k.,"  II,,  91 
t  Ibid.,  201. 


ON  SYNDERESIS  559 

to  their  vJives.*  In  the  wretched  condition  in  which 
we  now  find  many  of  these  savage  peoples  the  discovery 
by  them  of  such  laws  at  any  kind  of  later  period  seems 
to  us  an  absolute  impossibility.  Without  tradition, 
without  the  leisure  necessary  for  thinking,  with  no 
fixed  habitation  and  no  security  against  incursion  from 
other  warlike  and  nomadic  tribes,  often  with  no  settled 
form  of  government  and  very  little  knowledge  of,  or 
care  for  a  "  common  good,"  these  wretched  peoples 
could  no  more  have  formulated  the  code  of  laws  which 
they  at  present  recognise  f  than  a  body  of  unthinking 
vagrants  could  formulate  it  even  under  civilised  con- 
ditions. We  are  here  dealing  with  a  concrete  case. 
We  know  the  conditions  of  life  required  for  the  making 
of  such  laws  as  these,  and  we  know  that  these  con- 
ditions are  not  those  under  which  the  savage  races  now 
exist. 

The  reader  may  not,  indeed,  consider  that  we  are 
justified  by  the  facts  in  drawing  such  a  conclusion  as 
that  which  we  have  just  announced  ;  but  he  will,  at 
all  events,  agree  that  the  statement  that  savages  "  are 
entirely  wanting  in  moral  feeling  "  is  utterly  opposed 
to  fact,  and  to  the  clear  testimony  of  History  and 
Anthropology. 

A   DIFFICULTY   CONSIDERED 

Our  purpose  in  the  foregoing  argument  has  been  to 
sliow  that,  because  savages  are  possessed  of  moral 
codes  not  very  different  from  our  own,  their  moral 
beliefs  must  also  be  the  same  in  character  as  ours.  But 
in  connection  with  this  argument  a  difficult}^  presents 
itself,  of  which  much  has  been  made  by  Lord  Avebury 
and  others,  and  which  it  will  be  necessary  to  consider 

*  Whether,  even  in  this  former  state  of  civilisation,  these  laws 
were  given  by  revelation  or  were  discovered  by  Reason  is  quite  another 
question. 

•f  It  IS  the  universality  and  the  decisiveness  of  their  moral  percep- 
tions timt  we  most  insist  upon  here. 


56o  THE   SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

here — namely,  whether  it  is  lawful  to  conclude  that 
because  the  savage  codes  of  conduct  are  largely  similar 
to  our  own,  their  moral  beliefs  also  must  be  of  the 
same  character  as  our  own.  The  difficulty  may  be  put 
as  follows  :  May  it  not  be  that  if  the  savage  avoids 
murder  and  adultery  and  theft  he  avoids  them  either 
from  instinct,  as  the  animals  avoid  certain  actions,  or 
(if  he  acts  from  Reason)  from  some  non-moral  motive, 
such  as  because  it  pays  to  avoid  them  and  not  because 
he  believes  that  these  things  are  intrinsically  evil.  In 
either  case  practice  would  be  no  guarantee  of  the 
presence  in  the  savage  mind  of  moral  beliefs  such  as 
civilised  men  possess.  If  we  attribute  moral  percep- 
tions to  savages  simply  because  they  perform  their 
natural  duties  of  parental  and  filial  love,  then,  says 
Lord  Avebury,  "  we  must  equally  well  credit  rooks  and 
bees  and  other  gregarious  animals  with  a  moral  state 
higher  than  that  of  civilised  men,"  * 

Now,  this  difficulty  may  be  met  by  the  following 
considerations :  (i)  If  savages  in  their  external  acts 
follow  the  same  laws  of  conduct  that  prevail  amongst 
ourselves  it  devolves  upon  our  opponents  to  show  that 
the  motives  of  savages  in  so  doing  are  different  from 
ours — that  is,  that  the  practices  of  savages  proceed 
either  from  instinct,  as  is  the  case  with  animals,  or 
from  some  non-moral  motive  like  that  of  avoiding 
certain  painful  consequences,  instead  of  from  a  per- 
suasion that  these  acts  are  intrinsically  evil  and  to  be 
avoided.  But  this,  so  far  as  we  are  aware,  our  op- 
ponents have  not  succeeded  in  doing.  (2)  It  is  evident 
that  instinct  is  not  the  sole  motive  power  of  the  moral 
practices  of  savages.  For  savages  of  the  very  lowest 
grade  have  Reason  just  like  civilised  men,  and  where 
Reason  is  present  it  must,  to  a  large  extent,  become 
the  guide  of  conduct.  Besides,  savages  are  possessed 
of  written  codes,  or  at  least  they  are  able  to  give 
intellectual  expression  to  their  tribal  laws,  from  which 

•  "  Origin  of  Civilisation,"  page  416. 


ON  SYNDERESIS  561 

we  conclude  that  intellect,  not  instinct,  is  their  internal 
principle  of  conduct.  Again,  in  punishing  certain 
crimes,  savages  allow  for  certain  mitigating  circum- 
stances, such  as  the  fact  of  their  being  committed  in 
drunkenness,  which  plainly  is  possible  only  to  Reason. 

Then,  again,  the  motive  is  not  some  lower  non-moral 
end,  such  as  that  some  conduct  pays  and  other  conduct 
injures,  but  a  persuasion  that  certain  actions  are  in- 
trinsically good  and  to  be  done  and  others  intrinsically 
bad  and  to  be  avoided.  For,  in  the  first  place,  many 
of  the  testimonies  of  travellers  concern  not  merely  the 
acts  of  savages  but  their  confessions  that  certain  acts 
are  good  and  others  evil,  and  in  these  confessions  there 
is  no  mention  of  any  extrinsic  motive  such  as  the  pain 
or  the  pleasure  that  results  from  conduct  or  of  any 
condition  on  which  the  goodness  or  badness  of  these 
acts  depends,  but  only  the  simple  proposition  that  some 
acts  are  good  (categorically  good)  and  others  evil  ;  in 
other  words,  that  acts  are  morally  and  intrinsically 
good  or  evil.  Secondly,  savages  believe  that  the  gods 
will  and  must  punish  certain  very  heinous  crimes,  a 
belief  which  could  only  arise  from  a  conviction  of  the 
intrinsic  evil  of  these  crimes.  Thirdly,  the  nuptial 
rites  and  ceremonies  so  characteristic  of  savage  mar- 
riages denote  their  belief  in  a  certain  inner  sacredness 
attaching  to  the  state  of  marriage,  and  consequently 
a  belief  in  the  intrinsic  moral  evil  of  any  courses  of 
conduct  that  are  not  in  accordance  with  the  marriage 
law. 

These  are  only  a  few  of  the  arguments  that  might 

be  used  in  answer  to  Lord  Avebury.     But  it  seems  to 

us  little  better  than  wanton  and  unreasoning  unfairness 

to  claim  that  the  very  same  courses  of  conduct  that, 

in   the   case  of   civilised   men,   spring  solely   from   our 

moral   belief   in   their   intrinsic  goodness   may,   in   the 

savage  races,  be  the  outcome  of  other  faculties  or  other 

motives,  or  even  to  expect  us  to  prove  that  the  motives 

in  tiie  two  cases  are  the  same.     The  savage  is  a  man, 
Vol.  1—36 


562  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

in  all  essentials  just  like  ourselves,  and  his  mental  con- 
stitution must,  as  regards  the  ultimate  principles  and 
springs  of  action,  be  the  same  as  ours. 

Some  Principles  for  Estimating  the  Value  of  the 
Testimonies  of  Positivists 

We  think  it  well  to  put  before  the  reader  the  follow- 
ing points  which  we  think  should  be  borne  in  mind  in 
estimating  the  value  of  testimonies  such  as  those 
quoted  by  Lord  Avebury  and  P.  Ree  concerning  the 
moral   beliefs  of  savages  : — 

(i)  Those  testimonies  which  are  opposed  to  ours  are 
not  intended  generally  to  prove  that  no  savage  races 
acknowledge  moral  distinctions,  but  only  that  particular 
tribes  acknowledge  none. 

(2)  Where  two  men  testify,  one  that  he  could  not 
observe  any  knowledge  of  moral  distinctions  amongst 
certain  savage  tribes,  the  other  that  he  did  observe 
these  distinctions  and  that  a  knowledge  of  them  was 
evinced  in  the  customs  and  laws  of  these  peoples,  and 
proved  by  their  own  admissions  to  him,  then  this 
second  testimony  is  to  be  accepted  and  not  the  first 
(competency,  etc.,  of  course,  being  supposed).  This 
may  seem  a  strange  and  a  one-sided  claim  to  make, 
but  it  is  quite  logical,  and  it  would  hold  in  any  science 
that  depended  upon  observation  as  that  of  Anthro- 
pology does.  If  two  astronomers  testify,  one  that  he 
has  observed  a  comet,  not  for  a  moment  only  but  for  a 
long  time,  and  clearly,  another,  viewing  the  same  part 
of  the  heavens,  that  he  has  observed  none,  then  this 
second  testimony  is  not  supposed  to  prevail  against 
the  first,  or  even  to  impair  its  value,  since  the  conditions 
which  favour  observation  may  not  have  been  realised  in 
this  second  case. 

Still,  we  admit  that,  in  the  case  of  morals,  we  should 
be  able  to  explain  why  it  is  that  a  competent  observer 
has  failed  to  recognise  the  presence  of  moral  bclicls  in 


ON  SYNDERESIS  563 

those  very  same  cases  in  which  other  observers  seem 
to  have  had  very  httle  difficulty  in  finding  them.  The 
causes  of  this  faihire  may  be  man}^ — (a)  prejudice  in 
favour  of  a  particular  Ethical  theory,  [b)  romance — or 
the  desire  to  meet,  or  to  seem  to  have  met,  people 
with  customs  wholly  different  from  our  own,  (c)  incom- 
plete observation  consequent  on  hurry  (not  an  unknown 
thing  with  travellers),  or  upon  ignorance  of  the  lan- 
guage,* {d)  the  natural  reserve  of  savage  peoples  them- 
selves in  their  dealings  with  strangers,  f  {e)  more  than 
all  others,  the  habit  of  concluding  from  the  prevalence 
of  immoral  practices  to  the  absence  of  all  moral  beliefs. 
It  is,  in  general,  exceedingly  difficult,  and,  indeed, 
impossible,  to  argue  from  the  dissoluteness  of  a  race, 
to  the  total  absence  of  moral  principle  or  moral  beliefs 
amongst  its  members.  Thus  (to  take  a  case  mentioned 
by  Lord  Avebury  J),  according  to  Casalis,  the  Basuti, 
on  the  death  of  their  chief,  gave  themselves  up  to  every 
sort  of  licentiousness  until  his  successor  was  appointed. 
Can  we  accept  the  conclusion  that,  therefore,  they 
regarded  all  law  as  dependent  on  the  will  of  their  chief, 
whose  death  annulled  the  law  ?  If  so,  then  future 
historians  might  also  judge  that  most  workmen  in 
certain  Scotch  and  English  cities  regard  the  law  of 
temperance  as  suspended  on  bank  holidays,  since  on 
that  day  so  many  people  act  as  if  it  were  suspended. 
It  is  always  difficult  to  argue  from  outward  action  to 
inner  belief.  If  action  never  contradicted  inner  con- 
viction there  would  be  no  sin.  De  facto,  we  can  show 
proof  of  the  pure  moral  beliefs  of  the  Basuti. 

(3)  As  many  cases  of  immorality  recorded  appertain 
to  injustice  we  must  be  careful  to  ascertain  whether 
the  alleged  acts  are  really  acts  of  injustice,  or  w^hether 

*  A  remarkable  instance  of  mal-observation  is  provided  in  the 
case  of  the  Andaman  Islanders.  For  years  these  were  regarded  as 
without  religion  or  marriage.  They  are  now  known  to  be  a  highly 
religious  people,  and  monotheists,  whilst  their  marriage  system  is 
one  of  strict  monogyny.     See  Vol.  II.,  pages  37  and  45. 

I  See  instance  of  Maoris,  Vol.  II.,  page  39. 

j  "  Origin  oJ  Civilisation,"  page  418. 


564  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

they  are  not  rather  acts  that,  to  the  untutored  mind, 
might  seem  allowable,  even  though  these  minds  pos- 
sessed a  keen  sense  of  justice  and  of  the  law  generally. 
It  is  hard  to  expect,  for  instance,  that  in  an  environ- 
ment of  plunder,  such  as  nomadic  and  warlike  races 
live  in,  men  will  be  delicate  about  the  appropriation  of 
other  people's  goods,  when  there  is  absolutely  no 
security  for  their  own.  May  it  not  seem  to  them  that 
if  all  men  steal  from  them,  they  may  steal  freely  in 
return  ?     And  are  they  wholly  wrong  ? 

(4)  We  should  be  careful  to  ascertain  whether  the 
cases  in  question  are  really  cases  of  natural  law  or 
only  of  positive  law.  Positive  laws  may  and  must 
differ  according  to  circumstances  of  environment  and 
needs,  and  consequently  the  positive  laws  of  savages 
cannot  be  the  same  as  ours.  Even  the  natural  law  may 
vary  to  some  extent  in  various  nations,  since  it  often 
depends  in  its  application  upon  positive  conditions 
which  in  their  variety  and  unaccountableness  must 
yield  very  different  codes  of  morality  in  different  cases. 
Again,  the  secondary  principles  of  morality  may  vary, 
though  the  primary  cannot.*  These  differences  are 
often  left  out  of  view  in  treating  of  the  manners  and 
beliefs  of  savages. 

(5)  We  do  not  claim,  in  the  case  of  savages,  any 
certain  knowledge  of  morality  further  than  that  of  the 
simpler  primary  moral  principles  and  immediate  and 
easy  deductions  from  them.  In  complicated  cases — 
cases,  namely,  in  which  there  is  more  than  one  moral 
principle  involved — it  would  be  strange  if  the  savage 
mind  were  to  judge,  not  only  invariably,  but  eyen 
often,  aright.  In  these  difficult  cases,  as  a  rule,  it  is 
to  be  expected  that  untutored  minds  will  just  come  to 
such  conclusions  as  suit  their  own  individual  and  racial 

•  Thus,  much  is  often  made  of  the  practice  of  polygyny  and  of  dis- 
soluble marriaRos  amongst  savage  races,  though  neither  of  these  is 
opposed  to  the  primary  princijiles  of  the  natural  law.  For  dilfereuce 
of  primary  and  sucoudury  principles  sec  Vol.  II.,  pages  417,  419,  425, 
429. 


ON  SYNDERESIS  565 

convenience.  Take  the  case  of  homicide  as  an  instance. 
The  law  in  civiHsed  countries  is  roughly  this — that  no 
man  may  kill  another  unless  in  self-defence  or  when 
authorised  by  the  State  to  do  so — that  in  war  he  may 
kill  an  enemy  whenever  he  meets  one.  Now,  no  savage 
nation  would  allow  the  killing  of  a  man  by  one  of  his 
own  tribe.  If  it  allows  killing  in  other  cases,  the  reason 
is  that  inter-tribal  warfare  is  the  normal  condition  of 
these  nomadic  races.  We  have,  however,  express 
testimony  that  respect  for  human  life  in  many  cases 
extends  outside  the  tribal  limits,  i.e.,  that  some  races 
forbid  the  killing  of  all  except  members  of  tribes  known 
to  be  hostile.  On  the  general  principles,  therefore, 
the  views  of  savages  would  seem  to  be  fairly  correct, 
and  if  on  applied  questions,  as  to  when  competing 
interests  justilies  the  killing  of  others,  they  sometimes 
hold  erroneous  views,  their  error  is  to  be  attributed 
to  the  poverty  and  unreliability  of  the  savage  judgment 
in  practically  all  spheres  of  thinking,  wherever  the 
problem  is  in  the  least  complicated. 

But  let  us  now  take  the  two  cases  of  patricide  and 
infanticide,  so  much  relied  on  by  positivists.  The  old 
and  infirm  were,  in  the  case  of  some  savage  tribes, 
often  freely  done  away  with,  and  deformed  and 
illegitimate  children  were  strangled  at  birth.  Now, 
these  are  cases  of  the  complicated  ethical  problem  of 
which  we  have  spoken,  which  only  the  trained  mind 
may  be  trusted  to  solve  aright.  Take,  first,  the  killing 
of  aged  parents.  The  savage  finds  himself  here  con- 
fronted with  two  or  three  important  moral  principles. 
The  first  is  the  principle  that  the  killing  of  a  relation  is 
a  very  great  evil.  In  that  conviction  all  savage  tribes 
agree,  and  the  most  stringent  laws  are  enacted  against 
the  killing  of  a  member  of  one's  own  family.  Secondly, 
there  is  the  principle  of  affection  for  an  aged  and  infirm 
parent,  who  must  be  protected  from  pain.  Now,  in 
the  cases  under,  discission,  it  seems  to  us  that  this 
principle  of  affection  was  itself  the  actuating  force  that 


565  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

gave  rise  to  this  apparently  cruel  custom  of  patricide, 
because  in  cases  of  patricide  death  seemed  to  be  the 
only  source  of  relief  for  the  aged  and  the  infirm.  For 
it  should  be  remembered  that  these  wandering  tribes 
had  to  be  ever  ready  to  break  up  their  camps  and  fly 
at  the  approach  of  other  hordes  stronger  than  their 
own,  and  that  should  an  attack  be  made  the  old  and 
infirm  should  necessarily  become  captives  and  be  sub- 
jected to  torture.  Torture  and  death  were  the  general 
fate  of  prisoners  of  war.  We  have,  indeed,  the  testi- 
mony of  Flugel  and  Waitz  that  Indian  Chiefs  over  and 
over  again  enacted  laws  against  the  torturing  of  those 
whom  their  subjects  had  taken  in  battle,  but  we  know 
also  from  the  same  authorities  that,  though  these  efforts 
to  improve  matters  were  often  successful,  they  were 
not  always  so.  Thirdly,  there  was  question  here  of  a 
principle  so  difficult  of  solution  even  for  us  civilised  men, 
as  to  how  far  the  private  good  must  be  subjected  to  the 
necessities  of  the  State,  and  if  the  tribe  was  to  main- 
tain its  existence,  it  was  necessary  that  its  movements 
should  not  be  impeded  in  any  way  in  case  of  flight. 
But  that  the  old  and  helpless  would  impede  it  there 
could  be  no  doubt.  Here,  then,  were  several  principles 
which  it  was  not  easy  for  the  savage  to  reconcile  or  to 
choose  between,  and  it  is  no  wonder  if  he  chose  what 
seemed  to  be  at  once  the  more  filial  and  the  more 
patriotic  course — namely,  with  all  delicacy  and  affection 
to  put  his  parent  out  of  the  reach  of  pain,  and  at  the  same 
time  to  set  his  tribe  free  to  make  the  best  of  its  oppor- 
tunities against  any  other  tribe  that  might  appear. 

The  case  of  children  offered  a  similar  difficulty. 
After  the  birth  of  her  child  the  savage  mother  was 
often,  as  Westermarck  tells  us,  abandoned  by  her 
husband,  who  felt  himself  free  to  roam  the  plains,  and 
often  did  not  return  for  two  or  three  years.  Should  a 
strange  tribe  come  down  upon  them  during  that  time, 
the  mother  and  child,  not  being  able,  to  fly  with  the 
rest,    should    necessarily    be   captured ;     and    it    is   not 


ON  SYNDERESIS  567 

wonderful  if,  to  the  savage  mother's  mind,  it  seemed 
better  to  do  away  with  the  child  at  once  than  to  risk 
both  its  safety  and  her  own.  Illegitimate  children  were 
killed  because  there  was  nobody  to  support  them,  and 
deformed  children  because,  either  they  were  a  menace 
to  the  race,  or  because  they  were  believed  to  be  of  no 
good  import.  These  are  all  complicated  moral  cases, 
and  it  is  not  wonderful  that  the  savage  mind  could  not 
solve  them  correctly.  But  they  by  no  means  prove  that 
the  savage  mind  knew  nothing  about  the  immorality 
of  homicide.  Even  the  Romans,  who  could  scarcely 
be  said  to  favour  homicide,  passed  the  law  of  the  Twelve 
Tables.* 

In  such  concrete  cases  as  these,  therefore,  the  savage 
mind  must  often  err.  But  on  the  broader  principles 
of  the  natural  law  their  racial  sense  was  generally 
correct.  They  did  not  all  believe  in  monogyny  or  in 
indissoluble  marriage.  But  these  things  are  after  all 
not  primary  principles  of  nature.  Neither,  indeed,  was 
marriage  always  the  formal  ceremony  that  it  is  to  us. 
But  in  the  necessity  of  it  they  had  a  firm  belief.  How- 
ever, on  the  love  of  parents,  on  the  rights  of  men,  both 
as  against  one  another  and  against  society,  on  the 
wrongfulness  of  murder,  on  the  sanctity  of  the  hearth, 
on  the  excellence  of  justice,  and  benevolence,  and 
fortitude,  they  were  beyond  question  possessed  of  such 
a  certitude  as  could  scarcely  be  expected  from  men  of 
very  undeveloped  minds,  and  most  unthinking  lives. 
That  here  and  there  cases  may  be  found  of  races  so 
degenerate  as  to  evince  scarcely  any  moral  life  what- 
soever we  are  quite  prepared  to  admit.  We  have 
already  said  that  Conscience  may  decay.  But  from 
this  we  must  not  conclude  that  Conscience  is  not  a 
constant  human  possession,  or  that  it  is  but  the  result 
of  training  of  custom  or  of  convention. 

*  Savages  have  no  severer  laws  than  those  enacted  by  the  Romans 
against  the  slaves,  such  as  the  law  that,  if  the  master  of  the  house  were 
killed,  the  slaves  also  should  die  to  a  man. 


568  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

In  conclusion  we  may  be  permitted  to  express  some 
surprise  that  men  even  of  culture  and  learning  would 
seek  to  determine  what  is  natural  in  our  beliefs  from 
the  practices  and  attainments  of  the  lowest  and  poorest 
members  of  our  race,  instead  of  from  the  highest  and 
the  best.  Men  do  not  judge  of  the  powers  of  the  eagle 
from  one  that  has  never  been  allowed  to  see  the  open 
heavens,  and  consequently  never  comes  to  be  the 
splendid  thing  that  it  is  meant  to  be  in  the  design  of 
nature.  Why  should  we  judge  of  what  is  natural  to 
man  from  the  attainments  of  the  mentally  decrepit  and 
the  solitary,  for  whom  the  circumstances  of  their  lives 
have  made  thought  and  development  impossible  ?  * 

Though  ethicall}^  therefore,  we  should  have  no 
difficulty  in  admitting  the  possibility  of  very  wide 
differences  between  the  savage  codes  and  ours,  still, 
looking  at  the  matter  historically,  we  are  convinced 
that  not  only  have  savages  their  moral  feelings  and  a 
firm  grasp  of  the  general  difference  between  right  and 
wrong,  but  that  their  detailed  codes  are  in  the  main 
right,  and  in  principle,  so  far  at  all  events  as  the  primary 
laws  of  nature  are  concerned,  are  exactly  like  our  own. 
We  are  convinced  that  the  study  of  the  Naturvolker 
discloses  between  their  morality  and  ours  a  degree  of 
identity  on  all  the  broader  principles  which  is  far  beyond 
what  ethically  and  logically  we  should  have  expected 
or  been  prepared  for,  considering  that  in  other  things 
civilisation  and  savagery  stand  so  far  apart. 

II.  "  Homo  Sapiens  Ferus  "  f 

It  is  contended  that  the  wild  man  of  the  woods — 
the  solitary — is  conscious  of  no  moral  law.     How,  then, 

•  We  have  not  mentioned  the  argument  that  even  savages  often 
use  terms  expressing  certain  crimes  as  their  vilest  and  most  opprobrious 
terms  of  abuse.  St.  Paul  gives  prominence  to  the  argument  in  another 
connection. 

t  The  solitary  is  to  bo  carefully  distinguished  from  the  savage,  foi 
the  savage  livts  in  society  and  lias  the  use  of  speech,  the  solitary  lives 
alone  and  has  never  learned  to  .speak. 


ON  SYNDERESIS  569 

it  is  asked,  can  Conscience  be  regarded  as  natural  to 
man  ?  We  have  already  said  something  on  this  ques- 
tion in  another  chapter.  But  a  word  in  addition  may 
not  be  out  of  place.  It  will  not  be  necessary  here  to 
take  up  the  various  authentic  cases  brought  together 
by  Rauber  in  his  remarkable  work  on  the  wild  human 
solitaries — "  Homo  Sapiens  Ferus."  But,  looking  at 
these  cases  generally,  we  believe  that  they  will  be 
found  to  confirm  a  view  to  which  we  have  already 
given  expression — namely,  that  Reason,  absolutely  un- 
aided, and  especially  unaided  by  speech,  is  incapable 
of  exercise  except  in  the  crudest  possible  way,  and, 
therefore,  is  scarcely  capable  of  forming  for  itself  any 
conclusion  of  permanent  value,  whether  in  Mathematics 
or  in  Morals,  or  in  anything  else.  If,  however,  the 
faculty  of  Reason,  through  want  of  use,  has  not  de- 
generated, if  only  a  few  words  be  possessed,  then  with 
even  the  beginnings  of  thought  supplied  the  individual 
can  advance  very  rapidly  on  the  way  to  moral  truth, 
and  can  soon  come  to  believe  in  moral  distinctions 
apart  from  authority,  and  can  embrace  the  moral  truth 
in  and  for  itself,  and  show  a  grasp  of  moral  relations 
as  real  and  as  secure  as  that  which  he  possesses  of  the 
more  elementary  truths  of  Mathematics. 

Now  this  view  is  confirmed  by  the  study  of  the  cases 
mentioned  by  Rauber. 

In  every  instance  recorded  by  Rauber  the  Solitary's 
mind  bore  in  the  main  the  same  relation  to  Morals  as  it 
did  to  Mathematics  or  to  any  natural  science.  Before 
the  mind  could  make  any  inferences  it  had  to  be  taught 
a  language,  and  its  attention  had  to  be  directed  to  some 
particular  sphere  of  thought.  When  the  attention  of 
these  wild  solitaries  was   directed  to   the  moral  law  * 

*  The  wild  maiden  of  Champagne,  mentioned  by  Rauber,  had 
evidently  used  her  thinking  faculty  in  some  way,  early  in  life,  for 
though  she  could  not  speak  she  remembered  to  have  at  some  time  seen 
houses,  which  was  probably  a  remembrance  of  her  home  from  which 
she  had  been  lost  before  she  learned  to  speak.  This  may  have  been 
the  reason  why  there  was  no  difiiculty  in  teaching  her  the  moral  law, 
and  the  rudiments  of  religion.     The  moral  law  became  tu  her  a  rea  ity 


570  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

and  to  moral  distinctions  between  acts,  their  moral 
beliefs  came  home  to  them  as  rapidly  as  any  others, 
such  as  those  of  Mathematics  or  Physics,  or  rather 
much  more  rapidly.  We  have  records  in  Rauber's 
work  of  the  high  degree  of  moral  culture  attained  by 
many  of  these  reclaimed  children  of  nature.  We  have, 
as  far  as  we  remember,  no  record  of  their  attaining  to 
anything  like  proficiency  in  other  branches  of  learning. 

To  sum  up — We  have  seen  how  differences  of  moral 
codes  are  quite  compatible  with  the  natural  and  per- 
manent character  of  the  moral  laws  themselves.  If 
racial  intellects  differ  in  point  of  keenness,  why  not 
their  deductions  differ  also  ? — and  morality  is  for  the 
most  part  a  deduction.  Besides,  even  civilised  men 
often  fail  to  solve  complicated  moral  cases.  Why 
should  not  the  untrained  mind  fail  to  solve  compara- 
tively easy  ones  ?  Experience,  too,  as  we  saw  in  our 
chapter  on  the  moral  criterion,  plaNS  a  very  large  part 
in  the  drawing  of  our  moral  conclusions.  For  instance, 
we  have  often  to  discover  the  effect  of  a  course  of 
action  on  the  race,  before  we  can  tell  whether  it  is 
natural.  And  if  the  race  be  unsettled  and  without 
traditions,  as  is  for  the  most  part  the  case  with  savages, 
such  effects  as  these  are  hot  easily  calculated.  Ethically, 
therefore,  we  see  no  reason  why  we  should  not  own  up 
to  very  large  differences  in  moral  codes,  for,  even  though 
morals  are  natural,  there  is  great  room  for  differences  in 
human  belief. 

in  an  incredibly  short  space  of  time,  as  real  as  it  is  to  us  ;  and  her 
moral  ideas  were  the  most  refined  and  intense.  Later  in  life,  meeting 
with  some  mishap  and  fearing  tliat  she  was  going  to  die  of  hunger, 
she  uttered  the  prayer  which  Kauber  quotes  for  us,  and  which  for 
simple  beauty  could  scarcely  be  surpassed.  "  Oh  God,  why  didst 
Thou  take  me  out  of  the  solitude  where  1  had  plenty  to  eat,  in  order 
now  to  let  me  die  of  hunger.  But  Thou  canst  not  let  me  die,"  etc. 
The  delicacy  of  the  nu)ral  feeling  exlubited  in  this  prayer  could  not 
be  possible  to  one  who  until  ten  years  of  age  had  lived  without  moral 
training  of  any  kintl,  unless  the  moral  law  when  once  it  is  put  before 
the  mind  comes  home  to  it  with  that  fulness  and  reality  that  attaches 
only  to  a  system  of  real  objective  natural  truth. 


ON  SYNDERESIS  571 

APPENDIX 

Ethicians  have  made  various  attempts  to  reconcile  the 
variation  of  moral  codes  amongst  different  races  with  the 
theory  of  natural  moral  perceptions.  Of  these  we  shall 
here  quote  two,*  one,  the  theory  of  "formal  identity  "  with 
differences  of  matter,  the  other,  the  theory  of  "  kernal  identity  " 
with  differences  in  the  stage  of  development  attained.  Pro- 
fessor Kittel,  to  whom  Elsenhans  attributes  the  first  theory 
(it  really  is  the  same  as  Fichte's  theory  of  Conscience),  con- 
tends that  the  form  of  conscience  is  given  in  the  law — "  The 
good  is  to  be  done  " — the  matter  in  the  determination  of 
what  is  good.  On  the  former  he  says  all  are  agreed,  on  the 
latter  we  differ.  The  only  unity  that  is  necessary  for  natural 
law  is  that  of  form,  the  supplying  of  which  is  the  essential 
function  of  Conscience. 

Now,  this  theory  we  cannot  accept.  In  the  first  place,  it 
is  not  true  that  the  matter  of  conscience  can  so  vary  as  to 
leave  no  common  element  in  our  moral  beliefs  as  individuals 
or  as  races.  In  the  second  place,  there  is  no  such  thing  as  a 
distinction  of  form  and  matter  in  moral  truths.  The  principle 
that  "  the  good  is  to  be  done  "  is  as  much  a  part  of  the  matter 
of  conscience  as  the  principle  that  "  murder  is  to  be  avoided." 
Thirdly,  Conscience  prescribes  the  whole  law,  and  not  merely 
the  abstract  law  of  doing  the  good. 

The  second  theory  is  that  adopted  by  Dr.  Elsenhans 
himself.  He  argues  that  the  development  of  a  natural 
organism  may  vary  in  any  of  three  ways — (i)  Some  forms 
may  remain  latent  in  one  organism  which  in  others  are 
developed  ;  (2)  one  organism  may  be  in  point  of  development 
just  a  stage  or  a  period  in  advance  of  the  other,  the  two  lines 
of  development  being  otherwise  the  same  ;  (3)  two  organisms 
with  the  same  original  kernel  of  powers  may  develop  in 
response  to  two  different  sets  of  stimuli  from  environment, 
so  that  the  result  attained  must  be  different  in  each  case. 
It  is  in  this  third  way  that  he  explains  the  permanence  and 
variability  of  the  moral  conscience.  Originally,  he  tells  us, 
the  content  of  Conscience  is  the  same  for  all.  But  it  de- 
velops differently  in  response  to  differences  of  environment. 

We  cannot,  however,  subscribe  to  Dr.  Elsenhans'  interest- 
ing explanation  because  we  do  not  regard  conscience  as  an 
original  organism  that  develops  from  within  in  response  to 
stimuli.  Conscience  is  nothing  more  than  the  ordinary 
intellectual  faculty  which  is  moved  to  know  by  objective 

*  Taken  from  Elsenhans'  "  Wcsen  und  Entstehung  des  Gewisseas. 


572  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

things  and  relations,  and  to  such  a  faculty  the  analogy  of 
the  budding  flower  or  growing  organism  could  not  apply. 
Secondly,  we  do  not  admit  innate  moral  truths,  which  on 
Dr.  Elsenhans'  theory  are  an  absolute  necessity.  Thirdly, 
in  no  environment  could  the  human  mind  be  without  some 
sense  of  the  primary  moral  principles.  Fourthly,  environ- 
ment does  not  justify  all  differences  of  moral  judgments. 
Some  judgments  are  simply  false  and  opposed  to  the  per- 
manent natural  law,  which  is  to  a  large  extent  quite  inde- 
pendent of  the  requirements  of  environment. 


CHAPTER  XVII 

ON    THE    PROPERTIES    OR   ESSENTIAL   CONSE- 
QUENCES OF  MORALITY 

Every    moral    act    has    three    properties    or    essential 
consequences  : — 

(i)  Rectitude,  or  direction  of  the  will  of  the  agent  to 
the  ultimate  end,  or  its  opposite — "  wrongfulness." 

(2)  Imputability*  or  relation  of  ownership  between  a 
man  and  his  act,  and  the  consequent  attributing  of  it 
in  praise  or  blame  to  him  as  cause. 

(3)  Merit,  or  claim  to  retribution  according  to  Justice, 
and  its  opposite — Demerit. 

(i)  Of  Rectitude.  It  will  not  be  necessary  at  this 
point  to  speak  at  any  length  of  rectitude  and  wrongful- 
ness. Rectitude  or  rightness  adds  something  to  mere 
goodness  as  sin  adds  something  to  mere  evil.  Any 
perfection  in  an  object  is  good  and  any  privation  of  a 
good  in  anything — that  is,  any  want  of  that  perfection 
which  is  naturally  due  to  a  thing — is  evil.  But  "  recti- 
tude "  emphasises  the  fact  that  a  thing  which  is 
ordained  to  a  certain  end  moves  to  the  attainment  of 
that  end,t  whereas  wrongfulness  means  that  something 
which  is  ordained  to  a  certain  end  fails  to  move  towards 
its  attainment.  Now,  direction  to  a  given  end  always 
implies  a  rule  of  action,  which  rule  of  action  in  material 
things  is  their  own  nature.  But  man  is  directed  by 
Reason  his  rule  of  direction  being  proximately  his  own 
Reason,  and  ultimately  the  eternal  law.  A  right  action, 
therefore,  is  one  that  follows  the  law  of  human  Reason 
and  the  Eternal  law.  A  wrong  action  or  a  sin  is  one 
which  violates  these  laws. 

*  The  word  "  imputability  "  is  used  indiflPerently  of  bad  and  good 
acts.     "  Responsibility  "  is  most  often  used  of  bad  acts  only. 

t  This  in  addition  to  the  conception  of  good  as  fulness  of  being. 

573 


574  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(2)  Imputahility  and  responsibility  depend  on  owner- 
ship. He  who  produces  an  act  or  is  the  principal 
cause  of  it  owns  it,  and,  therefore,  an  act  is  imputable 
to  the  agent  who  produces  or  is  the  principal  cause  of 
it.  But  we  have  already  seen  *  that  to  be  free  and 
to  be  (principal)  cause  of  an  act  are  one  and  the  same 
thing.  Therefore,  the  ground  and  intrinsic  cause  of 
imputahility  is  freedom.  Freedom  has  thus  a  more 
direct  connection  with  imputahility  than  with  moral 
goodness.  For  of  morality  it  is  only  the  primary  con- 
dition, whereas  of  imputahility  it  is  the  ground  or 
intrinsic  cause.  Since,  however,  freedom  has  been 
already  sufficiently  considered  in  another  chapter  it 
will  not  be  necessary  at  this  point  to  enter  into  any 
formal  discussion  on  the  nature  either  of  imputahility 
or  of  responsibility. 

(3)  The  third  property  of  morality  will  require  fuller 
and  more  careful  consideration.  We  shall  treat  {a)  of 
Merit,  {b)  of  Demerit. 

(fl)  Of  Merit 

(i)  Merit  is  the  right  in  justice  to  retribution  for 
some  good  bestowed  on  another.  All  merit  is  a  relation 
of  justice,  and  it  is  based  on  the  fact  that  good  is  done 
to  another,  which  good  must  in  some  way  be  repaid. 
Now,  we  broadly  distinguish  between  three  grades  of 
justice  according  to  the  strictness  of  the  law  from 
which  the  relation  of  justice  springs.  Sometimes  an 
act  is  due  according  to  perfect  f  justice,  and  excludes 
every  element  of  grace  or  favour.  Sometimes  it  is 
due  in  perfect  justice,  but  presupposes  a  grace  or  favour 
of  some  sort,  through  which  the  relation  of  justice  arises. 
Sometimes  it  is  due  according  to  imperfect  justice  only. 
From  these  three  grades  of  justice  arise  three  classes  of 

•  Page  1 79. 

t  The  full  explanation  of  these  terms — perfect  and  imperfect 
Justice — is  reservetl  for  our  rliapler  on  Kinhls.  The  examjilis  given 
in  the  text  will  explain  the  terms  sulliciciit ly  for  present  purposes. 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  575 

merit — (i)  Merit  de  condigno  ex  rigore  justitiae.     (2)  Merit 
de  condigno  ex  condignitatc.     (3)  Merit  de  congruo. 

Merit  de  condigno  ex  rigore  justitiae. — This  kind  of 
merit  excludes  all  grace  or  favour,  and,  as  the  name 
itself  signifies,  it  arises  from  strict  law,  and  binds  in 
strict  justice.  Thus,  to  merit  that  a  man  fulfils  his 
side  of  contracts  by  our  fulfilling  our  own  side  is  to 
merit  de  condigno  ex  rigore  justitiae.  It  is  a  relation 
that  arises  out  of  the  purest  bargaining  between  buyer 
and  seller,  and  there  is  manifestly  no  element  in  it  of 
grace,  favour  or  liberality  of  any  sort.  It  binds  vi 
operis,  which  means  that  we  can  point  to  the  work 
done,  and  on  the  ground  of  that  work  can  press  our 
claim  to  retribution  before  the  strictest  legal  tribunal. 

Merit  de  condigno  ex  condignitate  also  binds  in  strict 
justice  and  vi  operis,  but  there  is  in  it  some  element  of 
grace  or  favour.  Thus,  if  I  publicly  guarantee  that 
he  who  wins  a  certain  race  will  receive  a  reward  of  a 
hundred  pounds,  and  if  in  the  hope  of  that  reward 
men  enter  for  the  prize,  he  who  wins  the  race  and  fulfils 
all  the  conditions  of  the  race  merits  the  reward  pro- 
mised. He  merits,  too,  according  to  strict  justice  and 
vi  operis — that  is,  he  can  make  good  his  claim  to  reward 
by  pointing  to  the  work  he  has  done,  and  need  make 
no  appeal  to  my  liberality  or  goodness  when  defending 
his  claim.     He  has  a  right  in  law  to  his  reward. 

Yet  there  is  in  this  case  some  element  of  grace  and 
liberality  which  did  not  obtain  in  the  case  of  merit  ex 
rigore  justitiae,  for  in  the  case  of  the  promise  it  is  alto- 
gether through  my  generosity  that  the  work  done 
entitles  a  man  to  reward,  and  it  is  this  element  of 
graciousness  and  favour  that  distinguishes  this  second 
kind  of  merit  from  merit  de  rigore  justitiae.  (It  is  in 
this  second  way  principally  that  a  man  is  said  to  merit 
with  God.  For  in  His  bounty  God  has  promised  to 
reward  certain  of  our  acts  which  of  themselves  could 
give  us  no  claim  to  reward.  Yet  the  promise  once 
made.  He  is  bound  {debet  Sibi)  to  its  fulfilment.) 


576  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Merit  de  congrno  binds  according  to  imperfect  justice 
only.  An  example  of  this  third  kind  of  merit  will  best 
explain  its  meaning.  Suppose  that  I,  a  rich  man,  make 
a  present  of  some  money  to  a  poor  man,  he  is  not 
bound  in  strict  justice  to  return  this  money,  for  it  is 
given  as  a  present,  and  no  stipulation  has  been  made 
as  to  its  return.  If,  however,  the  poor  man  should 
later  become  rich,  and  I  should  be  reduced  to  poverty 
he  is  bound  in  such  circumstances  to  help  me  according 
to  my  w^ants.  This  obligation,  however,  is  not  one  of 
strict  justice,  but  only  of  friendship  and  gratitude  and 
humanity,  which,  as  we  shall  see  in  the  following  chapter, 
are  allied  virtues  to  justice,  and  do  not  bind  by  a  strict 
law  of  justice.  In  such  cases  my  former  kindness  is 
not  a  sufficient  title  to  present  reward,  and  I  have  to 
appeal  to  other  considerations  besides  the  work  I  have 
done  in  claiming  reward.  I  merit  in  friendship,  not 
vi  operis. 

Sometimes  merit  de  congruo  arises  even  in  the  case 
of  contracts,  but  always  in  connection  with  something 
that  is  not  itself  strictly  contracted  for.  Thus,  suppose 
that  I  engage  to  work  for  a  certain  number  of  hours  a 
day  and  to  receive  in  payment  a  certain  sum,  and 
suppose  that  for  many  years  I  work  faithfully  for  my 
master,  never  missing  an  hour,  taking  a  more  than 
ordinary  interest  in  my  master's  business,  and  pushing 
it  on  in  every  way  in  my  power — in  this  c^se  I  certainly 
merit  something  more  than  the  stipulated  wages.  For 
though  I  have  technically  done  no  more  than  I  con- 
tracted to  do,  I  have  done  more  than  I  really 
contracted  to  do,  and  should  be  rewarded  accordingly. 
For  whatever  may  be  the  express  terms  of  a  contract, 
a  man  really  contracts  to  work  in  a  human  way  only, 
not  in  a  perfect  way,  and  every  human  thing  is  subject 
to  imperfection ;  and,  therefore,  if  a  man  works  per- 
fectly— that  is  in  more  than  a  human  way — he  has 
done  more  for  his  master  than  he  has  really  contracted 
for,  he  has  done  a  work  which  it  would  not  be  gracious 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  577 

in  a  master  to  leave  unrecognised.  In  strict  justice 
such  a  man  has  no  claim  to  recognition ;  he  has  no 
claim  vi  operis.  He  cannot  point  to  his  work  and 
claim  reward  at  law  on  account  of  it  alone,  because  the 
strict  terms  of  the  contract  were  that  he  should  do  all 
that  he  actually  has  done.  And  so  a  master  cannot 
be  strictly  called  unjust  if  he  does  not  give  more  than 
the  stipulated  wages  in  this  case.  But,  at  the  same 
time,  the  subject  has  really  done  more  than  he  bar- 
gained to  do  in  his  contract,  as  the  world  understands 
contracts,  and  it  will  be  an  unfriendly  and  an  ungrateful 
thing  to  allow  this  extra  labour  to  go  unrequited. 

It  may  be  asked,  however,  what  is  the  practical 
effect  of  this  kind  of  merit  ?  For  it  cannot,  as  we  have 
said,  be  pressed  at  law.  Neither  can  it  be  said  to 
create  a  strict  moral  obligation,  since  the  master  who 
pays  the  bare  week's  wages  has  done  all  that  his  con- 
tract binds  him  under  sin  to  do.  How,  then,  can  we 
speak  of  merit  of  the  kind  described  as  real  merit, 
effective  merit,  merit  that  is  of  use  to  a  man  ?  The 
answer  is  :  Though  merit  of  this  kind  does  not  impose 
a  strict  obligation  of  reward,  yet  it  loads  the  dice  in  our 
favour,  for  it  gives  us  some  title  to  reward — the  title 
not  of  a  strict  or  perfect  right  but  of  imperfect  right ; 
and  in  most  cases  the  result  of  such  imperfect  right  is 
that  we  probably  shall  get  our  reward.  For  most 
masters  are  grateful,  and  consequently  most  masters 
would  have  to  steel  their  hearts  in  order  to  resist  the 
claims  of  faithful  servants  to  some  suitable  reward. 
Merit  de  congruo  is,  therefore,  a  reality  which  has  its 
effect  in  actual  life,  and,  therefore,  it  has  a  right  to  be 
considered  in  a  work  on  Ethics. 


(2)    CONDITIONS   OF  MERIT 

Merit  requires  (i)  that  our  act  be  free,  for  it  is  a 
relation  of  justice  and,  therefore,  a  moral  or  human  and 
free  relation,  (2)  that  that  which  we  merit  be  not  already 

Vol.  1—37 


578  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

due  to  us  on  another  score,*  (3)  that  our  act  must  do 
good  to  him  with  whom  we  merit. 

(3)  WITH   WHOM   CAN   WE   MERIT  ? 

(i)  We  merit  with  other  men  who  benefit  by  our 
acts,  which  is  merit  in  its  strictest  sense,  for  all  merit 
is  a  relation  of  justice,  and  justice,  properly  speaking, 
obtains  only  between  equals, 

(2)  We  can  merit  with  society,  and  in  two  ways. 
First,  we  merit  with  society  by  every  good  that  we  do 
to  individual  men  (even  to  ourselves),  for  that  which 
does  good  to  the  part  benefits  also  the  whole  of  which 
it  is  a  part.  Secondly,  we  can  merit  with  society  by 
the  good  which  we  do  to  society  itself  directly. 

(3)  We  can  merit  with  God,  because  a  good  act  is 
referred  to  God  as  our  final  end,  and  redounds  to  God's 
honour — which  is  a  cause  of  merit.  A  bad  act  is  to 
His  dishonour,  and,  therefore.  He  can  punish  us  for  it. 
Again,  any  act  that  merits  with  society  merits  with 
God,  who  is  its  Supreme  Ruler.  But  since  there  can 
be  no  strict  right  against  God,  no  man  can  merit  with 
God  ex  rigorc  justitiae.  But  we  can  merit  with  Him 
according  to  the  two  aspects  of  merit  called  respectively 
ex  condignitate  and  de  congruo. 

(4)  SOME  ERRONEOUS  VIEWS   ON   MERIT 

The  views  which  we  shall  here  discuss  are  three  : — 

(a)  Leslie  Stephen's  theory  that  merit  implies  effort, 
and  therefore  an  element  of  disagreeableness  to  ourselves 
in  the  work  that  we  do. 

{(i)  The  same  author's  contention  that  merit  attaches 
only  to  works  of  supererogation. 

(y)  The  theory  of  Martineau  and  Shaftesbury  that 
merit  and  virtue  arc  in  inverse  ratio. 

♦  Only  in  this  sense  can  we  accept  the  condition  mentioned  by 
some  Scholastic  writers  that  a  meritorious  act  must  not  be  the  result 
of  contract.  Curiously  enough  Hobbes  expresses  the  view  that  all 
merit  requires  contract. 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  579 

(a)  Every  action  implies  some  effort,*  and  since  merit 
attaches  to  action  only,  merit  necessarily  supposes  some 
degree  of  effort.  But  the  theory  of  Leslie  Stephen  is 
that  merit  implies  the  overcoming  of  an  opposing 
desire,  and  that  it,  therefore,  implies  a  special  degree 
of  effort  which  is  not  required  for  action  as  such.  It 
is  to  this  theory  that  we  here  take  exception.  Merit 
is  a  relation  of  justice,  and  as  a  man  must  pay  me  for 
goods  that  I  sell  him,  whether  the  selling  of  these  goods 
be  disagreeable  or  not,  so  merit  depends  on  a  good 
done  to  another,  and  it  arises  whether  the  doing  of  such 
good  is  disagreeable  and  requires  effort  or  is  agreeable 
and  does  not  require  effort. 

But  though  effort  in  the  sense  explained  is  not 
required  for  merit,  it  is  nevertheless  a  criterion  of 
degree  of  merit.  To  do  a  good  act  which  is  disagree- 
able to  ourselves  is  more  meritorious  ceteris  paribus 
than  to  do  one  which  is  agreeable,  for  in  doing  a  dis- 
agreeable thing  there  is  greater  will-activity — there  is 
the  doing  of  the  good  act  and  the  overcoming  of  an 
opposed  desire — and  greater  will-activity  merits  more 
than  less  will-activity,  just  as  two  actions  merit  more 
than  one.  Effort,  then,  though  not  an  essential  of 
merit,  can  be  a  criterion  of  degree  in  merit. 

{(i)  Another  erroneous  theory  is  that  of  Leslie 
Stephen,  that  merit  belongs  exclusively  to  works  of 
supererogation,  t  and  that  consequently  acts  which 
to-day  are  meritorious  because  there  is  no  moral  neces- 
sity to  do  them,  may  in  a  thousand  years  be  devoid  of 
merit  since  in  the  meantime  they  may  become  our 
duty.  Now,  this  principle  does  not  hold  true  always. 
The  man  who  wins  a  race  has  merited  the  prize,  even 


*  Sidgwick  remarks  that,  according  to  this  theory,  were  there  no 
free  will  in  the  world  all  acts  would  be  equally  meritorious,  since  if 
there  were  no  free  will  there  could  be  no  effort. 

t  Martineau  distinguishes  merit  and  desert.  The  former  implies 
that  the  work  done  is  one  of  supererogation.  The  latter  makes  no 
such  implication.  Kant  maintains  that  merit  attaches  to  the  fulfilment 
of  imperfect,  not  of  perfect  obligations. 


58o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

though  his  master  compelled  him  to  enter  for  the  race, 
thereby  making  the  race  a  duty  ;  consequently,  merit 
may  attach  to  works  which  are  not  of  supererogation. 
But  in  many  cases  of  merit  de  congruo  this  principle 
does  apply. 

(y)  The  third  theory  that  merit  and  virtue  are  in 
inverse  ratio  is  connected  as  a  result  with  the  theory 
that  merit  implies  effort.*  Aristotle  says  that  to  the 
truly  virtuous  man  virtue  is  necessarily  pleasant,  from 
which  some  modern  ethicians  conclude  that  the  more 
virtuous  a  man  is  the  less  effort  he  has  to  make  in 
order  to  do  good,  and,  therefore,  the  less  the  merit 
attaching  to  his  acts. 

Now,  Aristotle's  principle  does  not  justify  this  con- 
clusion. For  (a)  even  though  virtue  makes  good  action 
easy,  still  virtue  itself  is  often  acquired  with  difficulty, 
and  hence  the  virtuous  man  may  have  had  to  make 
efforts  to  be  good.f  (6)  In  estimating  merit  regard 
must  be  had,  not  merely  to  the  effort  used,  but  to  the 
good  will  of  him  who  does  the  good  act,  it  being  possible, 
for  instance,  that  a  strong  man  who  lifts  a  fainting 
person  in  the  street  may  merit  as  much  as  the  weak  man 

♦  Leslie  Stephen  compares  virtue  to  value  in  use  or  intrinsic  value 
which  is  constant,  merit  to  value  in  exchange,  which  is  subject  to 
variation. 

t  This  point  recalls  Prof.  Dewey's  treatment  of  an  analogous 
question — namely,  how  we  are  to  reconcile  the  theory  that  to  the 
virtuous  man  virtue  is  easy  with  the  apparently  opposed  view  that 
virtue  supposes  struggle,  that  virtue  is  the  moral  disposition  in  the 
struggle  with  evil.  Dewey's  attempt  at  reconciliation  consists  in 
explaining  that  the  virtuous  man  is  one  who  has  had  his  fights,  and 
who  now  finds  virtue  easy  as  a  consequence  of  his  fights. 

Prof.  Simmel  gives  a  similar  solution  of  the  same  difficulty,  and 
illustrates  his  theory  by  an  example  taken  from  the  art  of  Music.  We 
admire,  he  tells  us,  the  virtuoso  who  plays  without  Music,  on  account 
of  two  things — the  case  with  which  he  plays  a  difficult  piece  and  the 
evident  fact  that  his  present  proficiency  is  the  result  of  much  past 
labour. 

On  this  analogy  with  which  Simmel  illustrates  his  theory  of  virtue 
and  merit,  we  would  remark  that  though  we  admire  the  present  pro- 
ficiency of  the  artist,  and  tliough  we  regard  that  proficiency  as  a  proof 
of  high  artistic  ability,  we  do  not  regard  his  supposed  long  hours  of 
labour  as  evidence  of  high  ability.  Were  we  sure  that  his  present 
proficiency  was  secured  without  labour,  we  should  admire  his  ability 
all  the  more. 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  581 

who  does  the  same  ;  for  the  strong  man  migh^  be  quite 
as  wilHng  to  give  the  same  help  that  he  now  gives  even 
if  it  cost  him  more  than  it  now  does.  Consequently,  it 
is  not  fair  to  the  virtuous  man  to  belittle  the  merits  of 
his  acts  because  of  his  finding  it  easy  to  do  good.  The 
virtuous  man  does  good,  not  because  he  finds  it  easy, 
but  because  it  is  good,  and  he  might  still  do  the  good 
even  though  he  found  the  "  good  "  difficult. 

Hence,  this  principle  of  inverse  ratio  is  not  absolutely 
true.  But  there  is  in  it  a  certain  element  of  truth  that 
must  be  taken  into  account  in  estimating  the  merit  of 
actions.  Of  two  men,  one  of  whom  is  born  with  a 
tendency  to  drink,  the  other  without  such  tendency, 
the  former  generally  merits  more  through  his  subse- 
quent sobriety  than  the  latter,  because  his  sobriety 
costs  more.*  In  this  sense  the  less  virtuous  man  may 
merit  more. 

The  theory  already  mentioned  that  merit  implies 
effort  and  struggle  introduces  us  to  another  kindred 
theory,  that  "  7noral  good  always  implies  struggle  " — a 
view  of  moral  goodness  which  we  may  be  allowed  to 
criticise  briefly  here,  though  its  bearing  on  the  question 
of  merit  is  indirect  and  remote. 

In  explanation  and  defence  of  this  theory  that  virtue 
always  implies  struggle  against  certain  opposing  ten- 
dencies. Professor  Royce  speaks  ironically  of  the  school- 
master who  considered  that  he  was  teaching  his  poor 
pupils  virtue  when  he  exhorted  them  not  to  cherish  in 
their  breasts  the  ambitious  passions  of  an  Alexander 
and  other  great  men  of  history  whom  there  was  no 
possibility  that  they  should  ever  imitate,  and  whose 
ambitions,  therefore,  it  was  quite  easy  for  them  to  avoid. 
True  virtue,  he  says,  supposes  struggle  and  effort,  a 
theory  which  he  illustrates  by  examples  from  the 
Science  of  Biology  which  represent  life  as  maintaining 
itself  by   the   struggle   of  opposing   elements.     "  Every 

*  We  are  here  speaking  of  merit  in  the  natural  order  only.  The 
question  of  supernatural  merit  would  be  treated  quite  differently  by  us. 


582  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

function,"  he  writes,  "  depends  upon  a  corresponding 
deficiency."  "  Living  ...  is  constant  dying."  His 
conclusion  is  that  moral  good  must  consist  in  the  over- 
coming of  its  opposite,  which  is  the  temptation  to  evil. 
To  the  evident  objection  that  his  illustration  from 
Biology  proves  too  much,  since  if  good  is  the  union  of 
opposites  then  no  man  could  be  actually  good  without 
committing  actual  evil,  Professor  Royce  replies  that 
"  active  disease  is  no  part  of  the  life  of  a  healthy 
organism,"  and  that,  so,  actual  evil  is  not  necessary 
to  good,  but  that  yet  the  warding-off  of  possible  evil 
is  not  only  compatible  with  "  good,"  but  is  a  part  of 
and  necessary  to  "  good." 

Our  criticism  of  this  theory — the  theory  that  as  life 
and  health  consist  in  overcoming  disease,  so  moral 
goodness  consists  in  the  struggle  against  evil — is  that 
not  only  is  active  disease  no  part  of  a  healthy  organism, 
but  a  healthy  organism  may  exist  without  experiencing 
even  the  tendency  to  disease,  and  consequently  if  the 
analogy  of  Ethics  with  Biology  is  to  be  maintained, 
moral  good  does  not  necessarily  imply  any  tendency 
to  or  struggle  with  evil.  The  analogy  of  inoculation  is 
sometimes  used  in  support  of  the  theory  we  are  now 
considering.  But  applied  to  Ethics  such  an  analogy 
is  misleading  and  erroneous.  No  doubt  it  is  a  good 
thing  to  innoculate  bodies,  and  thus  produce  artificially 
a  struggle  with  disease  in  order  that  the  body  may  be 
able  to  resist  this  same  disease  more  effectively  if  it 
should  appear  later.  But  were  we  sure  that  disease 
would  not  appear  later  we  should  not  inoculate  the 
body,  and  we  should  not  consider  it  necessary  or  even 
useful  to  do  so.  So  a  person  may  be  highly  moral 
who  has  had  no  struggle  with  evil,  for  evil  is  no  neces- 
sary part  of  our  moral  constitution.  Hence,  struggle 
is  not  an  essential  of  moral  goodness.  We  admit,  how- 
ever, and  this  is  the  only  element  of  truth  in  Professor 
Royce's  theory,  that  if  a  man  were  thrown  into  the 
necessity    of    struggling    against    evil    tendencies,    and 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  583 

were  successful  in  his  struggle,  he  will,  as  a  rule,  be  all 
the  stronger  and  more  virtuous  for  his  victory. 

But  this  theory  has  also  a  practical  bearing  which 
we  must  consider.  Some  philosophers  have  actually 
taught  that  since  there  can  be  no  virtue  without  risk 
and  struggle  against  temptation,  it  is  irrational  to  shun 
the  risk  and  the  temptation.  Milton's  diatribe  against 
what  he  calls  "cloistered  virtue"*  is  an  example  of 
such  teaching.  Professor  Royce's  attack  on  that  virtue 
as  "  cheap  "  which  has  never  been  in  danger  shows  a 
similar  tendency. 

Now,  this  teaching  is  both  illogical  and  dangerous. 
It  is  illogical  because  it  supposes  that  goodness  has 
not  a  value  in  itself,  that  the  whole  value  of  good 
action  consists  in  the  overcoming  of  evil.  This  we 
cannot  allow.  Virtue  has  a  value  all  its  own,  not  a 
money  value  indeed,  but  a  moral  value — a  value  that 
is  very  much  higher  than  that  of  riches.  And  having 
a  value  in  itself  it  should  not  be  called  "  cheap,"  because 
it  has  not  been  in  contact  with  evil.  Nowhere  in  his 
work  on  Morals  does*  Professor  Royce  speak  of  that 
health  of  body  as  "cheap  "  which  has  never  been  in 
the  vicinity  of  sickness,  nor  of  those  riches  as  "  cheap  " 
which  have  never  been  nigh  to  being  lost.  Why  ? 
Because  these  things  are  valuable  in  themselves.  Nc 
sensible  person  would  think  of  frequenting  unsanitary 
districts  in  order  to  incur  the  danger  of  fever,  nor  drink 
intoxicating  liquors  in  order  to  become  proof  against 
intemperance,  nor  run  grave  risks  of  disfigurement  in 
order  to  enhance  a  good  appearance.  For  such  things 
are  valued  on  their  own  account,  which  is  the  very 
reason  why  they  are  so  carefully  guarded  from  danger. 
How  then  can  it  be  irrational  to  shun  temptations  to 
evil,  or  why  should  virtue  be  derided  because  it  has  not 
been  in  contact  with  evil  ?  We  repeat — virtue  has  a 
value  on  its  own  account,  as  much  so  as  the  beautiful 
face  or  bodily  health,  and  it  should  be  guarded  from 

*  In  his  "  Arcopagitica." 


584  THE  SCIENCE  OF   ETHICS 

temptation  or  danger  as  far  as  is  compatible  with  our 
duties  to  God  and  to  humanity,  just  as  anything  of 
great  price  would  be. 

This  theory  is  also,  as  we  said,  a  dangerous  theory. 
For  it  is  a  dangerous  thing  to  set  a  value  on  temptation 
in  any  shape  or  form.  Temptation,  even  if  overcome, 
does  not  always  add  to  our  moral  strength.  If  tempta- 
tion were  necessarily  a  source  of  strength,  then  the 
longer  a  temptation  continues  and  is  resisted  the  easier 
we  should  find  it  to  overcome  temptation.  But  we 
know  that  the  opposite  is  the  case.  The  man  who 
resists  for  half  an  hour  may  fail  in  the  end  through 
"  moral  exhaustion  "  ;  and  from  this  we  may  rightly 
conclude  that  temptation,  even  resisted,  is  not,  as  such, 
a  source  of  moral  strength.  Consequently  it  ought  not 
be  represented  as  necessary  to  virtue. 

But  temptation  overcome,  if  it  is  not  necessary  to 
virtue  or  moral  goodness,  is  always  a  title  to  greater 
merit,  a  fact  which  may  serve  as  an  excuse  for  intro- 
ducing the  question  of  '  temptation  and  virtue  '  into  the 
present  chapter. 

(&)  On  Demerit  and  Punishment 

We  can  best  understand  the  general  theory  of  pun- 
ishment by  considering  a  special  case.  When  a  man 
steals  money  justice  requires  that  what  is  taken  should 
be  restored  ;  also  that  reparation  be  made  for  any  loss 
sustained  by  the  owner.  This  is  the  ordinary  con- 
ception of  restitution  to  which,  all  are  agreed,  the  thief 
is  bound  in  strict  duty.  But  the  liabilities  created  by 
an  act  of  stealing  go  farther  still.  Stealing  is  not 
merely  an  injustice  against  my  neighbour ;  it  is  also 
a  violation  of  law  and  of  the  order  established  by  law ; 
it  is  not  merely  an  injury  but  a  crime  and  a  sin  also, 
and  all  are  agreed  that  through  its  criminal  character 
stealing  renders  a  man  liable  to  an  additional  penalty 
over  and  above  that  of  restitution  to  the  individual. 
It  is  this  additional  penalty  with  which  the  law  visits 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  585 

a  criminal  act  that  is  spoken  of  as  punishment.  Not 
only  stealing  but  every  violation  of  law  renders  a  man 
liable  to  punishment  ;  punishment  is  a  natural  and 
invariable  consequence  of  wrong-doing.  The  various 
kinds  of  punishment  and  also  its  ground  and  reason  are 
the  special  subject  matter  of  the  present  section. 

Punishment  is  of  two  kinds — prospective  and  retro- 
spective. Prospective  punishment  is  punishment  in- 
flicted on  account  of  the  good  effect  which  it  produces 
either  on  the  offender  or  on  society  at  large.  As  directed 
to  the  improvement  of  the  offender  it  is  spoken  of  as 
emendatory  ;  as  directed  to  the  prevention  of  crime  in 
society  at  large  it  is  known  as  deterrent.  Retrospective 
punishment  or  punishment  inflicted  as  reparation  for, 
or  in  vindication  of  a  law  which  has  been  violated,  is 
spoken  of  as  retributive. 

Now  it  will  not  be  necessary  to  refer  at  an}^  length 
ot  the  right  of  rulers  to  inflict  emendatory  or  deterrent 
punishment.  Rulers  are  charged  with  seeking  the  good 
of  their  subjects  in  every  act  of  government,  and  granted 
that  a  man  has  put  himself  in  the  power  of  the  law  by 
crime  it  is  the  right  and  even  the  duty  of  the  ruler  to 
give  proper  consideration  to  this  end  ;  and  therefore 
he  may  choose  such  a  form  of  punishment  as  will  at 
once  vindicate  the  majesty  of  the  law  and  at  the  same 
time  help  to  improve  the  delinquent  and  to  deter  others 
from  crime.  Indeed  in  the  infliction  of  punishment  an 
earthly  ruler  ought  to  make  the  two  latter  ends  his 
chief  consideration  ;  for  though,  as  we  shall  show  in 
a  moment,  the  retributive  element  is  always  present, 
even  where  punishment  is  inflicted  by  the  State,  still 
the  chief  function  of  an  earthly  ruler  continues  alwaj's 
to  be  the  promotion  of  the  good  of  his  subjects  ;  it  is 
for  this  that  communities  form  into  States  and  subject 
themselves  to  the  restrictions  imposed  by  law.  In  in- 
flicting punishment,  therefore,  a  ruler  should  chiefly  aim 
at  the  interest  of  his  subjects.  He  may  even,  if  the  good 
of  the  offender  and  of  society  requires,  dispense  with 


586  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

punishment  altogether  in  particular  cases,  leaving  it  to 
the  Supreme  Judge  and  Lawgiver  to  exact  in  His  own 
way  whatever  is  necessary  by  way  of  vindication  or 
retribution.* 

Let  us  now  consider  the  question  of  retj;ibutiye  punish- 
ment.    We   shall    first    (a)    quote    a   passage   from    St. 
Thornas  giving   a   far-reaching   analysis  of  what   retri- 
butive  punishment    is :     then    {b)    we   shall   quote   his 
doctrine    on    the    purpose    or    ground    of    retributive 
^punishment,     {a)  "  We  may  argue,"  he  writes,|  "  from 
'  the    domain    of    physical    nature    to    human    affairs, 
I  that   if  any  thing  rises  up  against   another,   it  suffers 

loss     from     that     other Passing     to     men     we 

find  that  each  one  has  a  natural  inclination  to  react 
on  (or  put  down)  one  who  rises  up  against  him.  But 
whatever  |  things  are  contained  in  any  order  are  in  a 
sense  one  in  relation  to  the  principle  governing  the 
order.  Hence  whatever  rises  up  against  an  order  is 
put  down  by  that  order  and  by  the  person  who  controls 
it.  But  sin  is  an  inordinate  act  and  therefore  whoever 
sins  acts  against  some  order  :  consequently  he  must 
be  put  down  or  degraded  by  that  order  ;  which  degra- 
dation is  punishment.  Hence  man  may  be  punished 
by  a  threefold  punishment  according  to  the  three  orders 
to  which  he  is  subject.  In  the  first  place  human  nature 
is  subject  to  the  order  of  human  reason  ;  secondly,  to 
the  order  of  human  government,  spiritual  of  temporal, 
political  or  economic  ;  thirdly,  to  the  general  order  of 
divine  government.  Each  of  these  orders  is  upset  by 
sin,  for  a  sinner  violates  the  order  of  reason,  of  human 
law,  and  of  divine  law  ;  hence  he  incurs  a  triple  penalty, 

•  "  Pocnac  praescntis  vitae,"  writes  St.  Thomas  ("  S.  Thcol.,"  II. 
II.,  Q.  LXVI.  Art.  0),  "  ntagis  sunt  medicinalcs  quam  rctributivae  ; 
retributi'i  enim  resorvatur  divino  Judicio  quod  est  secundum  voritatem 
in  peccantcs  "  {Italics  ours). 

t  .S'.  Jheol.  1.  11.,  Q.  LXXXVII.,  Art.  i. 

j  St,  Thomas  reasons  very  carefully  here.  Punishment  is  not  of 
the  nature  of  violence  done  to  a  thing  completely  outside  itself,  but  a 
reaction  of  the  whole  against  the  part.  It  is  therefore  a  reaction  which 
is  the  right  of  the  injured  organism  and  of  the  ruler  who  has  charge 
of  ilH  interests,  tlie  part  being  subject  to  the  whole.  The  argument 
goes  to  show  that  punishment  besides  being  natural  is  rightful  also. 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  5«7 

one  from  himself,  viz.,  remorse  of  conscience,  one  from 
men,  and  a  third  from  God." 

Retributive  punishment  is  therefore  the  natural  re- 
action of  law  and  ruler  upon  the  wrong-doer ;  it  is 
analogous  to  the  reaction  that  takes  place  upon  impact 
between  one  body  and  another,  and  to  the  natural 
reaction  of  self-defence  amongst  living  things.  "  Punish- 
ment," writes  Mr.  Bradley  is,  "  the  reaction  of  the 
moral  organism." 

[b]  In  his  Theory  of  Good  and  Evil,  Prof.  Rashdall, 
referring  to  the  doctrine  of  '  reaction,'  just  described, 
makes  the  admission  that  in  punishment  the  ruler  does 
rise  up  against  and  reacts  on  the  criminal.  "  I  don't 
deny,"  he  writes,  "  that  in  punishment  the  organism 
reacts  against  the  criminal  "  ;  but  he  goes  on  to  ask 
the  reasonable  question,  "  Why  ought  it  so  to  react  ? 
If  it  has  a  purpose  in  doing  so  let  that  purpose  be  ex- 
pressed." This  question  leads  us  to  the  ground  or  pur- 
pose of  retributive  punishment  which  again  is  clearly 
set  forth  by  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  following  Aristotle. 
The  ruler,  he  tells  us,  reacts  on  or  punishes  the  criminal 
in  order,  by  inflicting  loss,  to  restore  the  equilibrium  of 
welfare  or  happiness  which  the  criminal  has  unjustly 
disturbed  in  his  own  favour  and  at  the  expense  of  the 
rest  of  the  order  of  which  he  forms  a  part.  "  An  act  * 
of  sin,"  he  writes,*  "  makes  a  man  liable  to  punishment, 
because  he  has  transgressed  the  order  of  divine  justice, 
to  which  order  it  is  impossible  to  return  except  through 
a  certain  penal  compensation  which  restores  the  equi- 
librium of  justice.  So  that  he  who  has  indulged  hisj 
own  will  inordinately,  by  acting  against  the  Divine 
law  suffers  according  to  the  order  of  Divine  justice 
something  contrary  to  his  will.  And  the  same  is  ob-  \ 
served  in  the  case  of  injuries  done  to  men,  viz.,  by  the 
infliction  of  pain  the  equilibrium  of  justice  is  once  more  ' 
restored."     And    Aristotle    writes  if     "the   judge   tries' 

•  "  S.  Theol."  II.  II.,  Q.  LXXXVII.,  Art.  6. 
t  Nich.  Eth.,  v.,  4,  5. 


588  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  restore  equality  by  the  penalty  or  loss  which  he 
inflicts  on  the  offender,  subtracting  it  from  his  gain. 
For  in  such  cases,  though  the  terms  are  not  always 
quite  appropriate,  we  generally  talk  of  the  doer's  gain, 
and  the  sufferer's  loss."  *  Retributive  punishment 
therefore  restores  the  equilibrium  of  justice  by  the'\ 
infliction  of  an  evil  equivalent  to  a  man's  ill-gotten 
pleasure.  The  law  looks  equally  to  the  right  distri- 
bution of  pleasures  as  it  does  to  the  right  distribution 
of  material  goods  ;  indeed,  material  goods  are  only  a 
means  to  pleasure.  And  therefore  just  as  the  law  will 
insist  on  the  restoration  of  goods  unjustly  secured  at 
the  expense  of  another,  thereby  restoring  the  order  of 
justice,  so  also  it  insists  on  the  neutralising  by  pain 
of  pleasure  secured  at  the  expense  of  the  public  order ; 
and  that  is  what  crime  and  sin  are — the  inordinate 
indulging  of  our  own  will  or  the  inordinate  securing  of 
pleasure  at  the  expense  of  the  law  or  of  the  order  re- 
quired by  reason.  The  restoration  of  the  right  order  of 
pleasures  by  the  infliction  of  a  proportionate  pain  is 
what  we  mean  by  retributive  punishment.  What  each) 
sin  is  in  relation  to  justice  can  most  easily  be  seen 
from  the  idea  of  injustice  '  writ  large.'  Let  every  man 
be  free  to  violate  the  law  at  will,  and  order  and  justice 
would   be   completely   removed   from   the   world. |     So 

*  Kant  is  amongst  the  most  vigorous  defenders  of  the  retributive 
view.     See  Philosopliy  of  Right,  part  II.,  i. 

t  We  have  not  considered  the  question  of  the  measure  of  punishment 
or  what  the  degree  of  punishment  ought  to  be.  This  would  be  clearly 
very  difficult  to  determine  in  general  terms  in  the  case  of  crimes  against 
the  State.  In  regard  to  the  Divine  Law  evidently  the  most  serious 
part  of  punishment  is  the  loss  of  the  end  to  whicli  the  law  is  directed,  " 
i.e.  the  last  eml.  We  do  not  with  Butler  regard  punishment  as  equiva- 
lent to  all  the  consequences  of  crime,  as  being  hurt  follows  from  a  fall. 
But  such  consequences  as  are  decreed  by  the  Lawgiver  are  certainly 
sp  ial  in  character.  Most  terrible  of  ail,  and  indeed  most  natural, 
I  the  loss  of  our  final  end.  Just  as  a  tree  in  which  the  natural  require- 
ments arc  not  fullillcd  must  fail  to  reach  its  natural  end,  so  man  by 
violating  the  natural  law  misses  his  natural  end. 

We  may  l»e  permitted  to  refer  at  this  point  to  another  erroneous 
theory  of  retributive  punishment  be.side  that  of  Butler,  viz.,  the  theory 
of  IV-ntham  that  retributive  or  what  he  culls  vindictive  punishment 
is  "  the  pleasure  of  vengeance  to  the  party  injured."     Vengeance  and 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  589 

also  each  crime  and  sin  are  a  partial  disturbance  of  the 
right  order  of  enjoyable  things. 

From  all  this  it  will  be  understood  that  not  only  in 
the  Divine  order,  but  also  in  that  of  human  law,  though 
the  earthly  ruler  may  be  more  concerned  with  the 
future  welfare  of  his  subjects  than  with  the  restoring 
of  justice,  yet  the  retributive  element  is  first  and  funda- 
mental in  all.  For  emendatory  punishment  supposes 
crime  and  can  only  be  inflicted  on  account  of  crime. 
The  ruler  would  have  no  right  to  inflict  pain  on  his 
subjects  merely  for  the  sake  of  emendation.  Punish- 
ment can  be  inflicted  only  when  the  order  of  the  law  has 
been  broken  in  on  through  the  commission  of  a  crime. 

Now  many  writers,  particularly  those  of  the  Utili- 
tarian school  have  attempted  to  defend  the  opposite 
theory.  Following  Plato  they  maintain  that  punish- 
ment is  essentially  prospective  in  character,  i.e.,  either 
emendatory  or  deterrent.  What  is  spoken  of  as  retri- 
butive punishment  is,  they  claim,  not  only  not  funda- 
mental, but  is  an  injustice  and  immoral.  Pain  is  an 
evil,  they  say,  and  therefore  retributive  punishment 
instead  of  neutralising  evil,  is  itself  a  new  evil  and  a 
wrong.  They  claim  moreover  that  the  conception  of 
duty  makes  clear  the  prospective  and  not  the  retributive 
theory  of  punishment.  "  It  is  maintained,"  writes 
Sidgwick,  "  that  ought  implies  can,  and  in  a  certain 
sense  the  Determinist  will  agree  to  the  contention 
because  a  man  should  be  able  to  do  what  he  ought  to 
do.  But  if  he  is  not  able  to  do  this  his  inability 
arises  from  want  of  sufficient  motives,  and  it  is 
precisely  this  want  of  sufficient  motives  that  punish- 
ment (emendatory  punishment  of  course)  is  meant  to 
supply." 

Against  this  view  that  punishment  is  primarily  and 

retributive  punishment  are  not  the  same.  Vengeance  aims  at  pleasure 
the  pleasure  of  hurting  an  enemy  and  always  supposes  a  wrong  done 
to  one's  self  personally  or  to  some  one  whom  the  avenger  loves.  Punish- 
ment aims  at  securing  justice  simply,  and  proceeds  out  of  the  cold 
judgment  that  the  law  has  been  violated. 


590  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

essentially  prospective  in  character  we  urge  the  follow- 
ing arguments  : 

First — In  the  popular  mind  (and  we  see  no  reason 
for  thinking  that  the  popular  conception  is  here  at 
fault)  punishment  is  always  retrospective  in  character. 
It  is  always  regarded  as  inflicted  on  account  of  a  crime. 
The  use  of  a  surgeon's  knife  is  not  regarded  as  punish- 
ment even  though  it  is  painful  and  aims  at  the  emenda- 
tion of  the  subject.  Nor  would  the  popular  mind  con- 
cede to  a  judge  the  right  to  inflict  pain  on  any  person 
merely  for  the  sake  of  improving  him  or  deterring 
others  from  crime.  The  popular  idea  of  punishment 
is  very  truly  set  forth  by  Kant.  A  man  "  must  first 
be  found  guilty  and  punishable,  before  there  can  be  any 
thought  of  drawing  from  his  punishment  any  benefit 
for  himself  or  his  fellow-citizens."  * 

Secondly,  in  the  case  of  every  crime  a  law  is  violated, 
and  this  criminal  element  is  always  present  where 
punishment  is  inflicted.  But  sometimes  punishment 
may  be  inflicted  where  there  is  no  question  of  an  emen- 
datory  or  deterrent  element.  The  emendatory  theor}^, 
e.g.,  could  not  apply  in  the  case  of  capital  punishment, 
whilst  the  deterrent  theory  supposes  a  certain  proneness 
in  the  community  to  the  violation  of  law,  whereas  it  is 
possible  to  imagine  punishment  inflicted  on  an  individual 
living  in  a  community,  the  other  members  of  which 
have  no  similar  tendency  to  evil. 

Thirdly,  punishment  must  generally  be  proportioned 
to  the  crime.  Now,  were  the  emendatory  end  primary^ 
this  would  not  be  the  case,  since,  then,  punishment 
should  be  proportioned  not  to  the  crime",  but  to  what 
is  necessary  for  the  improvement  of  the  criminal. 

These  two  statements  of  ours  (a)  that  punishment  should 
be  proportioned  to  the  crime  {b)  that  on  the  emendatory 
theory  this  would  be  impossible,  have  been  called  in  question 
by  adherents  of  the  emendatory  theory.    They  say  (a)  that 

•  But  a  judge  may  much  more  easily  abstain  from  inllicling  pain 
than  assume  tlie  right  of  inflicting  it. 


ESSENTIAL  CONSEQUENCES  591 

punishment  is  not  and  need  not  be  proportioned  to  the 
crime  since  for  the  same  deed  a  known  criminal  is  punished 
more  severely  than  a  first  offender  ;  {b)  that  even  if  punish- 
ment should  be  proportioned  to  the  crime,  the  emendatory 
theory  would  still  stand,  since  it  is  by  proportioning  punish- 
ment to  the  crime  committed  that  associations  of  pain  are 
formed  which  will  most  effectively  lead  to  the  avoidance  of 
future  crime. 

To  these  two  objections  we  reply  as  follows  :  (a)  first 
offenders  are,  as  a  rule,  less  guilty  than  hardened  criminals, 
since  they  are  more  inexperienced  and  ignorant.  The  lighter 
punishment  inflicted  on  them  is  proof,  therefore,  of  the 
retributive,  rather  than  of  the  emendatory  character  of 
punishment.  Again,  even  though  we  claim  that  punish- 
ment should  be  proportioned  to  the  crime  we  do  not  say  that 
the  proportion  should  be  exact.  Punishment  is  essentially 
retributive,  but  some  margin  should  be  left  for  purposes  of 
emendation.  Hence  the  lighter  punishment  inflicted  on 
.  some  does  not  disprove  the  fundamentally  retributive 
character  of  punishment.  Again,  an  offence  repeated  is 
graver  in  its  consequences  to  the  community  than  a  first 
offence.  For  crime  is  contagious  and  tends  to  spread  in 
proportion  as  it  is  repeated.  Hence  repeated  crime  ought 
to  be  punished  more  severely.  Differences,  therefore,  in 
punishment  confirm  rather  than  disprove  the  retributive 
theory,  since  they  correspond  to  differences  in  the  crime 
committed. 

{b)  To  the  second  objection  given  above,  viz.,  that  even 
if  it  were  true  that  punishment  should  be  proportioned  to 
the  crime,  the  emendatory  theory  would  still  hold  good, 
since  it  is  only  by  proportioning  punishment  to  the  crime 
that  the  required  deterrent  associations  are  formed,  we 
reply :  these  painful  associations  could  be  secured  if  punish- 
ment were  inflicted  on  the  occasion  of  the  crime,  and  without 
proportioning  one  to  the  other.  Hence,  in  the  emendatory 
theory  punishment  need  not  be  proportioned  to  the  crime. 

Fourthly,  we  claim  that  on  the  emendatory  theory 
it  would  be  useless,  and,  therefore,  immoral,  to  punish 
a  hopeless  recalcitrant.  But  even  the  hopeless  recal- 
citrant must  be  punished.  Therefore,  the  emendatory 
theory  is  not  true.  Our  third  and  fourth  arguments 
taken  together  yield  us  the  following  strong  case 
against  the  emendatory  theory  :     {a)   even  if  emenda- 


592  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

tion  were  possible  only  by  the  infliction  of  very  grave 
punishment  such  punishment  could  not  be  inflicted 
unless  the  crime  committed  were  also  grave :  {b)  on 
the  other  hand,  a  grave  crime  may  be  punished  very 
severely  even  though  emendation  be  regarded  as  wholly 
impossible.  In  neither  case,  therefore,  is  punishment 
to  be  explained  by  the  motive  of  emendation.  It  rests 
in  both  cases  upon  a  deeper  purpose. 

To  our  fourth  argument  it  may  be  objected  that  a 
hopeless  recalcitrant  might  be  punished  on  the  pro- 
spective the'ory  as  a  means  to  preventing  others  from 
wrong-doing)  for  punishment  may  be  deterrent  as  well 
as  emendatory.  And  we  fully  admit  the  force  of  this 
answer  in  so  far  as  it  favours  the  deterrent  theory. 
But  we  do  not  consider  that  punishment  as  deterrent 
could  stand  alone.  It  could  not  be  right  to  inflict , 
punishment  on  any  man  simply  for  the  sake  of  others., 
Personal  pain  presupposes  either  personal  guilt  or  the 
possibility  of  personal  improvement  ;  and  since,  in  the 
case  considered,  improvement  is  out  of  the  question, 
we  cannot  agree  that  punishment  could  be  inflicted 
unless  punishment  be  mainly  retrospective. 

This  concludes  our  case  against  the  theory  that 
punishment  is  primarily  prospective — i.e.,  is  either 
emendatory  or  deterrent. 


CHAPTER  XVIII 

OF  HABITS  AND  VIRTUES 

Meaning  of  Habit.— In  its  widest  meaning  "  habit  '* 
is  any  quality  in  an  object  which  increases  or 
diminishes  its  perfection.  Thus,  beauty,  strength, 
virtue  are  habits.     Also  ugliness,  weakness,  vice. 

In  this  wide  sense  habits  are  divided  into  entitative 
and  operative — the  first  class  being  those  habits  that 
perfect  or  impair  the  substance  of  a  thing,  the  second 
class  of  habits  being  those  that  perfect  or  impair  a  thing 
in .  its  powers.  Thus,  beauty  is  an  entitative  virtue, 
piano-playing  is  an  operative  habit. 

Now,  since  Ethics  has  principally  to  do  with  action, 
we  are  as  ethicians  interested  in  operative  habits  only. 
In  this  sense  habit  properly  defined  is — any  quality 
whereby  an  agent  who  is  by  nature  indifferent  to  a 
certain  course  of  action  or  to  the  opposite  course  comes 
to  be  permanently  inclined  to  one  course  rather  than  to 
another.  In  the  pages  that  follow  we  shall  speak  of 
habits  in  this  restricted  sense  of  operative  habits  only. 

We  said  in  our  definition  that  an  operative  habit 
dwells  only  in  indifferent  or  undetermined  powers.  By 
this  we  do  not  mean  that  operative  habits  dwell  exclu- 
sively in  powers  that 'are  free,  for  there  are  some  powers 
which  are  not  free,  and  which  yet,  not  being  determined 
to  one  way  of  acting,  can  admit  of  operative  habits. 
Thus,  animals  can  be  trained  by  different  methods  to 
move  in  different  ways,  and  any  permanent  tendency 
got  by  training  to  move  in  a  particular  way  is  an 
operative  habit.  But,  in  its  fullest  sense,  habit  dwells 
» in  free  powers  only,  because  only  the  free  subject  is 
undetermined  in  the  proper  sense  of  the  word. 

That  habit   dwells  only  in  such   powers  as  are  not 

Vol.  I.-3S  593 


594  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

determined  to  one  mode  of  action  is  evident.  For  if 
a  thing  is  by  nature  determined  to  one  end  only,  and 
can  act  in  only  one  way,  any  further  helping  of  it  to 

•  '  its  end  would  be  useless  and  impracticable,  and  it  is 
not  to  be  supposed  that  nature  has  made  provision 
for  the  reception  into  our  faculties  of  what  would  be 
useless  to  them  in  the  work  of  attaining  their  end. 
Hence,  such  faculties  do  not  admit  of  habits. 

We  have  said  also  that  operative  habits  are  to  be 
found  above  all  in  the  free  powers  of  man.  The  free 
/powers  are  either  the  human  will  itself  or  such  powers 
as  can  come  under  its  influence.  In  both  of  these  we 
may  have  operative  habits.  Thus,  operative  habits 
may  be  found  in  the  imagination  or  the  sensuous 
appetites  because  these  powers  are  undetermined,  and 
'  they  are  to  a  large  extentr^under  the  control  of  the  will. 
They  are  to  be  found  ii^he  motor  powers  particularly. 
The  fingers,  for  instance,  may,  through  practice,  tend 
to  assume  a  certain  succession  of  positions  in  order  to 
the  production  of  successive  musical  chords.  This 
tendency  of  the  fingers  is  a  habit,  and  good  piano  playing 
will  depend  to  a  large  extent  on  the  perfection  of  such 
habits,  for  through  them  come  facility,  and  evenness, 
and  good  tone  in  playing.  But  it  should  be  remembered 
that  habits  dwell  rather  in  the  faculties  that  move  the 

f  organs  than  in  the  organs  themselves,  for  it  is  only  in 
so  far  as  the  organs  are  under  the  influence  of  the  motor 
faculty  that  they  can  be  affected  by  habits  at  all.  Thus, 
the  habit  of  piano-playing  dwells  in  the  motor  power  or 
faculty  rather  than  in  the  material  fingers  themselves. 

Can  there  be  operative  habits  in  the  intellect  ?     At 
first  sight  it  would  seem  as  if  there  could  not,  for  the 

j  intellect    is    determined    to    a    single    object — namely, 

c  truth — and  it  can  no  more  help  assenting  to  a  proposi- 
tion which  is  seen  to  be  true  than  the  eye  can  help 
seeing  visible  objects.  It  would  seem,  therefore,  that 
in  the  intellect  there  is  no  room  for  operative  habits, 
the  function  of  which  would,  of  course,  be  to  aitl  the 


HABITS   AND  VIRTUE  595 

intellect  to  assent — an  aid  which  apparently  the  intel- 
lect does  not  require.  Yet  in  spite  of  this  difficulty 
we  maintain  that  the  intellect  does  admit  of  operative 
/habits,  for  the  subject  of  habits  need  not  be  free.  It 
is  sufficient  that  it  be  by  nature  "  in  potentia  ad  plura  " 
/ — that  is,  not  determined  to  one  effect.  But  the  intel- 
lect is  not  determined  to  one  effect.  It  can  be  deter- 
mined in  diverse  ways  and  is  capable  of  many  different 
acts.  Thus,  not  all  men  are  moved  to  think  or  assent 
by  the  same  influences,  nor  do  all  intellects  reach  the 
same  thought.  Therefore,  the  intellect  is  capable  of 
receiving  habits. 

But  not  only  is  the  intellect  not  determined  by  nature 
to  one  effect,  it  is  also  in  many  of  its  acts  even  free,  as 
the  Scholastics  say,  by  participation.  For  to  a  large 
extent  the  intellect  is  under  the  control  of  the  will, 
which  can  actually  make  a  man  assent  to  a  proposition 
in  cases  in  which,  on  the  mere  objective  evidence,  the 
intellect  would  withhold  assent — i.e.,  we  can  force  our-  , 
selves  to  believe  many  things  even  though  they  be  not 
evidently  true.  Hence,  the  intellect  is  movable  by  a 
free  power  and  admits  of  habits. 

Habits  are  either  natural  or  acquired.  In  common 
parlance  we  limit  the  term  "  habit  "  to  acquired  habit, 
and  often  define  it  as  "a  faculty  afforded  by  repeated 
action."  But  some  habits  are  natural,  and  even  when 
a  habit  is  acquired  some  part  of  it  is  often  natural. 
This  distinction  is  of  some  importance  in  regard  to  the 
question  of  the  merit  attaching  to  certain  habits. 

\a)  On  Virtues  and  Vices  in  General 

Virtues  and  vices  are  operative  habits  *  because  they 
move  the  will  directly  to  certain  acts.  They  dwell  only 
in  the  higher  powers  of  the  soul,  and  when  perfect  they 
dwell  in  free  powers  only — that  is,  in  powers  that  are 
either  free  in  themselves  or  free  as  under  the  control  of 

•  Virtue  has  been  defined  as  "  habitus  operativus  bonus." 


f 


596  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

the  free  will.  An  imperfect  virtue  may  dwell  in  powers 
that  are  not  free  in  either  of  these  two  senses.  Perfect 
virtues  are  those  that  not  only  give  a  man  the  power  of 
acting  well,  but  also  actually  impel  him  to  act  well,  or 
which  not  only  give  him  the  power  of  using  his  faculties 
aright,  but  also  incline  him  to  use  them  aright.  Thus, 
perfect  virtue,  or  virtue  in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  term, 
is  defined — "  quaedam  qualitas  mentis,  qua  recte  vivitur, 
qua  nemo  male  utitur."  An  imperfect  virtue  is  one 
which  "  gives  a  man  the  power  to  act  aright,  but  does 
not  incline  him  to  act  aright."  As  we  said,  a  perfect 
virtue  always  dwells  in  a  free  power — that  is,  a  power 
which  is  either  free  itself — ^namely,  will — or  a  power 
which  is  under  the  control  of  freedom,  whereas  the 
imperfect  virtues,  although  operative  habits,  may  be 
in  a  power  over  which  free  will  has  no  control,  or,  at 
all  events,  they  can  be  in  such  a  faculty  irrespective  of 
any  influence  which  it  is  in  the  power  of  the  will  to 
exercise  over  it.  In  this  latter  sense  imperfect  virtues 
are  to  be  found  in  the  speculative  Reason — i.e.,  they 
are  there  irrespective  of  its  control  by  will. 

These  imperfect  virtues  dwelling  in  the  speculative 
Reason  are  three — namely.  Wisdom,  Science,  and  Intel- 
lect. Wisdom  is  the  knowledge  of  conclusions  through 
their  highest  principles  or  causes.  Science  is  the  know- 
ledge of  conclusions  through  their  immediate  causes. 
Intellect  *  is  the  knowledge  of  the  first  or  highest 
])rinciples  themselves.  These  virtues  dwell  in  the  specu- 
lative intellect.  They  are  operative  habits  because 
they  give  us  a  power  of  doing ;  but  they  do  not  impel 
or  incline  us  to  do.  Hence,  they  are  not  perfect  virtues, 
but  imperfect.     There  is  one  other  imperfect  intellectual 

•  Intellect  in  this  sense  of  a  habit  or  a  speculative  virtue  is  to  be 
carefully  distinguished  from  wiiat  is  usually  called  the  faculty  of 
intellect,  which  is  the  same  ground  faculty  as  Reason  or  the  ordinary 
rational  faculty. 

The  reader  should  not  be  surprised  at  our  present  broad  use  of 
the  word  "  virtue."  It  is  only  custom  that  has  limited  the  word  to 
what  arc  known  as  the  moral  virtues,  of  which  we  are  soon  to  speak, 
Wc  arc  here  following  the  stricter  philosophical  usage. 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  597 

virtue,  and  it  dwells  not  in  the  speculative  but  in  the 
'practical  intellect — namely,  Art.  Art,  like  the  other 
imperfect  virtues,  gives  a  man  the  power  of  doing  the 
good  thing,  but  it  never  inclines  him  to  do  it.  It  enables 
a  man  to  produce  the  beautiful  effect,  but  it  does  not 
make  him  produce  that  effect,  nor  does  it  necessarily 
incline  him  so  to  do.  Thus,  it  differs  from  Prudence 
and  from  the  moral  virtues  of  which  we  shall  presently 
speak,  for  these  are  all  perfect  virtues. 

Now,  whereas  an  imperfect  virtue  merely  makes  a 
man  capable  of  doing  a  good  work,  a  perfect  virtue 
i  actually  makes  a  man  good  himself,  since  it  inclines  him 
to  the  good  work,  and  from  this  difference  between  the 
imperfect  and  perfect  virtue  there  arises  a  twofold 
distinction  between  Art,  on  the  one  hand,  and  Prudence 
and  the  Moral  Virtues  on  the  other — namely,  (a)  first, 
that  Art  has  nothing  to  do  with  a  man's  love  of  the 
good  work  but  only  with  the  outer  work  itself,  whereas 
the  primary  effect  of  the  other  virtues  is  to  set  up  in 
a  man  a  good  attitude  towards  his  work,  to  make  him 
love  it  (eVii/  o  TTfrnTTUiv  ttws  fX"'*'  TrpaxTr/  is  the  descrip- 
tion given  by  Aristotle).  Thus  he  is  quite  as  much  an 
artist  who  hates  sculpture  as  he  who  loves  it,  provided 
both  can  make  good  statues.  But  to  be  truly  temperate 
one  should  love  temperance.  Again,  (b)  were  an  artist 
knowingly  and  willingly  to  paint  a  faulty  picture,  it 
is  not  his  Art  that  is  blamed  for  it  but  his  bad  will, 
whereas,  if  his  error  is  unconscious  and  unwilling,  it  is 
his  Art  that  is  brought  to  task  and  criticised.  In  the 
case  of  the  moral  virtues  the  opposite  is  true.  He  who 
does  wrong  knowingly  is  without  these  virtues,  whereas 
he  who  does  wrong  unconsciously  may  possess  these 
virtues  to  a  high  degree. 

Thus,  Art  is  judged  by  the  perfection  of  a  man's  work 
alone,  by  what  he  produces,  and  not  by  his  attitude 
towards  his  work,  and  hence  we  define  Art  as  the  "  recta 
ratio  factibilium."  But  Prudence,  which,  being  a  per- 
fect virtue,  concerns  a  man's  attitude  towards  his  work, 


598  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

is  defined  as  the  "  recta  ratio  agibilium  " — a  definition 
which  will  be  explained  presently. 

But  just  as  there  are  imperfect  virtues  in  the  specu- 
lative and  practical  Reason,  so  also  there  are  perfect 
virtues,  but  with  this  great  difference,  that  whereas  the 
perfect  virtues  depend  on  the  fact  that  intellect  is  under 
the  control  of  the  free  will,  the  imperfect  virtues  are 
independent  of  this  control.  In  the  speculative  intellect 
we  have  the  supernatural  perfect  virtue  of  Faith,  which 
is  an  assent  of  the  intellect  under  motion  of  the  will  to 
revealed  truth.  Faith  depends  to  some  extent  on  will, 
for,  to  make  an  act  of  faith,  the  intellect  has  to  be 
moved  by  will  to  assent.  Faith,  then,  is  the  perfect 
virtue  of  the  speculative  intellect ;  but  in  Ethics  it 
does  not  concern  us,  because  Ethics  deals  only  with  the 
natural  virtues,  whereas  Faith  is  supernatural.  The 
only  perfect  virtue  of  Intellect  considered  in  Ethics  is 
Prudence.* 

(b)  On  Prudence 

(i)  Prudence  we  have  already  defined  as  the  "  recta 
ratio  agibilium,"  by  which  we  mean  a  virtue  of  the 
Practical  Reason  which  not  only  enables  a  man  to 
know  in  concrete  circumstances  what  means  are  best 
to  take  to  a  good  end,  but  also  inclines  a  man  to  take 
these  means  with  promptitude  and  precision.  Prudence 
resides  in  the  intellect,  not  in  the  will,  for  its  acts  are 
intellectual  acts.  By  Prudence  we  enquire  about, 
examine  or  judge,  and  direct  ourselves  to  the  adoption 
of  the  proper  means  to  an  end  desired,  and  since  these 
are  all  acts  of  the  intellect.  Prudence  is  a  virtue  of  the 
intellect — that  is,  of  the  practical  intellect,  since  it 
'  appertains  to  action  or  ends.     Its  acts  are  three-fold, 

•  To  aid  the  reader  at  this  j)oint  wc  give  the  list  of  intellectual 
virtues  briefly  thus  :  In  the  speculative  intellect  there  are  the  three 
imperfect  virtue.s — Wisdom,  Science,  and  Intellect—and  one  perfect 
virtue — Faith — which,  being  supernatural,  TUhics  does  not  consider. 
In  the  practical  intellect  there  is  one  imperfect  virtue — Art — and  one 
perfect  virtue  — Prudence.  But  none  of  these  are  moral  virtue*-; 
moral  virtues  dwell  in  the  appetites  only. 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  599 

as  we  said — enquiry,  judgment,  and  command  (consiliare, 
judicare,  praecipere)  ;  but  its  principal  act  is  command 
\  — that  is,  the  moving  of  a  man  to  take  the  means.  He 
who  knows  the  proper  means,  but  is  not  moved  to  take 
them,  or  is  slow  and  indifferent  about  them,  is  just  as 
imprudent  as  he  who  entertains  a  project  but  does  not 
know  what  means  to  take  to  its  accomplishment.  And 
the  means  with  which  Prudence  deals  are  not  necessary 
means  but  contingent  means — that  is.  Prudence  deals 
with  cases  in  which  there  is  a  plurality  of  ways  of 
gaining  our  end   ((/jpovTjo-is,    as  Aristotle  writes,     .     .    . 

irepl    Tiuv     dSwaroiv     aAAws    ex^'*')-       From     this     it     foUoWS 

that  only  rational  beings  are  prudent,  since  only  rational 
beings  have  a  choice  of  means  to  ends. 

From  all  these  characteristics  of  Prudence  we  see  that 
it  is  a  special  virtue  and  distinct  from  all  the  other 
virtues.  It  differs  from  the  moral  virtues  or  the  virtues 
of  the  will,  because  it  resides  in  a  distinct  faculty — 
namely,  the  practical  Reason — and  it  differs  from  the 
virtues  of  the  speculative  intellect,  because  its  formal 
\  object  is  different — the  speculative  virtues  deal  with 
necessary  laws.  Prudence  with  contingent  laws./^It- 
differs  also  from  Art,  although  Art  resides  in  the  same 
power  as  Prudence,  and,  like  Prudence,  concerns  what 
is  contingent ;  for,  as  we  have  seen.  Art  deals  with 
products  (factibilia).  Prudence  with  operations  *  (agibilia). 

It  is  important  that  we  should  determine  how 
Prudence  stands  related  to  the  other  virtues.  We 
said  that  Prudence  appertains  to  the  means  by  which 
I  we  are  to  gain  our  end,  and  that  he  alone  is  prudent  in 
the  fullest  sense  who  not  only  knows  the  means  that 
lead  to  the  final  end,  but  is  moved  to  take  them.  And 
in   this   way   Prudence  is   necessary  for   all   the  moral 

*  Of  course,  as  controlled  by  mind.  Art  refers  to  the  merest 
externals.  A  dance  is  artistic  and  graceful  as  mere  external  move- 
ment and  whether  the  artistic  effect  was  produced  purposefully  or  not. 
But  Prudence  refers  principally  to  inner  movement.  We  do  not  speak 
of  a  man  as  prudent  unless  his  act  was  purposefully  directed  to  a  good  j 
end.  '  1 


6oo  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

virtues.  For  the  moral  virtues  move  to  the  final  end, 
and  Prudence  indicates  the  means  to  that  end  and  moves 
to  their  adoption.  It  is  necessary  to  the  other  virtues 
for  another  reason — namely,  that  without  it  the  other 
virtues  cannot  secure  the  mean  of  virtue.  For  we  shall 
'  see  later  that  every  virtue  consists  in  a  mean  between, 
'  extremes.  But  this  mean,  when  translated  into  terms 
of  action,  is  found  to  consist  in  the  proper  use  of  the 
things  that  lead  to  our  end — "  per  rectam  dispositionem 
eorum  quae  sunt  ad  finem,  medium  invenitur."  Now, 
if  the  same  things  led  always  and  in  all  circumstances 
to  the  final  end — i.e.,  if  the  mean  of  virtue  were  the 
same  for  every  man — then  each  virtue  would  of  its  own 
nature  assure  the  attainment  of  the  mean  of  virtue, 
.and  in  that  way  Prudence  would  not  be  necessary  for 
'attaining  the  mean.  But  the  mean  of  virtue  is  not  the 
same  in  all  circumstances,  and  hence  the  necessity  of 
the  virtue  of  Prudence  to  indicate  the  right  and  proper 
course  in  individual  cases.  Without  Prudence,  there- 
fore, the  moral  virtues  themselves  could  not  keep  the 
mean ;  for  instance,  without  it  fortitude  would  turn 
to  rashness,  and  temperance  to  insensibility  ;  for  it  is 
not  in  the  conception  of  his  end  that  an  over-temperate 
man  sins,  since  his  end  is  to  make  sense  subordinate  to 
Reason ;  he  sins  in  not  using  the  right  means  to  this 
end — that  is,  he  fails  for  want  of  Prudence.  Prudence, 
therefore,  keeps  a  man  right  in  the  use  of  the  means  in 
the  case  of  each  virtue,  and  so  Prudence  is  a  necessary 
condition  of  every  virtue.  But  if  Prudence  is  necessary 
to  the  other  virtues  so  also  the  other  virtues  are  neces- 
sary to  Prudence,  because  a  man  is  not  moved  either 
to  enquire  about  or  to  adopt  the  right  means  to  the  end 
unless  he  desires  the  end,  and  since  the  desire  of  good 
ends  is  effected  by  the  moral  virtues,  so  without  the 
moral  virtues  a  man  cannot  rightly  be  called  prudent. 
However,  this  law  of  connection  between  Prudence  and 
the  other  virtues  holds,  properly  speaking,  only  for  the 
ordinary  moral  virtues— that  is,  those  which  are  required 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  6oi 

in  ordinary  circumstances ;  so  that  a  man  could  be 
prudent  whilst  yet  he  is  not  actually  possessed  of  such 
high  virtues  as  those  of  magnificence  and  magnanimity. 
Nevertheless,  a  truly  virtuous  man  will  be  found  to  be 
generally  possessed  of  these  virtues  to  some  extent, 
or  at  least  of  such  virtues  as  would  on  a  little  cultivation 
easily  rise  to  the  level  of  magnificence  and  magnanimity 
did  the  proper  occasion  present  itself. 

Modern  philosophy  has  done  much  to  bring  the  virtue 
of  Prudence  into  contempt  by  representing  it  as  ex- 
clusively a  selfish  virtue — a  virtue  by  which  each  man 
seeks  to  secure  his  own  greatest  happiness.  But  Pru- 
dence no  more  exclusively  concerns  the  individual 
happiness  than  do  the  other  virtues.  For,  there  is  a 
Prudence  that  prescribes  the  right  means  to  the  family 
good  or  general  good,  as  well  as  that  which  secures  one's 
own  personal  good.  In  other  words.  Prudence  may  be 
economic  and  political  as  well  as  "  monastic  "  (in  the 
Scholastic  sense  meaning  "  individual  ").  However, 
when  used  wdthout  quahfication,  the  word  "  Prudence  " 
("  Prudence  "  simply)  has  always  been  understood  as 
appertaining  to  the  individual  good  only. 

We  have  said  that  he  only  is  prudent  in  the  full 
\  sense  who  seeks  the  means  that  will  lead  him  to  his 
final  end.  The  man  who  indulges  in  evil  courses  may, 
indeed,  be  astute  (8civot?j?  Aristotle  calls  it)  in  the 
discerning  of  means,  and  such  astuteness  is  sometimes 
called  Prudence.  But  such  a  habit  of  mind  is  really 
only  the  semblance  of  Prudence  since  it  does  not  con- 
cern our  final  end,  or  rather  since,  while  leading  to  the 
attainment  of  lesser  ends  it  often  leads  to  the  total 
loss  of  our  principal  and  final  end.  But  there  is  an 
astuteness  which  has  something  in  it  of  Prudence,  but 
yet  in  so  far  as  it  is  identified  with  Prudence  is  Prudence 
of  an  incomplete  kind  only.  This  lesser  kind  of  Prudence 
is  twofold— first,  there  is  the  Prudence  that  helps  to  the 
possession  of  the  proper  means  but  does  not  move  us  to 
their  adoption  ;    secondly,  there  is  the  Prudence  that 


6o2  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

moves  to  the  adoption  of  the  means  to  ends  which, 
though  good  in  themselves,  are  yet  not  sought  as  leading 
to  the  final  end.  Thus,  there  are  prudent  business  men, 
prudent  navigators,  prudent  soldiers,  all  of  whom  may 
seek  good  ends  without  conscious  reference  to  the  final 
end.  The  prudent  man  (simply)  is,  as  Aristotle  says 
(Nich.  Eth.  VI.,  9,  7),  he  who  in  all  things  seeks  the 
right  means  to  his  last  end. 

(2)  The  parts  of  Prudence. 

The  parts  of  a  virtue  are  three-fold — integral  parts, 
subjective  parts,  and  potential  parts. 

Integral  parts  are  those  qualities  of  mind  that  concur 
to  make  up  the  complete  virtue,  in  the  same  sense  that 
the  parts  concur  to  make  up  a  house.  Subjective  parts 
are  the  various  subordinate  species  of  a  virtue  or  the 
kinds  of  virtue  into  which  a  certain  virtue  can  be  dis- 
tinguished, in  the  sense  that  houses  are  distinguished 
into  stone  and  wooden  houses,  round  and  square. 
Potential  parts  are  certain  annexed  virtues  which  con- 
cern certain  secondary  objects  that  have  not  the  same 
importance  nor  are  so  difficult  of  attainment  as  the 
object  of  the  principal  virtue.  The  integral  parts  of 
Prudence  are  enumerated  by  Aquinas,  following 
Aristotle.  The  requirements  of  Prudence,  in  so  far 
as  it  is  a  cognitive  virtue — that  is,  in  so  far  as  it  merely 
indicates  the  right  means — are  five — namely,  memory, 
Reason,  intellect,  Md^cUity  (or  the  power  of  acquiring  a  | 
knowledge  of  the  right  means  from  others),'  and  con- 
jecture (solertia,  or  the  power  of  rapid  personal  percep- 
tion of  the  right  means).  Again,  the  requirements  of 
Prudence,  in  so  far  as  it  is  preceptive,  or  moves  to  the 
adoption  of  the  means,  are  three — providence,  or  the" 
adoption  of  the  essential  means  ;  circumspection,  wliicli 
considers  the  circumstances ;  caution,  which  guards 
against  impediment  and  opposition. 

The  SUBJECTIVE  parts  of  Prudence,  or  its  main  divi- 
sions,   will    correspond    with    the    principal    classes    of 


\ 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  603 

those  whose  good  it  seeks.  As  we  have  already  pointed 
out,  these  principal  kinds  are  prudence  simply  (which 
concerns  the  individual  good),  economic  prudence,  and 
political  prudence. 

The  potential  parts  of  Prudence,  or  its  annexed 
virtues,  are  three.  They  have  reference  to  certain 
subordinate  acts  belonging  to  Prudence.  The  principal 
act  of  Prudence  is,  as  we  saw,  that  act  of  command 
which  moves  us  to  the  adoption  of  the  proper  means. 
But  this  act  is  itself  preceded  by  two  other  subordinate 
acts — namely,  counsel,  or  the  setting  about  the  enquiry 
as  to  what  means  will  lead  us  to  our  end,  and  judgment 
or  the  weighing  of  these  means — that  is,  the  formation 
of  sound  practical  judgments  on  the  means.  This 
can  be  done  either  by  reasoning  from  practical  principles 
or  by  following  our  own  good  sense  when,  on  account 
of  the  peculiarity  of  the  case,  there  are  no  commonly 
admitted  principles  to  go  by.  These  three  acts  imply 
the  three  annexed  virtues,  to  which  philosophers  have 
given  the  names  Eubulia,  Synesis,  and  Gnome. 

EuBULiA  moves  a  man  to  the  enquiry  what  means 
will  lead  to  the  end.  Now,  once  moved  to  this  enquiry, 
some  men  are  capable  of  a  good  practical  judgment  in 
ordinary  cases  in  which  there  are  commonly  admitted 
principles  to  go  by,  which  is  the  virtue  of  SYxNESIS. 
But  men  who  are  capable  of  a  good  judgment  in  ordinary 
cases  would  be  wholly  at  sea  in  dealing  with  out-of- 
the-way  or  uncommon  cases  to  which  the  general 
principles  of  prudent  action  do  not  appl}^  and  the 
prudence  which  comes  into  play  in  such  cases  is  of  a 
much  higher  order  than  that  of  Synesis,  for  it  judges 
by  higher  principles  and  it  involves  a  certain  "  per- 
spicacity of  judgment  "  (perspicacitas  judicii)  which  in 
ordinary  cases  is  not  required.  To  this  virtue  which 
guides  a  man  in  abnormal  circumstances  is  given  the 
name  of  Gnome.  All  these  are  annexed  virtues  or 
potential  parts  of  the  intellectual  virtue  of  Prudence. 
We  now  go  on  to  speak  of  the  Moral  virtues. 


6o4  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

(c)  The  Moral  Virtues 
(i)  The  Moral  virtues  compared  with  Prudence. 

Like  Prudence,  the  moral  virtues  are  perfect  virtues, 
but  unlike  Prudence  they  dwell  not  in  the  intellect  but 
in  the  appetitive  faculty  of  the  will.  Being  perfect 
virtues,  the  Moral  virtues  are  essentially  conative  habits 
— that  is,  their  function  is  to  incline  one  to  the  attain- 
ment of  ends. 

Prudence,  therefore,  having  nothing  to  do  with  ends 
as  such,  but  only  with  the  proper  use  of  means,  is  not, 
rightly  speaking,  a  moral  virtue,  but  it  is  moral  by 
participation,  in  so  far,  namely,  as  it  is  a  necessary 
element  in  every  virtue,  for,  as  already  explained, 
without  Prudence  there  can  be  no  moral  virtue.  We 
saw  that  the  reverse  of  this  proposition  is  also  true — 
without'  the  moral  virtues  no  man  is  prudent.  A  man 
may  be  astute  in  taking  the  proper  means  to  certain 
ends,  but  if  such  ends  lead  him  away  from  his  final  end, 
the  so-called  prudent  man  is  the  least  prudent  of  all. 
.  Better  the  foolish  man  who,  through  very  foolishness, 
may  miss  his  way  and  fail  to  realise  his  evil  purposes, 
^'^and  so  may  be  by  chance  brought  to  a  right  life,  than 
the  so-called  prudent  man  who,  if  once  he  sets  his  mind 
on  evil,  is  certain  to  achieve  it.  Again,  Prudence  cannot 
of  itself  control  the  passions.  The  control  of  the  passions 
^  is  the  work  of  the  moral  virtues.  But  passion  uncon- 
trolled makes  Prudence  impossible,  since  passion  tends 
to  blind  the  intellect  and  Prudence  is  a  virtue  of  the 
intellect.  Consequently,  without  the  moral  virtues  we 
cannot  be  prudent,  just  as  without  Prudence  there  can 
be  no  moral  virtue. 

(2)  The  Moral  virtues  compared  with  knowledge  and 
passion. 

Since  the  moral  virtues  reside  in  the  will  it  follows 

that  they  are  essentially  inclinations  of  the  will  to  some 

I  end.     Tlu'y   are,    tlicrcft)re,   quite   distinct   from   know- 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  605 

ledge  or  mere  intellectual  ideas.  They  cannot  be  ac- 
quired by  teaching  or  by  mere  study,  but  only  by 
practice  or  direct  infusion  from  a  higher  Power.  Some 
ancients  taught  that  virtue  could  be  acquired  by  teach- 
ing, the  reason  of  their  doctrine  being  that  they 
identified  all  virtue  with  knowledge.  But  all  virtue 
is  not  knowledge,  and  the  wise  man  is  not  the  only 
virtuous  man.  The  moral  virtues  presuppose  know- 
ledge, but  they  are  essentially  habits  of  the  appetite.* 

Now,  as  the  moral  virtues  residing  in  the  will  are 
necessarily  distinct  from  the  intellectual,  so  also  they 
are  distinct  from  the  passions,  since  the  passions  reside 
in  the  sensitive  appetite.  Moral  virtues  also,  indeed,  -i 
reside  in  the  sensitive  appetite,  but  only  in  so  far  as  '^'^ 
the  sensitive  appetite  comes  under  the  control  of  the 
will.  But  the  passions  reside  in  the  "  sensitive "  as 
such — that  is,  as  independent  of  the  will.  A  man 
driven  on  by  furious  passion  is  passionate  in  so  far  as 
he  is  a  creature  of  sense.  He  is  temperate  in  so  far  as 
these  same  passions  are  made  subject  to  reason  and  the 
will.  Between  the  moral  virtues  and  Passion  there  is 
also  this  difference,  that  passion  is  morally  quite  in- 
different— that  is,  may  be  turned  to  good  or  evil  use — 
but  virtue  is  always  good  in  itself,  and  can  never  be 
for  evil  purposes — "  qua  nemo  male  utitur." 

(3)  The  objects  of  the  moral  virtues. 

Some  of  the  moral  virtues  are  intended  directly  to 
control   the   internal   passions,    others   to   regulate   our 

♦  The  Socratic  theory  that  all  virtue  is  knowledge,  and  is,  therefore, 
teachable,  and  that  all  vice  is  due  to  ignorance,  is  to  be  found  in  the 
writings  of  a  good  many  modern  philosophers.  Thus,  Fichte  writes — 
"  If  we  had  a  clear  idea  of  duty  we  should  do  it,  for  to  clearly  conceive  f^ 
is  to  require  of  myself  to  do."  To  which  we  answer — "  Clearly  to 
conceive  "  is  to  "  require  of  myself  to  do  "  in  the  sense  of  "  seeing  that 
that  I  should  do,"  which  is  not  the  same  as  "  inclining  to  the  doing  of 
duty."  Only  the  moral  virtues  incline  us  to  do  what  we  clearly  con- 
ceive to  be  our  duty.  Fichte's  argument  is  meant  primarily  to  show 
that  evil  action  is  due  to  ignorance.  But  we  have  seen  that  though 
evil  action  does  presuppose  a  certain  blinding  of  the  intellect  to  the 
evil  of  the  action,  still  this  *!amo  blinding  is  voluntary  and  conscious, 
and  it  does  not  really  make  \.s  ignorant  of  what  we  do  (See  page  225). 


6o6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

external  acts.  For  moral  goodness  sometimes  con- 
sists in  a  relation  between  the  agent  and  his  act,  and 
sometimes  in  the  external  act  itself.  In  the  former 
case  the  end  of  virtue  is  the  controlling  of  the  passions, 
in  the  latter  the  regulating  of  the  external  act.  Thus, 
temperance  controls  the  inner  passions  and  only  in- 
directly concerns  the  outer  action.  The  man  who, 
thinking  he  is  drinking  water,  really  drinks  spirits,  and 
consequently  gets  drunk,  has  committed  no  offence 
against  the  virtue  of  Temperance.  Temperance,  then, 
has  to  do  with  a  man's  relations  to  his  acts — i.e.,  with 
his  internal  feelings  and  passions.  It  is  the  same  with 
Fortitude.  But  Justice  regulates  our  external  acts 
directly,*  and  only  indirectly  concerns  the  inner  pas- 
sions. For  in  acts  of  justice  there  is  always  the  "  ratio 
debiti  ad  alterum,"  and  that  can  only  have  reference 
to  our  external  acts. 

(4)  The  mean  of  the  moral  virtues. 

The  end  ..of  virtue  is  to  perfect  .the^wiU-  But  the  will 
is  perfected  by  conformity  with  the  law  of  right  action. 
Hence,  law  is  the  measure  of  virtue.  Now,  we  can 
violate  a  law  in  either  of  two  ways — either  by  excess 
or  defect,  either  by  exceeding  in  the  doing  of  that 
which  the  law  ordains  or  by  failing  to  come  up  to  its 
requirements.  Thus,  the  law  which  binds  us  to  eat 
in  order  that  the  body  may  be  maintained  can  be 
violated  either  by  eating  too  much  or  too  little.  Be- 
tween the  two  extremes  of  defect  and  excess  lies  the 
mean  of  the  moral  virtues. 

Now,  the  proper  measure  of  the  mean  of  virtue  is 
human  Reason,  for  the  natural  law  dwells  in  our 
Reason,  t  But  Reason  does  not  prescribe  the  same 
course  of  conduct  for  every  variety  of  circumstance 
and  character,  but  varies  in  its  requirements  according 
to    individual    opportunities,    character,    and    circum- 

•  Sec  page  O29, 
t  Sec  page  633. 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  607 

stances  ;  and,  therefore,  the  mean  of  the  moral  virtue 
also  varies  with  the  individual  circumstances.  This  is 
expressed  by  Aquinas  saying  that  the  mean  of  the  moral 
virtues  is  determined  in  relation  to  ourselves,  and  that  it 
is  a  mean  of  Reason,  not  of  objects — medium  rationis, 
not  rei. 

In  the  case  of  one  virtue,  however,  it  happens  that 
the  medium  rationis  coincides  with  the  tnedium  ret — 
namely,  the  virtue  of  Justice.  For  Justice  appertains 
to  action  not  to  passions  ;  whereas  it  is  in  relation  to 
our  passions  and  other  subjective  needs  that  the  re- 
quirements of  individuals  differ  from  one  another.  The 
mean,  therefore,  of  the  virtue  of  Justice  is  the  medium 
rei,  which  is  the  same  for  all  men.  But  in  the  case  of 
the  other  moral  virtues  the  mean  is  a  mean  of  Reason 
not  of  objects,  Medium  rationis  not  rei,  and  thus  the 
law  of  the  other  virtues  is  not  the  same  for  one  man  as 
for  another.  What  would  be  a  sin  in  one  man  might 
be  a  morally  good  act  in  another.  Temperance  and 
fortitude,  for  instance,  will  always  make  allowance  for 
needs  and  character.  But  the  law  of  justice  (in  the 
case,  for  instance,  of  bargaining)  is  that  we  pay  the  price 
of  what  we  buy — without  distinction  of  persons,  feelings, 
or  character. 

Aquinas  remarks  that  besides  the  moral  virtues  the 
intellectual  virtues  also  are  a  mean.*  Now,  the  intel- 
lectual virtues,  like  the  moral,  are  ordained  to  "  good." 
But  the  good  which  is  attained  by  the  intellectual 
virtue  is  truth,  according  to  which  the  mind  afhrms 
that  a  thing  is  which  is,  or  is  not  which  is  not.  Hence, 
the  mean  in  the  case  of  the  intellectual  virtues  is  their 
conformity  to  reality — excess  in  the  case  of  intellectual 
virtues  being  false  affirmation,  and  defect  false  negation. 
But  in  respect  of  this  mean  of  truth  and  its  relations  to 
the  virtue  of  which  it  is  a  mean  there  is  a  difference 
between   the   virtues   of  the   speculative   and   practical 

*  The  word  "  mean,"  it  seems  to  us,  is  used  in  reference  to  the 
intcllc:ctual  virtues  in  u  translerred  sense  onJy. 


6o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

intellects.  For  the  truth  of  the  speculative  intellect  is 
truth  absolutely.  But  the  truth  of  the  practical  intel- 
lect is  truth  in  regard  to  right  appetite,  it  being  the 
proper  function  of  the  practical  Reason  to  tell  what  is 
required  for  the  satisfaction  of  appetite.  Hence,  whilst 
in  regard  to  objects  or  reality  both  kinds  of  virtues — 
those  of  the  speculative  intellect  and  those  of  the 
practical — are  measured  by  reality,  since  both  must 
conform  to  truth,  the  virtues  of  the  practical  intellect 
are  also  themselves  a  measure  and  a  rule.  They  are 
the  measure  and  rule  of  appetites  and  of  their  proper 
satisfaction.* 

From  what  we  have  said  on  the  mean  of  Reason  we 
shall  be  able  to  understand  Aristotle's  definition  of 
virtue.  It  is  "  the  habit  of  fixing  the  choice  in  the 
golden  mean  in  relation  to  ourselves  defined  by  Reason 
as  a  prudent  man  would  define  it." 

.  Now,  as  we  said,  the  mean  of  a  virtue  is  a  mean 
I  which  is  based  on  the  law  of  Reason,  and,  therefore,  it 
is  founded  not  on  the  exigencies  of  any  particular 
moment  or  of  any  mere  part  of  man  ;  it  is  a  mean  in 
I  reference  to  our  whole  life  and  to  the  whole  man ;  for 
the  law  of  Reason  takes  account  of  the  whole  life  and 
the  whole  man.  Thus,  the  mean  of  liberality  is  cal- 
culated not  on  the  ground  of  our  present  possessions 
merely,  but  with  a  view  to  our  future  needs.  So  also 
the  mean  in  eating  and  drinking  is  not  the  mean  which 
will  suit  our  bodily  welfare  only,  but  the  mean  that 
suits  our  bodily  and  mental  welfare.  He  who  by 
drinking  alcohol  incapacitates  himself  for  thinking  is 
quite  as  intemperate  as  he  who  drinks  in  such  a  way  as 
to  impair  his  bodily  strength.  Hence,  the  golden  mean 
of  virtue  is  never  the  golden  mean  of  one  faculty  only, 
but  the  golden  mean  in  the  whole  man  and  of  our 
whole  life.  Consequently,  since  in  an  organism  "  much 
must  be  left  in  potentia,"  it  being  neither  necessary 
nor  good  that  every  part  of  the  organism  be  worked 
•  See  Vol.  II.,  page  Co. 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  609 

to  the  fullest  extent,  it  follows  that  the  golden  mean 
of  virtue  does  not  necessarily  imply  the  use  of  all  our 
faculties,  but  only  such  use  of  our  faculties  as  is  neces- 
sary for  human  perfection.  Thus,  there  is  no  law  im- 
pelling each  man  to  study  mathematics  or  to  prosecute 
music,  or  to  exercise  his  muscles,  or  to  continue  the 
race  (except  there  is  danger  of  its  disappe'arance). 
Special  reasons  apart,  any  man  is  free  to  refrain  from 
the  use  of  any  one  of  his  faculties,  provided  he  uses 
his  energies  sufficiently  in  other  ways  (it  is  manifest  uv 
that  we  must  use  our  energies  in  some  way,  for  every  ||[f——- 
man  is  bound  to  put  his  life  to  some  good  account). I(/' 
Nay,  if  for  any  worthy  reasons  a  man  abstains  from  the 
exercise  of  a  particular  faculty,  this  abstention  may  be 
itself  an  act  of  virtue.  Thus,  some  people  abstain  from 
drinking  wines  that  thereby  they  may  have  more  money 
for  their  children.  Some  spend  their  lives  in  study  and 
despise  all  material  enjoyments  in  order  that  they  may 
promote  the  ends  of  science.  Some  remain  unmarried 
that  they  may  be  able  to  serve  the  State  in  some  very 
special  capacity  which  the  duty  of  father  or  husband 
might  render  difhcult,  others  that  they  may  give  them- 
selves up  to  the  service  of  the  poor  and  be  free  to 
answer  their  "  come  hither  "  and  "  go  thither  " — a 
freedom  which  to  a  married  man  would  be  impossible ; 
<loT  the  father  belongs  to  his  wife  and  children  ;  and 
they,  and  not  the  poor,  have  the  first  claim  upon  his 
^time  and  attention.  Hence,  the  unmarried  state  is 
quite  in  accordance  with  the  mean  of  virtue.  And 
consequently,  though  family  ties  are  sacred  ties,  and 
though  the  duties  of  family  life  must  be  undertaken 
by  a  sufficient  number  to  secure  the  continuance  and 
welfare  of  the  race,  still  there  will  be  always  need  for 
the  larger  philanthropy  of  those  who  wish  to  abstain 
from  marriage  in  order  to  be  in  a  position  to  undertake 
those  great  and  self-sacrificing  works  which  only  the 
free  and  unfettered  man  can  undertake.  Again,  we 
repeat,  though  virtue  consists  in  a  mean,  this  mean  is 
Vol.  1—39 


lisy 


6io  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  be  judged  in  reference  to  our  whole  life  and  to  the 
whole  organism.  It  does  not  imply  the  exercise  of  every 
power  in  the  organism,  much  less  does  it  imply  the 
exercise  of  all  the  powers  at  each  moment.* 

(5)  Enumeration  of  the  Moral  virtues. \ 

In  enumerating  the  moral  virtues  it  is  important  that 
we  should  select  a  proper  basis  of  division  in  order, 
first,  to  avoid  overlapping  and  consequent  repetitions 
and  omissions ;  and,  secondly,  in  order  that  our 
enumeration  may  be  sensible  and  serviceable,  as  an 
enumeration  of  the  moral  virtues  ought  to  be. 

The  following  is  Aquinas'  deduction  of  Aristotle's  list  of 
moral  virtues.  The  moral  virtues  are  of  two  kinds — those, 
namely,  which  have  to  do  with  our  actions  and  those  that 
deal  with  the  passions.  Only  one  virtue  refers  primarily 
to  actions,  viz.,  Justice,  and  so  we  may  proceed  immediately 
to  the  enumerating  of  the  others.  Some  may  think  that 
an  easy  method  of  enumerating  the  virtues  that  deal  with 
the  passions  would  be  that  of  enumerating  the  passions 
themselves.  But  this  method  would  not  give  us  a  true  result, 
because  the  number  of  the  passions  could  not  possibly  be 
the  same  as  the  number  of  virtues  that  deal  with  the  passions. 
For  the  passions  dwell  in  the  sensuous  appetite,  whilst  the 
virtues  dwell  in  the  rational  appetite.  It  is  quite  impossible, 
therefore,  that  each  passion  should  correspond  to  a  single 
virtue.  The  passions  are  divided  "  according  to  their  object, 
in  relation,  however,  to  the  sensitive  appetite,"  whilst  the 
virtues  are  divided  "  according  to  their  object,  but  in  relation 
to  Reason."  And  so  it  is  quite  possible  that  there  should 
be  many  virtues  controlling  a  single  passion  and  many 
passions  controlled  by  a  single  virtue.  For  instance,  the 
single  virtue  of  temperance  controls  the  passion  for  drink, 
the  sexual,  and  several  other  passions ;  whilst  several 
virtues  control  the  single  passion  of  delight  or  of  hatred. 
The  proper  basis  of  enumeration,  therefore,  cannot  be  the 

•  See  Vol  II.  p.  391,  note. 

t  The  reader  should,  before  beginning  this  list  of  the  virtues,  be 
careful  to  understand  the  distinction  on  which  so  much  turns  in  the 
present  enquiry,  between  the  irascflile  and  concupiscible  sensuous 
apjHJtitc.  The  second  appetite  tcntls  to  the  enjoyment  of  any  sensuous 
end.  The  first  tends  to  the  overcoming  of  the  dillicullies  incident  to 
any  end. 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  6ii 

enumeration  of  the  passions  themselves.  But  we  have 
already  indicated  the  proper  ground  of  division — namely, 
the  objects  of  the  passions  in  relation  to  Reason. 

The  general  object  of  the  passions  is  the  "  good  "  of  some 
sort ;  but  the  "  good  "  can  be  apprehended  either  by  (I.)  the 
bodily  senses  or  by  (II.)  our  interior  powers  of  perception, 
(I,)  Now,  the  only  bodily  sense  that  has  a  special  passion  of 
its  own,  is  the  sense  of  touch.*  There  is  no  passion  of 
seeing,  or  hearing,  or  smelling,  or  tasting,  since  these 
faculties  never  tend  to  get  out  of  the  control  of  Reason. 
But  the  passion  of  touch  requires  two  separate  virtues  for 
its  control,  one  to  restrain  it  from  going  too  far,  one  to  em- 
bolden it  to  go  far  enough.  These  virtues  are — Temperance 
and  Fortitude.  These  two  virtues  have  to  do  with  outer 
pleasures  and  pains  f— temperance  with  the  pleasures  of 
eating,  drinking,  etc.,  fortitude  with  the  pains  of  the  body, 
and  death.  All  such  pleasures  and  pains  are  pleasures  and 
pains  of  touch.  We  now  come  (II.)  to  goods  which  are 
perceived  by  our  inner  powers  alone.  These  are  called  goods 
of  the  inner  man,  because  no  outer  sense  can  perceive  them. 
No  outer  sense,  e.g.,  can  enjoy  honour  or  riches  as  such. 
These  things  we  enjoy  inwardly  alone.  Now,  the  goods  of 
the  inner  man  are  thus  enumerated.  They  are  either  (a), 
such  as  will  perfect  a  man  in  himself  personally  or  {0)  perfect 
him  in  relation  to  his  surroundings.  The  first  of  these  two 
divisions  yields  us  four  distinct  virtues,  the  second  also  four, 
(a)  Either  the  perfection  that  is  personal  to  me  is  a  good  of 
the  body  like  riches,  or  a  good  of  the  soul  like  honour.  If  of 
the  body,  then  two  virtues  are  necessary  to  its  proper  use — 
first,  liberality  in  the  giving  of  what  I  have,  even  though  it 
be  small,  and  magnificence  in  giving  out  according  to  the 
measure  of  Reason  large  sums  of  money  which  naturally  I 
shrink  from  parting  with.  The  first  dwells  in  the  con- 
cupiscible  appetite,  which  tends  to  hold  what  it  has  ;  the 
second  in  the  irascible,  for  we  tend  to  shrink  from  anything 
really  great,  J  the  "  great  "  being  always  apprehended  as  a 


*  The  word  "  touch  "  is  here  used  in  its  broadest  signification. 

t  The  virtue  that  enables  us  to  face  opposition  and  contempt  of 
friends  is  sometimes  called  fortitude.  It  really  is  not  fortitude  but 
magnanimity. 

X  It  is  evident  from  observation  that  the  virtue  of  liberality 
is  quite  different  from  that  of  maf^'nificence.  Many  rich  men  are 
liberal  without  being  magnificent.  The  two  classes  differ  not  merely 
in  degree  but  in  their  very  actuating  ideas.  Magnificence,  however, 
is  not  to  be  confounded  with  profligate  liberality,  for  even  magiuficence 
should  be  according  to  Reason, 


6i2  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

difficulty.  On  the  other  hand,  the  good  that  perfects  a 
man  in  himself  may  be  a  good  of  the  soul,  like  honour.  Now 
just  as  in  the  case  of  goods  of  the  bod\',  so  also  in  the  case 
of  honour,*  two  virtues  are  required,  one  which  makes  a 
man  seek  all  the  honour  he  deserves,  but  in  ordinary  matters 
(which  virtue  is  without  a  name ;  let  us  call  it  by  the  name 
of  the  extreme  to  which  it  is  most  allied,  viz.  philotomia  f )  : 
the  other  magnanimity  by  which  we  claim  deserved  honour  but 
on  a  large  scale.  This  completes  the  list  of  virtues  under  the 
heading  "  personal  good."  Then  (^)  there  is  the  social 
good.  The  good  that  appertains  to  my  social  nature — i.e., 
the  good  which  manifests  itself  in  my  dealings  with  other 
men — is  either  such  as  is  yielded  with  a  serious  purpose  or 
it  is  such  as  belongs  to  the  lighter  amenities  of  life,  in  the 
way  of  plays,  jokes,  music,  and  convivialities  of  all  sorts. 
To  the  second  belongs  the  particular  virtue  called  Eutrapcleia, 
by  which  a  man  is  enabled  so  to  act  in  his  dealings  with  others 
as  to  make  lighter  the  burden  of  life  for  other  men,  and,  at 
the  same  time,  not  pander  to  man's  baser  nature.  The  first, 
or  the  serious  social  good,  yields  three  virtues  according  as 
t  we  will  to  do  others  a  positive  good  (which  is  friendship)  or 
to  make  things  pleasant  for  them  in  their  dealings  with  us 
{affability  or  meekness),  or  merely  to  express  our  thoughts  to 
them  in  a  due  manner  {truth). X  These  eleven  form  Aristotle's 
well  known  table  of  the  moral  virtues — "  Justice,  temperance, 
fortitude,  liberality,  magnificence,  magnanimity,  philotomia, 
meekness  or  affability,  friendship,  truth,  and  pleasantry." 

The  other  virtues — prudence,  wisdom,  etc. — are  intellectual 
virtues,  not  moral.  Of  some  of  these  moral  virtues  we  shall 
have  to  say  a  good  deal  presently.  But  we  must  now  say 
one  word  on  the  last  of  these  moral  virtues,  which  of  the 
whole  eleven  is,  perhaps,  the  least  understood. 

EuTRAPELEiA  §    or    "  pleasantry "    is    that    virtue    which 

[enables  a  man  by  means  of  his  own  manner,  conversation, 

iietc.,  to  make  lighter  the  burden  of  life  for  self  and  for  others, 

I  without  in  any  way  pandering  to  man's  baser  nature.     This 

virtue  principally  regards  the  happiness  of  others.     It  comes 

of  two  joint  sources — lightness  of  heart  and  benevolence. 

•  It  should  be  remembered  that  honour  in  the  Aristotelian 
sense  is  not  the  same  as  inner  honesty  or  truthfulness,  but  rather  the 
honour  that  others  pay  us.     It  is  quite  external. 

t  It  is  ambition  in  the  domain  of  honour,  but  short  of  great  honour. 

I  Truth  especially  in  regard  to  ourselves  or  sincerity  with  ourselves. 
It  is  opposed  to  boastfulne.ss  and  undue  self -depreciation.  The  truthful 
man  is  always  himself  (ai'OiK&crros  t«s). 

§  The  word  is  sumctimus  translated  playfulness,  sometimes  wit. 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  613 

All  good  is  diffusive  of  itself,  and  Eutrapeleia  is  a  special 
kind  of  goodness  which  inclines  us  to  make  other  people 
happy,  not  by  the  giving  of  gift^,  but  by  a  communicating 
of  our  own  personal  happiness  to  them  in  pleasant  conversa- 
tion and  amusements.  For  we  cheer  others  by  expressing 
our  own  cheer  provided  we  choose  the  right  time,  place,  and 
circumstances.  But  Eutrapeleia,  like  other  virtues,  is  a 
mean  between  extremes.  Its  act,  pleasantry — the  pleasantry 
of  good  cheer — is  a  mean  between  the  buffoonery  of  the  loud 
and  vulgar  man  and  the  ill-humour  of  the  sour  man.  It  is 
just  as  far  apart  from  indecency  as  it  is  from  prudishness ; 
for  though  its  end  is  to  make  things  pleasant,  it  must  be 
always  under  the  control  of  Reason,  and  always  takes  account 
of  circumstances,  persons,  and  times.  Speaking  positively, 
it  is  the  easy  pleasantry  of  the  man  who  wishes  to  see  the 
whole  world  gay,  but  recognises  at  the  same  time  that  gaiety 
is  only  one  side  of  our  life,  and  that  it  can  tire  as  well  as 
exhilarate.  The  over-jocular  man  is  second  only  to  the 
sour  man,  for  the  over-jocular  man  bores  by  his  buffoonery, 
whilst  sour  people,  to  use  Aristotle's  severe  description, 
"  are  for  all  pleasant  intercourse  wholly  unfit,  inasmuch  as, 
contributing  nothing  jocose  of  their  own,  they  are  savage 
with  all  who  do."  Between  buffoonery  and  sourness  stands 
the  virtue  of  Eutrapeleia  or  pleasantry. 

(d)  The  Cardinal  Virtues  ♦ 

(i)  The  traditional  enumeration  of  the  cardinal  virtues 
has  come  down  to  us  from  Plato.  They  are  prudence, 
justice,  fortitude,  and  temperance.  They  are  called 
cardinal  because  (i)  they  are  the  principal  virtues  or 
heads  of  virtues,  (2)  because  to  a  certain  extent  there 
can  be  no  single  virtu(i  without  them.  So  fundamental 
are  they  that  some  philosophers  have  considered  these 
four  not  as  distinct  virtues,  but  rather  as  general  con- 
ditions of  soul  produced  by  and  necessary  to  all  the 
[I  other    particular    virtues.     Thus,    they    have    regarded 

*  We  see  no  good  reason  why  we  should  depart  from  this  time- 
honoured  enumeration.  Whewell  noticetj  five  Cardinal  virtues — (i) 
Benevolence,  (2)  Justice,  (3)  Truth,  (4)  Purity  {i.e.,  the  due  subjection 
of  the  passions  and  sentiments  to  one  another),  (5)  Order,  or  love  of 
law.  Socrates  reduces  all  to  wisdom  ;  the  Egoists  to  prudence  or  self- 
love  ;  others  to  the  self-regarding  virtues  (temperance,  prudence 
courage)  and  the  extra-regarding  (benevolence  and  truth). 


^ 


6i4 .  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Prudence  not  as  a  special  virtue  but  as  general  discre- 
tion, without  which  there  can  be  no  virtue,  Justice  as 
general  observance  of  duty,  Temperance  as  general 
moderation,  and  Fortitude  as  general  strength  and 
endurance  of  soul.  Now,  if  these  four  be  only  general 
and  not  special  virtues  it  is  plain  that  though  Prudence 
must  be  distinct  from  the  other  three  (since  it  dwells  in 
the  intellect — they  in  the  will),  yet  those  other  three 
cannot  be  distinct  from  one  another,  but  will  be  simply 
parts  of  that  single  quality  of  the  soul  which  we  might 
call  its  moral  soundness.  But  inasmuch  as  we  regard 
these  virtues  as  distinct  from  one  another,  we  regard 
them  also  as  special  virtues,  and  not  merely  as  general 
characteristics  of  the  perfect  soul. 

(2)  Enumeration  of  the  cardinal  virtues. 

Virtue  gives  a  man  a  readiness  to  act  rationally,  and 
it  resides  in  such  powers  as  come  under  the  control  of 
Reason.  In  this  the  virtues  are  different  from  the 
passions,  which  have  their  seat  in  the  sensuous  appetite 
quite  irrespective  of  its  control  by  Reason. 

Now,  in  man  there  are  four  distinct  rational  powers 
having  reference  to  conduct — (i)  The  practical  Reason 
itself,  (2)  the  rational  will,  (3)  the  concupiscible  appetite, 
(4)  the  irascible  appetite.  All  four  are  rational.  For 
the  first  is  Reason  itself,  and  the  other  three  come 
under  the  control  of  Reason — they  are  rational  by  par- 
ticipation. Now,  corresponding  to  these  four  powers 
we  must  have  four  distinct  capital  virtues.  They  are 
prudence,  justice,  temperance,  and  fortitude,  the  first 
enabhng  Reason  to  discover  the  acts  that  lead  on  to  the 
last  end  ;  the  second  determining  the  will  to  seek  the 
good  which  is  due  to  others  ;  the  third  restraining  the 
wanton  rush  of  concupiscence  after  pleasure  ;  the  fourth 
encouraging  a  man  to  be  bold  when  otherwise  he  would 
figlit  shy  of  difficulties. 

It  may  be  asked  why  do  we  dcinand  t)iil)-  one  \Jrtue 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  615 

for  will — namely,  the  virtue  which  perfects  it  in  relation 
to  others.  We  answer  because  we  do  not  need  to  be 
inspired  by  virtue  to  seek  our  own  good  and  pleasure, 
but  we  do  need  virtue  in  order  to  be  just  to  others. 

This  enumeration,  it  will  be  seen,  is  based  upon  the 
consideration  of  the  subjective  powers  in  which  the 
several  virtues  reside.  The  same  result  is  reached  when 
we  take  as  ground  the  objects  of  the  virtues  instead  of 
the  powers  in  which  they  reside.  The  one  object  of 
the  several  virtues  is  the  good  of  Reason — the  good, 
namely,  which  Reason  secures  to  us  in  relation  to  action 
or  to  conduct.  Now,  such  good  is  either  (i)  the  act  of 
Reason  itself,  and  the  virtue  which  directs  the  Reason 
in  reference  to  its  own  acts — that  is,  the  virtue  which 
has  as  its  object  the  acts  of  Reason  is  prudence — or 
(2)  the  objects  of  the  acts  of  Reason.  These  also  are 
objects  of  the  virtues.  But  the  objects  of  the  acts  of 
Reason,  so  far  as  conduct  is  concerned,  are  either  our 
outward  acts  or  our  inner  passions.  For  external  action 
we  have  the  virtue  of  justice.  For  the  inner  passions 
we  must  have  two  virtues,  one  to  restrain  passion  from 
hurrying  us  on  to  wish  what  Reason  forbids — namely, 
temperance — controlling  the  concupiscible  appetite,  and 
one  to  keep  the  passion  from  unduly  holding  us  back 
when  Reason  impels  us  forward — namely.  Fortitude — 
directing  the  irascible.  Temperance  restrains  our  head- 
long desires,  fortitude  conquers  apprehensiveness  and 
over-timidity.  This  gives  us  the  same  four  virtues  that 
we  have  already'  deduced. 

Whether  these  methods  of  deduction  are  persuasive 
or  not  the  reader  may  judge  for  himself,  but  it  is 
certain  that  they  do  bring  out  the  importance  of  the 
four  virtues  in  question  by  emphasising  their  se\-eral 
functions  in  relation  to  conduct.  That  these  four 
virtues  have  a  special  and  a  most  important  bearing  on 
human  conduct  no  one,  we  think,  will  be  disposed  to 
deny,  and,  therefore,  it  is  necessary  to  say  a  word  about 
each    of    them    in    particular.     On    prudence    we    have 


6i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

nothing  to  add  to  what  we  have  written  already  in  the 
early  portions  of  the  chapter. 

{e)  On  Temperance 

(i)  The  virtue  of  temperance  controls  us  in  the  pur- 
suit of  pleasures.  Just  as  without  desires  and  some 
pleasure  we  could  not  live  at  all,  so  if  pleasure  and 
desire  get  beyond  the  control  of  Reason  our  life  ceases 
to  be  a  human  life.  Temperance  moderates  our  desires 
and  our  search  for  pleasure  and  inclines  us  to  a  life 
according  to  Reason.  In  one  sense  temperance  is  a 
property  of  every  virtue,  for  every  virtue  consists  in 
the  mean  of  Reason,  which  is  the  temperate  pursuit  of 
ends.  But  there  is  also  a  special  virtue  of  temperance 
with  a  special  subject-matter,  the  purpose  of  which  is 
to  restrain  us  in  the  use  of  those  pleasure  that  draw 
our  wiUs  most  strongly — namely,  the  pleasures  of  touch, 
or  what  are  known  as  organic  pleasures.  These  pleasures 
are  such  as  appertain  to  preservation  either  of  the 
individual  or  of  the  race ;  and  from  the  nature  and  im- 
portance of  the  end  to  which  these  pleasures  are  allied, 
they  are  in  the  design  of  nature  made  difficult  of  re- 
sistance, and  hence  the  control  of  them  requires  to  be 
effected  by  a  special  virtue — that  of  temperance. 

Ordinarily,  we  need  no  virtue  to  impel  us  to  the 
pursuit  of  pleasure.  Our  need  is  to  restrain  the  desire 
for  too  much  delight,  and  hence  the  essential  function 
of  temperance  is  to  restrain  this  desire.  The  virtue  of 
temperance  is  itself  a  mean  between  insensibility  to 
pleasure  on  the  one  hand  and  gluttony  and  lust  on  the 
other. 

Gluttony  and  lust  are  evidently  evil  because  they 
mean  excess  in  pleasure.  But  "  insensibility "  to 
pleasure  is  also  evil  because  nature  herself  has  attached 
delights  to  those  acts  that  are  necessary  for  human  life, 
and,  therefore,  the  natural  order  requires  that  a  man 
should  use  these  pleasures  in  so  far  as  they  are  necessary 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  617 

to  his  own  life  or  the  Hfe  of  the  race.*  Now,  a  man  can 
only  maintain  his  own  life  by. his  own  acts,  and,  there- 
fore, every  man  should  seek  some  of  the  pleasures  at- 
taching to  the  preservation  of  his  own  life.  But  the 
life  of  the  race  does  not  require  the  co-operation  of  all 
men  but  only  of  a  certain  number,  and  hence  a  man  is 
not  bound,  except  under  exceptional  circumstances,  to 
seek  those  organic  pleasures  which  attach  to  the  main- 
tenance of  the  race. 

(2)  The  parts  of  temperance. 

The  parts  of  any  virtue,  as  we  have  already  pointed 
out  in  the  case  of  prudence,  are  three-fold — the  integral 
parts  or  those  conditions  of  mind  that  constitute  the 
virtue,  the  subjective  parts  or  its  subordinate  kinds,  the 
potential  parts  or  those  secondary  virtues  which  secure 
the  same  observance  of  law  in  the  less  important  and 
less  difficult  things  which  the  principal  virtue  secures  in 
regard  to  its  principal  subject-matter. 

The  integral  parts  of  temperance  are  shame  [vere- 
cundia),  which  inclines  us  to  avoid  the  disgrace  of  intem- 
perance ;  and  sense  of  propriety  {honestas),  which 
induces  a  love  of  the  beauty  of  temperance. 

The  subjective  parts  of  temperance  are  abstinence, 
chastity,  and  reserve  [pudicentia] . 

Of  the  potential  parts,  some  regard  the  interior  acts 
of  the  mind — namely,  continence,  humility,  meekness — 
some  affect  the  outwards  act — for  instance,  modesty — 
some  affect  not  exterior  acts  but  exterior  goods — namely, 
frugality  and  simplicity.  Of  these  various  parts  of 
temperance  three  require  to  be  defined — namely, 
humility,  modesty,  and  meekness,  (i)  Humility  means 
the  true  estimate  of  our  own  worth,  as,  first  of  all, 
having  nothing  of  ourselves  ;  but,  secondl}',  as  having 
a   great    deal    from    God.     Humilit\',    therefore,    is    the 

*  The  law  or  norm  of  temperance  is  thus  constituted  by  the  natural 
ends  of  the  faculties  in  question.     See  Vol.  11.,  page  59. 


6i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

source  and  spring  of  true  human  dignity,  for  though 
by  it  we  are  led  to  rate  ourselves  as  nothing  in  one 
respect,  we  are  in  another  made  conscious  of  the  great 
place  we  occupy  in  the  Universe  as  men,  and  conscious 
also  that,  having  our  own  individual  responsibilities, 
we  have  also  our  own  individual  rights  as  against  the 
rest  of  the  race.  Humility  puts  no  man  in  a  false 
position  in  the  world,  for  the  simple  reason  that  humility 
must  above  all  things  be  true.  It  moves  us  to  a  low 
opinion  of  ourselves  in  regard  to  what  is  from  ourselves  ; 
and  comparing  what  is  in  us  of  ourselves  with  what  is 
in  other  men  from  God,  it  bids  us  consider  ourselves 
lower  than  other  men.  But  then,  as  Aquinas  remarks, 
"  humility  does  not  require  that  we  regard  that  in 
ourselves  which  is  from  God  as  lower  than  that  which 
seems  to  be  of  God  in  other  men."  Humility  cuts  no 
man  out  from  the  race  for  life  and  the  goods  of  life,  but 
it  bids  him  know  that  what  he  wins  there  belongs  to 
Another  as  well  as  to  himself.  (2)  Modesty  is  the 
outward  sign  of  inward  temperance  of  mind  and  heart. 
(3)  Meekness  is  the  temperate  use  of  anger  and  of  the 
law  of  punishment.  It  inclines  us  to  be  dignified  and 
self-possessed  under  insult,  not  out  of  contempt  or 
pride,  but  because  it  is  good  for  us  to  restrain  our  animal 
nature,  so  that  when  moved  to  anger  we  may  be  able 
to  act  prudently  with  others,  and  upbraid  or  punish 
them  according  to  Reason.* 

(/)  On  Fortitude 

(i)  Fortitude  is  the  virtue  which  braces  the  soul 
courageously  to  face  grave  dangers,  and  particularly 
our  greatest  earthly  evil — death.  Only  he  who  faces 
death   boldly   can   be   called   brave  absolutely,   for,   as 

•  How  far  the  supernatural  are  beyond  these  natural  virtues  will 
easily  be  seen  in  connection  with  these  three  virtues  of  Humility, 
Modesty,  and  Meekness.  The  supernatural  lifts  them  into  a  plane 
that  is  altogether  above  unaided  human  Reason.  It  is  the  super- 
natural that  supplies  us  with  our  highest  ideals  of  conduct  as  well  as 
with  our  saints  and  heroes. 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  619 

Aquinas  says,  the  only  effect  which  a  virtue  properly 
regards  is  its  highest  effect  "  ad  rationem  virtutis  per- 
tinet  ut  respiciat  ultimum." 

But  bravery  in  meeting  death  is  not  always  the  out- 
come of  the  virtue  of  fortitude,  for  fortitude  implies 
that  we  go  to  meet  death  for  the  sake  of  forwarding 
some  good  cause.  Hence,  it  is  not  always  fortitude 
proper  that  sustains  us  in  sickness,  or  in  the  stress  of 
storm,  or  when  attacked  by  robbers.  But  it  is  fortitude 
that  leads  a  soldier  to  battle  and  that  sustains  the  martyr 
on  the  rack.  However,  every  willing  sacrifice  that  is 
made  for  the  sake  of  good  falls  somewhere  within  the 
domain  of  fortitude. 

The  acts  of  fortitude  are  two-fold — sufferance  [sus- 
tinere)  and  aggression.  And,  since  it  is  a  more  difficult 
thing  to  repress  fear  than  to  restrain  daring,  therefore, 
sufferance  is  the  principal  of  the  two  acts  of  fortitude. 
Sufferance  is  more  difficult  than  aggression  for  other 
reasons  also.  For  in  sufferance  our  enemy  is  regarded 
as  the  stronger,  in  aggression  we  regard  ourselves  as 
the  stronger,  and  it  is  more  difficult  to  defy  strength 
than  weakness.  In  sufferance  the  evil  has  actually 
come  upon  us  or  is  imminent,  in  aggression  the  evil  is 
still  in  the  future.  Sufferance  is  ordinarily  a  prolonged 
evil,  aggression  may  consist  in  a  single  attack.  Conse- 
quently, sufferance  is  more  difficult  than  aggression, 
and  is  the  principal  act  of  fortitude. 

Again,  fortitude  is  all  the  greater  the  more  sudden  the 
danger  to  be  faced.  Indeed,  it  is  onl}'  in  the  case  of 
sudden  danger  that  we  can  be  certain  whether  it  is 
fortitude  that  sustains  us.  For  when  danger  arises  on 
a  sudden  it  can  only  be  the  habitual  virtue  of  fortitude 
that  actuates  us,  whereas  even  a  coward,  if  he  gets 
time  enough,  can  prepare  his  mind  to  face  a  grave 
danger. 

Some  men  think  that  only  he  is  brave  who  delights 
in  danger  and  pain.  But  this  is  a  mistaken  notion.  A 
man   may   be   actuated   by    fortitude   and   yet    feel   no 


620  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

delight  in  his  act.  Such  a  man  will,  no  doubt,  ex- 
perience delight  in  the  thought  of  the  cause  he  is  pro- 
moting ;  but,  on  the  other  hand,  he  may  inwardly 
grieve  or  be  sad  at  the  loss  he  is  himself  willingly  sus- 
taining, and  if  this  loss  should  be  accompanied  by  bodil}^ 
pain  this  latter  may  even  drive  out  of  our  consciousness 
all  delight  arising  from  the  thought  of  the  cause  for 
which  we  are  fighting.  And  if  fortitude  does  not  neces- 
sarily exclude  sadness  so  neither  does  it  necessarily 
exclude  anger.  On  the  contrary,  a  moderate  anger 
will  promote  the  ends  of  fortitude,  for  anger  helps  ag- 
gression. And  through  anger  even  sadness  may  be  a 
help  to  fortitude.  For  though  of  itself  sadness  tends  to 
diminish  fortitude  by  increasing  fear,  sadness  will  also 
excite  a  man  to  righteous  anger,  which  is  an  aid  to  ag- 
gi'ession.  On  another  score,  also,  anger  may  be  an  aid 
to  fortitude,  for  anger  makes  life  itself  seem  less  worth 
living  for,  and  it  is  thereby  calculated  to  increase 
"  daring." 

(2)  The  parts  of  fortitude. 

We  repeat  that  the  parts  of  a  moral  virtue  can  be 
either  subjective,  integral,  or  potential  parts.  Now, 
fortitude  does  not  admit  of  subjective  parts — i.e.,  of 
different  kinds  of  fortitude — in  the  braving  of  death. 
But  we  may  distinguish  integral  and  potential  parts  of 
fortitude — integral — that  is,  the  elements  that  go  to 
make  up  fortitude — and  potential  or  annexed  virtues — 
that  is,  those  lesser  virtues  which  play  the  same  rdle 
in  regard  to  less  difficult  spheres  of  action  that  fortitude 
proper  plays  as  regards  the  most  difficult  of  all  acts — the 
facing  of  death. 

The  acts  of  fortitude  are,  as  we  have  said  already, 
aggression  and  sufferance.  Now,  aggression  demands 
two  habits  of  mind.  One  a  liabit  that  prepares  the 
mind  for  aggression — namely,  confidence  (fiducia) — tlic 
other  a  habit  that  perfects  the  work  of  aggression  once 
begun — namely,  magniliccnce  or  the  virtue  which  enables 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  621 

us  to  fling  away  or  risk  goods  of  great  price  than  which 
none  is  greater  than  hfe  itself.  These  are  the  two 
integral  parts  of  fortitude  regarded  as  an  aggression. 
But  these  or  similar  which  are  integral  parts  of  fortitude 
in  regard  to  the  greatest  of  evils — death — are  annexed 
virtues  or  potential  parts  of  it  when  they  regard  some 
lesser  evil.  Thus  magnificence  can  be  a  potential  part 
in  so  far  as  it  appertains  to  the  spending  of  money, 
magnanimity  in  so  far  as  fortitude  enables  us  to  despise 
unmerited  honour. 

The  second  act  of  fortitude  is  siifjerancc,  which  has 
two  integral  parts,  one  of  which  counteracts  the  effects 
of  sadness,  which  of  itself  would  tend  to  lower  our 
courage.  This  is  the  virtue  of  patience.  The  other 
sustains  us  in  the  long  struggle  against  bodily  mis- 
fortune lest  we  become  worn  out  and  yield — namely, 
perseverance.  These  same  two  virtues  when  they  con- 
cern the  lesser  evils  are  potential  parts  of  fortitude. 

Fortitude  is  a  mean  between  cowardice  and  reckless- 
ness ;  yet  the  mean  of  fortitude  may  often  even  border 
on  recklessness,  or,  rather,  what  would  be  recklessness 
in  some  circumstances  would  be  fortitude-  in  others. 
We  may  in  Reason  risk  more  the  greater  the  good  that 
is  being  promoted. 

[g)  On  Justice 

(i)  Plato  defines  Justice  as  the  perfect  harmony  of 
all  the  powers  of  the  soul.  As  so  defined  Justice  is 
simply  co-extensive  with  the  "  good."  The  Aristotelian, 
and  Scholastic  conception  of  Justice  is  quite  different 
from  this  ;  for,  with  these  latter.  Justice  is  a  special 
virtue  with  a  special  subject-matter  distinct  from  that 
of  the  other  virtues.  Aquinas  defines  Justice  as  "  the 
constant  will   to  give  to  everyone  his  own."  *     It  is, 

*  "  Perpetua  et  constans  voluntas  jus  suum  unicuique  tribuendi." 
"  Perpetua  "  is  here  meant  to  refer  to  the  object  of  the  voluntas  rather 
than  to  the  voluntas  itself — that  is,  it  is  the  will  permanently  to  rcndiir, 
etc.  "  Voluntas  "  in  this  definition  refers,  as  Aquinas  explains,  to  the 
act,,  not  to  the  faculty,  of  will. 


622  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

therefore,  a  special  virtue,  and  its  special  subject-matter 
is  our  exterior  acts  in  relation  to  other  people.  All 
Justice  is  "  ad  alterum."  Its  end  is  to  secure  right 
social  relations  between  one  person  and  another.  It 
obtains  between  equals  as  the  word  "  Justice  "  itself 
indicates,  and  hence  it  is  only  in  a  metaphorical  sense 
that  we  can  speak  of  Justice  as  governing  the  relations 
of  a  man  with  himself — that  is,  as  governing  the  parts 
of  man  in  their  relation  to  one  another  and  to  the  whole 
person. 

Justice  resides  in  the  appetite,  not  in  the  knowing 
faculties,  for  its  end  is  not  knowledge  but  action — ^the 
just  man  is  one  who  gives  what  is  due,  not  one  who 
knows  what  is  due.  And  the  appetite  in  which  it  re- 
sides is  the  will,  not  the  sensuous  appetite,  for  sense 
does  not  apprehend  the  relation  of  moral  equality  be- 
tween one  person  and  another. 

Though  Justice  is  a  special  virtue,  still  there  is  a 
sense  in  which  it  is  a  general  virtue  including  every 
virtue.  For  the  individual  man  is  a  part  of  society, 
and  whatever  redounds  to  his  good  benefits  society 
also  indirectly,  and,  vice  versa,  any  virtue  that  benefits 
society  benefits  the  parts  of  society  or  the  individuals. 
'So,  every  virtue,  since  it  benefits  someone,  benefits 
society  of  which  that  person  is  a  part.  Hence,  "  all 
virtue  is  in  Justice  comprehended,"  and  it  is  in  this 
sense  that  Aristotle  defines  Justice  as  "  every  virtue." 
As  directing  the  acts  of  all  the  virtues  to  the  common 
good,  justice  is  a  "  general  virtue,"  in  which  sense  we 
call  it  "  legal  justice."  But  besides  this  general  virtue 
of  Justice  there  is  a  particular  virtue  of  Justice  which 
directly  and  immediatel}'  regulates  the  dealings  of  one 
person  with  ancrther,  and  it  is  in  this  sense  that  we 
speak  of  Justice  in  the  present  chapter. 

Now,  men  are  related  to  one  another  not  by  their 
inner  passions  but  by  external  actions  and  by  objects, 
and  hence  the  subject-matter  of  Justice  is  not  the  same 
as  lliat  of  the  other  virtues — namely,  the  interior  pas- 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  623 

sions — but  outer  acts  and  objects.  These  it  regulates 
according  to  the  natural  laws  of  society.  And  since 
Justice  concerns  outer  actions  and  objects,  not  our 
inner  passions,  the  mean  of  virtue  which  is  secured  in 
the  case  of  Justice  has  no  dependence  on  inner  passions. 
It  is  a  medium,  not  rationis,  but  rei.  Thus,  the  mean  of 
Justice  in  the  case  of  buying  and  selling  is  the  price  of 
the  object  bought,  and  this  is  the  same  for  every  man, 
no  matter  what  may  be  his  inner  feelings.  The  mean 
of  the  other  moral  virtues  like  Temperance  and  Forti- 
tude is  different  for  different  persons. 

(2)  The  parts  of  Justice. 

As  in  the  case  of  the  other  virtues,  we  must  distinguish 
between  the  subjective,  the  integral,  and  the  potential 
parts  or  annexed  virtues  of  Justice  also. 

The  stibjedive  parts  of  justice. 

The  subjective  parts  of  Justice,  or  its  subordinate 
species,  are  two — Commutative  and  Distributive  Justice. 
Commutative  Justice  regulates  the  dealings  of  one  person 
with  another.  Distributive  Justice  regulates  the  deal- 
ings of  society  with  the  individual.  Distributive  Justice 
is  "  exercised  by  the  whole  community  through  its  head 
to  the  members,"  its  special  function  being  to  secure 
proper  distribution  of  those  goods  that  are  common  by 
nature  amongst  the  various  members  of  the  State, 
according  to  the  merits  of  individuals  and  the  require- 
ments of  the  State.  Distributive  Justice  secures  fair 
play  and  proper  treatment  for  subjects,  and  also  equality 
so  far  as  the  requirements  of  State  allow.  It  is  the  pre- 
ventative against  favouritism,  one-sided  laws,  unequal 
taxation,  maladministration  of  funds,  and  those  other 
political  evils  to  which  a  ruler  may  be  inclined  either 
through  personal  likings  and  weaknesses,  or  skilful  wire- 
pulling, or  through  the  dependence  of  a  sovereign  on 
the  good  will  of  certain  classes  of  his  subjects. 


624  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

The  strict  conception  of  Justice  is  realised  only  in  the 
case  of  Commutative  Justice,  for  only  in  the  case  of 
Commutative  Justice  is  there  a  plurality  of  persons  (the 
relations  of  Distributive  Justice  being  rather  those  of 
whole  to  part  than  of  one  person  to  another),  and  only 
in  the  case  of  Commutative  Justice  is  there  equality 
between  the  parties.  But  Commutative  Justice  can 
obtain  between  States  as  well  as  between  individuals, 
for  States,  like  individuals,  are  many,  and  in  their 
capacity  as  perfect  societies  they  are  equal  to,  and 
independent  of,  one  another. 

Commutative  Justice  is  so  called  because  it  concerns 
contracts  or  exchanges  {commutationes) .  These  con- 
tracts are  either  voluntary  or  involuntary.  The  ex- 
pression "  voluntary  contract,"  need  not  be  explained. 
An  involuntary  contract  takes  place  when  one  man 
injures  another,  for  by  injuring  another  we  take  a  good 
from  him,  and  this  act  binds  us  to  restitution  in  the 
same  way  that  the  bargaining  in  a  voluntary  contract 
binds  us  to  pay  for  what  we  have  received. 

The  integral  parts  of  Justice. 

Since  Justice  concerns  outer  actions,  not  inner  pas- 
sions, the  full  law  of  justice  is  to  pay  what  is  owed. 
Hence,  we  cannot,  as  in  the  case  of  the  other  virtues, 
speak  of  the  integral  parts  of  Justice — that  is,  of  those 
dispositions  that  make  up  the  perfect  virtue.  The  one 
integral  constituent  that  makes  up  the  perfect  virtue  is 
the  will  to  pay  what  is  due.  But  we  might  consider 
this  will  to  pay  what  is  due  in  two  aspects,  one  negative 
and  the  other  positive — namely,  the  will  to  avoid  injury 
and  to  do  good.  These  two  dispositions  we  may  speak 
of,  if  not  as  integral,  at  least  as  quasi-integral,  parts  of 
Justice. 

.    The  potential  parts  of  Justice. 
The  potential  parts  or  annexed  virtues  of  any  par- 
ticular virtue  concern,  as  we  said,  certain  matters  that 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  625 

on  the  one  hand  have  a  certain  agreement  with  the 
principal  virtue,  and  on  the  other  hand  fall  short  of 
the  principal  virtue  in  some  respect.  Now,  in  respect 
of  the  first  condition,  we  may  consider  every  virtue 
that  regards  in  any  way  our  relations  with  other  people 
as  appertaining  to  Justice.  The  second  condition  of 
an  annexed  virtue,  that  it  falls  short  of  the  principal, 
can  be  realised  in  either  of  two  ways  in  the  case  of 
Justice — either  by  a  want  of  equality  between  the 
persons  concerned  in  the  transaction  or  because  that 
which  is  owed  is  owed  not  by  a  strict  law  but  only  from 
friendship  or  liberality. 

Now,  under  the  first  heading,  which  i=  want  of 
equality,  we  find  as  annexed  virtues  to  Justice  those  of 
religion  which  regulates  our  relations  to  God,  piety 
which  regulates  a  child's  relations  to  its  parents,  respect 
{observatU^JL^  which  secures  a  due  rendering  of  honour 
to  sup'fetK^s.  Under  the  second  heading,  or  the  absence 
of  strict  law,  there  are  many  annexed  virtues,  some  of 
which  are  close  up  to  the  principal  virtue  of  Justice — 
e.g.,  truth  * — whilst  others  are  only  remotely  connected 
with  it,  like  affability  and  friendship.  But  all  these  in 
some  way  or  another  concern  our  duties,  whether 
perfect  or  imperfect,  to  other  persons,  and  hence  they 
are  parts  of  Justice.  | 

(3)  Jiistice — a  natural  virtue. 

When  we  say  that  justice  is  natural  we  do  not  mean 
that  it  is  implanted  in  a  man's  will  by  nature,  but  only 
that  the  good  which  the  virtue  of  justice  secures  is  a 
natural  good — i.e.,  it  is  something  which  is  good,  not 

*  When  we  say  that  truth  is  not  enforced  by  a  strict  law  we  speak 
of  truth  as  a  part  of  Justice,  as  something  that  is  owed  to  other  men, 
and  the  violation  of  which  is  an  offence  to  other  men.  As  so  regarded 
truth  is  not  enjoined  by  strict  law,  for  our  duty  to  tell  the  truth  is  not, 
properly  speaking,  a  duty  to  other  men.  But  if  we  regard  lying  as  a 
violation  of  the  natural  end  of  a  faculty,  then  it  is  a  violation  of  a 
strict  law  of  nature.  For  further  consideration  of  this  point  see  Vol.  II. 
page  74. 

j  I'or  comparison  of  justice  with  charity  see  Vol.  II.  page  2. 

VOL.  I — 40 


626  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

by  convention,  but  by  the  law  of  nature,  and  its  opposite 
is  naturally  and  intrinsically  evil.  Now,  that  there  are 
laws  of  nature  binding  men  to  certain  actions  for  the 
good  of  their  fellowmcn  we  have  already  shown  in  our 
chapter  on  The  Good.  So  far  as  Justice  depends  on 
these  natural  laws  it  is  a  natural  virtue.  Some  rights  of 
Justice  are,  indeed,  not  natural  since  they  depend  on 
positive  law  merely.  And  of  those  rights  that  are 
natural  some,  whilst  resting  ultimately  upon  the  natural 
law,  are  yet  to  a  certain  extent  determined  by  the  State 
or  by  reference  to  some  empirical  fact.  But  there  are 
some  rights  which  depend  immediately  and  solely  on 
the  moral  natural  law  itself  and  are  independent  of 
every  empirical  consideration.  There  are,  therefore, 
rights  which  are,  in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  word,  rights 
of  nature,  and  so  there  must  be  a  natural  virtue  of 
justice  for  the  maintenance  of  those  rights.  But  for  the 
proof  of  this  proposition  we  must  refer  our  reader  to 
our  chapter  on  Rights,  in  which  we  establish  the 
existence  of  natural  rights.* 

Hume's  objections  showing  that  rights  of  Justice  are 
not  natural. 

Hume's  objections  refer  principally  to  rights  of  pro- 
perty which  many  modern  Ethicians  regard  as  co- 
extensive with  rights  of  Justice  generally.  In  these 
objections  he  attempts  to  show  that  property,  and  the 
laws  of  Justice  to  which  it  gives  rise,  obtain  not  neces- 
sarily but  only  under  certain  contingencies,  that  conse- 
quently they  cannot  be  natural,  and,  therefore,  that 
Justice  is  not  a  natural  virtue.  These  objections  are  : 
(fl)  If  there  were  no  lack  of  goods  in  nature  there  would 
be  no  virtue  of  Justice.  There  is,  for  instance,  no  law 
of  Justice  concerning  the  use  of  the  air.  (6)  If  men 
were  perfectly  generous  there  would  be  no  need  of  Justice. 
Justice    arises    from    selfishness,    and    the    consequent 

•  Also  to  Vol.  II,  page  8i,  where  we  establish  the  ground  of  com- 
mutative Justice. 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  627 

danger  that  some  men  will  not  have  a  sufficiency  of 
goods,  (c)  In  the  case  of  famine  there  is  no  law  of 
Justice.  In  famine  every  man  may  take  anything  that 
he  can  get.  Now,  these  three  conditions — an  absolutely 
unlimited  supply  of  goods,  unlimited  generosity,  and 
complete  famine,  though  not  often  to  be  met  with,  are 
still  possible  conditions  of  things,  and  their  opposites 
are  accordingly  mere  accidental  conditions.  And  since 
it  is  on  these  latter  conditions  that  Justice  and  right 
depend.  Justice  and  rights  cannot  be  natural. 

Reply — In  the  first  place,  as  we  have  already  pointed 
out,  the  rights  here  referred  to  are  all  rights  of  propert}-. 
So  that  even  if  rights  of  property  were  not  natural  there 
would  still  remain  other  rights  that  are  natural — e.g., 
the  right  of  a  husband  to  his  wife's  fidelity,  of  an  indi- 
vidual to  non-interference  from  others,  of  children  to 
training.  Secondly,  the  right  of  property  itself,  we 
admit,  does  not  stand  on  quite  the  same  level  as  certain 
other  natural  rights  :  it  depends  more  than  other  rights 
on  contingent  conditions.  Thirdly,  Hume's  arguments 
do  not  avail  to  prove  that  the  right  of  property  is  con- 
ventional or  not  natural  in  some  sense.  For  it  is  not 
true  that  right  would  be  extinguished  in  case  of  a 
plentiful  supply  of  goods,  or  of  generosity,  or  in  case 
of  famine,  [a)  Even  if  there  were  no  lack  of  goods  in 
nature  a  man  would  still  have  a  right  to  what  he  pro- 
duces. Nor  can  it  be  said  that  it  would  be  absurd  to 
claim  a  thing  as  one's  own  under  such  conditions — when, 
namely,  everybody  had  more  than  enough.  We  can 
readily  imagine  a  man  wishing  to  have  a  thing  simply 
because  he  himself  had  made  it,  even  though  there  was 
in  nature  a  superabundance  of  such  things.  So  that 
even  if  there  was  no  lack  of  goods,  men  could  still 
possess  and  would  probably  insist  on  rights  of  pro- 
perty. However,  is  not  Hume's  supposition  absurd  ? 
The  supply  of  goods  in  a  limited  world  must  be  always 
limited.  The  most  one  could  expect  to  find  in  this 
-world   is   not    unlimited   riches   but    very   great   riches. 


628  THE  SCIExNXE  OF  ETHICS 

And  rights  of  property  would  still  hold  even  though 
the  world  were  well  supplied  with  the  goods  of  life. 
His  claim  that  men  have  not  a  right  to  a  certain  por- 
tion of  air  is  also  untenable.  Every  man  has  a  right 
to  as  much  air  as  is  necessary  for  life.  School  managers 
and  inspectors  insist  on  such  a  right,  {b)  Even  if  men 
were  perfectly  generous  each  would  have  a  right  to  the 
products  of  his  own  labour.  And  even  though  all  were 
generous  we  should  probably  still  insist  upon  our  rights. 
Men  do  not  always  care  to  depend  on  the  generosity  of 
others,  (c)  Even  in  the  case  of  famine  each  man  would 
have  a  right  to  certain  things.  One  starving  man 
would,  for  instance,  have  a  right  to  keep  the  loaf  that 
he  had  in  his  possession,  and  another  would  have  no 
right  to  take  it  violently  from  him.  A  starving  man 
has  a  right  to  his  life,  for  ancfther  may  not  kill  him  in 
order  to  obtain  food.  In  the  case  of  famine,  therefore, 
man  still  has  rights. 

But  even  though  we  could  not  show  that  in  these 
abnormal  conditions  contemplated  by  Hume  men  still 
had  rights,  we  should  nevertheless  contend  that  such 
cases  do  not  disprove  the  existence  of  a  natural  right  of 
property  under  normal  conditions.  All  natural  right 
obtains  under  natural  conditions  ;  but  some  of  Hume's 
conditions — that  of  an  infinity  of  goods  and  that  of  a 
universal  famine — are  not  natural  conditions.  And  just 
as  we  should  not  judge  that  there  was  no  natural  method 
of  walking,  since  if  all  legs  were  paralysed  men  could  not 
move,  so  neither  should  we  claim  that  certain  natural 
rights  do  not  exist  because  of  the  difficulty  or  impossi- 
bility of  exercising  them  under  very  abnormal  con- 
ditions. 

(4)  Justice  an  objective  virtue. 

Justice,  as  we  have  seen,  has  to  do  with  outer  opera- 
tions, not  with  internal  passions.  It  is  common  know- 
ledge that  if  a  man  makes  a  contract,  he  is  bound  to 
fulfil  it  from  his  side,  provided  also  it  is  fullilled  from 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  629 

the  other,  and  that  until  the  contract  is  fulfilled  and,  in 
the  case  of  pecuniary  contracts,  payments  made,  the 
law  of  justice  remains  unsatisfied,  no  matter  what  may 
be  the  defaulter's  intentions  or  what  the  cause  of  his 
defalcation.  So  also  if  I  pay  a  man  what  I  owe  him, 
but  pay  him  by  mistake,  thinking  I  am  paying  some- 
body else,  the  law  of  justice  requires  no  more  of  me. 
It  is  fully  satisfied  by  the  outer  act.  The  end  of,  justice 
Js  the  outer  fulfilling  of  justice,  and  it  lias  nothing  to  do 
with  inner  states  of  mind,  desires,  passions,  knowledge 
or  affections  of  giver  or  receiver.  In  this  sense  justice 
is  an  objective  virtue.  Its  principle  is  the  objective 
principle  of  equality — not  in  the  sense  that  each  man's 
possessions  must  be  equal  to  every  other  man's,  but 
that  each  man  must  be  left  in  possession  of  what  he 
owns.  If  that  equilibrium  is  once  disturbed  the  law  of 
justice  requires  that  it  be  restored  again.  Justice  has 
reference,  therefore,  to  an  objective  relation  only — that 
is,  it  binds  a  man  to  the  doing  of  a  certain  outward  act, 
not  to  the  doing  of  that  act  from  any  particular  affection, 
or  intention,  or  passion.  As  independent  of  passion  it 
has  been  called  the  frigid  or  the  mathematical  virtue. 

Having,  therefore,  no  reference  to  passion  or  to  any- 
thing subjective,  it  is  useless  to  seek  to  ground  this 
virtue  upon  any  internal  affection.  It  is,  like  mathe- 
matics, a  law  of  things,  and  it  is  grounded  on  the  nature 
of  things  themselves.*  In  this  connection  the  reader 
will  find  it  interesting  to  criticise  for  himself  some  of 
the  ordinary  subjective  theories  of  the  principle  of 
Justice — for  instance,  the  two  theories  which  ground 
Justice  respectively  upon  the  feelings  of  (i)  sympathy, 
(2)  gratitude — the  first  of  which  theories  is  taught  by 
Hume,  the  second  by  Sidgwick.f 

*  See  ground  of  justice,  Vol.  II.  page  8i. 

t  Spencer  bases  the  sentiment  of  Justice  on  the  love  of  personal 
.rcedom,  which,  under  the  influence  of  certain  subjective  laws,  becomes 
transformed  into  an  altruistic  feeling.  Mill  bases  it  on  the  animal 
feeling  of  resentment,  which  when  purified  becomes  the  desire  for 
punishment. 


630  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

THEORIES   OF  A   SUBJECTIVE   GROUND   OF   JUSTICE 

(a)  Hume's  theory. 

Hume  postulates  two  grounds  for  the  sentiment  of 
Justice — Sympathy  and  Utihty.  But  S3'mpathy  is  the 
chief  element,  and  to  that,  according  to  him,  the  virtue 
ultimately  reduces — that  is,  I  pay  a  man  what  I  owe 
him  because  I  sympathise  with  him,  or  rather  I  feel 
that  I  am  bound  to  pay  him,  because  of  sympathy. 

Criticism  of  Hume's  theory — If  sympathy  be  the 
spring  of  justice  it  is  strange  that  the  two  conceptions, 
justice  and  sympathy,  have  become  so  completely 
divorced  with  time.  Of  course,  it  may  be  said  that 
association  can  first  bind  things  together  which  after- 
wards become  independent,  and  that  even  though 
formerly  the  conception  of  justice  arose  out  of  that  of 
sympathy  it  is'  not  to  be  wondered  at  if  it  has  now 
become  independent  of  that  conception.  But  surely  in 
matters  of  this  kind,  where  we  are  dealing  with  concep- 
tions that  are  known  to  everyone,  we  are  not  free  to 
suggest  that  two  conceptions  were  once  causally  con- 
nected— ^that  is,  that  one  arose  out  of  the  other — when 
as  a  matter  of  fact  we  have  no  empirical  evidence  of 
their  having  ever  been  connected,  and  when,  in  addition, 
they  are  now  distinct  conceptions,  and  independent, 
and  even  often  opposed.  Thus,  I  pay  a  man  because 
I  know  I  am  bound  to  pay  him,  not  because  I  love  him 
or  sympathise  with  him,  and  I  claim  payment  from  him 
because  he  is  bound  to  pay  me,  and  for  no  other  reason. 
I  may  hate  him,  as  I  have  already  said,  I  may  have  no 
sympathy  with  him,  yet  I  am  certain  with  an  unmis- 
takable certitude  that  I  must  pay  him  what  I  owe. 
In  justice,  then,  as  such  there  is  no  element  of  sympathy. 

{b)  Sidgwick's  theory. 

Sidgwick  admits  that  the  prominent  clement  in  justice 
is   equality,   but   yet   he   insists   that    the   principle  of 


HABITS  AND  VIRTUE  631 

justice  is  not  equality  but  gratitude.  The  principle  of 
gratitude  is,  he  says,  that  "  the  good  done  to  an  indi- 
vidual ought  to  be  requited  by  him,"  from  which  he 
concludes  that  "  men  ought  to  be  rewarded  in  propor- 
tion to  their  deserts."  Thus,  to  say  a  man  has  a  right 
to  the  produce  of  his  labour  is  only  another  wa}'  of 
saying  that  he  has  a  right  to  be  rewarded  out  of  grati- 
tude for  services  rendered.  In  this  way  Sidgwick 
claims  to  be  able  to  explain  what  he  regards  as  the 
otherwise  inexplicable  right  of  first  occupation  ;  for  on 
no  other  title,  he  tells  us,  ma}^  a  man  appropriate  what 
he  finds  and  has  not  previously  owned  than  the  title  of 
the  boon  conferred  upon  the  community  by  his  dis- 
covery. Punishment,  the  reverse  of  reward,  being 
essentially  grounded  on  the  principle  of  an  eye  for  an 
eye  and  a  tooth  for  a  tooth,  is,  he  claims,  based  upon 
the  negative  of  the  conception  of  gratitude — that  is, 
upon  the  feeling  of  resentment. 

Criticism — Now,  this  argument  will  easily  be  seen  to 
be  erroneous  if  we  consider  how  essentially  opposed  are 
the  two  virtues  before  us.  For  (a)  gratitude  always 
supposes  the  returning  of  a  good  which  yet  need  not  be 
returned — a  return  for  which  there  was  no  stipulation, 
a  return  which  is  perfectly  free  and  spontaneous. 
(&)  Gratitude  presupposes  that  the  good  done  in  the 
first  instance,  and  for  which  a  return  is  now  being 
made,  was  free  and  spontaneous,  and  unstipulated  for. 
(c)  Gratitude  has  regard  to  passion,  to  subjective 
feeling,  to  affection.  I  am  satisfied  with  a  man's  grati- 
tude when  I  know  that  he  thinks  well  of  me,  that  he 
remembers  what  I  have  done  for  him.  Even  if  he 
makes  a  return,  what  he  gives  is  given  only  as  a  token 
of  remembrance.  Consequently  it  need  not  be  on  a 
par  with  the  good  originally  done,  {d)  Both  gratitude 
and  sympathy  prompt  us  to  reward  a  man  for  ser\-ices 
attempted  but  not  succeeded  in.  [e)  Finally,  gratitude 
is  an  altruistic  feeling.  Now,  justice  differs  in  all  these 
points  fropi  gratitude.     («)  Justice  moves  a  man  to  £^ 


632  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

return  of  goods  because  this  return  has  been  stipulated 
for,  and  because,  therefore,  these  goods  belong  to  the 
other  party  to  the  contract,  [b)  It  supposes  that  those 
things  which  were  originally  given,  and  for  which  a 
return  is  being  made,  were  given  as  a  result  of  contract 
and  not  in  friendship  merely.  It  is  stern  obligation 
from  beginning  to  end.  (c)  Justice  cares  nothing  about 
inner  passion  or  intention.  It  simply  requires  that  a 
certain  payment  be  made,  whether  out  of  gratitude  or 
hatred,  from  selfish  or  altruistic  motives,  it  does  not 
matter.  "  Frigidum  illud  verbum,  meum  ac  tuum  " 
describes  it  admirably,  for  a  debt  of  justice  is  discharged 
because  it  has  to  be  discharged,  and  because  there  is 
no  way  out  of  it.  "  Small  tokens  of  remembrance  "  can 
never  be  equivalents  of  justice,  which  is  satisfied  only 
with  payment  of  the  last  penny,  {d)  Justice,  as  a  rule, 
cares  nothing  about  good  which  is  merely  willed  or 
attempted.  If  we  might  put  it  so.  Justice  demands  pay- 
ment only  for  goods  delivered  at  our  doors,  [e]  Justice 
is  neither  an  altruistic  nor  an  egoistic  feeling.  If  it 
requires  that  I  be  just  to  others,  it  requires  also  that 
others  be  just  to  me.  It  represents  a  mere  equation 
bet\\'een  man  and  man. 

Justice,  therefore,  cannot  be  based  on  gratitude. 


CHAPTER  XIX 
ON  LAW 

{a)  General  Conception  of  Law 

(i)  Our  first  business  in  framing  a  right  conception  of 
law  is  to  show  that  Law  is  a  function  of  Reason.  Law 
is  defined  by  various  writers  to  be  a  "  rule  of  action" 
a  "  rule  of  direction,"  a  "  settled  principle  of  action,"  a 
"  measure  of  action,"  a  principle  following  which  we  are 
led  to  pursue  certain  lines  of  conduct  and  to  avoid 
others.  This  element  of  "  guidance  "  or  of  "  rule  "  is 
the  fundamental  element  in  our  conception  of  law.  The 
word  "  law  "  is  applied  principally  and  essentially  to 
rules  of  human  action,*  but  we  use  it  in  a  transferred 
sense  in  regard  to  other  things,  always,  however,  with 
the  same  meaning  of  a  rule  of  action  or  of  movement  of 
some  sort.  Thus,  we  speak  of  chemical  laws,  meaning 
thereby  the  principles  according  to  which  elementary 
substances  enter  into  chemical  combinations  with  one 
another  ;  of  the  laws  of  plants — that  is,  the  laws  which 
guide  the  movementys  and  growths  of  plants  ;  of  the 
laws  of  animals — that  is,  the  principles,  instincts,  etc., 
which  guide  the  acts  of  animals.  In  all  these  cases 
law  directs  action  or  movement. 

^  Now,  in  the  case  of  man,  as  also  in  the  case  of  other 
living  things,  a  rule  of  action  means  alwa3S  a  principle 
according  to  which  proper  means  are  taken  to  the  attain- 
ment of  some  end  ;    and  since  Reason  f  alone  is  com- 

*  A  "  lawyer,"  absolutely  speaking,  is  one  who  is  versed  in  human 
laws. 

t  The  designing  of  means  always  implies  reasoning.  Hence  a 
mere  "  sense  "  could  not  make  laws.  Sense  could  not  even  apprehend 
the  abstract  relation  of  proportion  or  of  suitability  between  means 
and  ends.  For  this  reason,  though  animals  may  attack  an  enemy, 
thf-y  cannot  devise  means  by  which  to  kill  an  enemy. 

633 


634  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

^petent  to  devise  means  for  obtaining  an  end,  it  follows 
that  law  is  primarily  a  function  of  Reason. 

But,  though  law  belongs  essentially  to,  and  dwells  in 
the  directing  Reason  {est  in  regulante  et  mensuranie) 
it  is  evident  that  law  belongs  by  participation  to,  and 
exists  in,  the  subject  ruled  {est  in  regulato  et  mensuraio). 
Thus  the  laws  that  govern  the  movements  of  machinery 
are  a  participation  and  reflection  of  the  mind  of  him 
by  whom  the  machinery  is  designed.  The  law  of  the 
Divine  Reason,  which  designed  the  structure  and  func- 
tions of  the  animal  kingdom,  dwells  by  participation  in 
animals,  and  directs  them  to  their  ends.  This  exten- 
sion of  the  laws  of  Reason  to  the  things  which  are 
directed  by  Reason  is  a  point  of  cardinal  importance  in 
Ethical  Science,  and  will  be  considered  at  greater  length 
when  we  come  to  speak  of  the  natural  and  eternal  laws 
and  their  relation  to  one  another. 

But  though  law  proceeds  from  Reason,  it  bears  also 
some  reference  to  will.  For,  law  being  a  rule  of  action, 
it  has  two  essential  elements — it  is  a  plan  and  a  directing 
or  moving  force.  It  arranges  a  line  of  action,  and  it 
binds  to  the  adoption  of  that  line.  It  is  a  thought  and  a 
command.  For  instance,  a  human  law  is  something 
more  than  a  mere  plan  for  the  securing  of  the  common 
good.  It  is  a  plan  which  the  legislator  lays  on  our  wills 
for  acceptance,  a  plan  which  the  legislator  .binds  us  to 
follow. 

Hence,  law  is  a  function_flQ^of  intellecj^  '^1qd<^  but  QJ 
Yfill  also.  Intellect_  is  the  planning,  the  thinking,  the 
arrangmg  power — will  the  moving,  the  bindmg_j)Qwer. 
Yet,  priJTiarily^and  essentially,  law  is  a  functiflji.  of 
^  Ke!n?oh  or  intellect,  and  not  dl  will ;  lor^wiDTj^n  binding 
iis^grfivf"«^  its  ail'tiCLloh  fluiii  Rtj^rson.  WilT^rges  to 
tKcdoing  of  a  certain  act ;  but  it  urges,  in  the  case  of  a 
genuine  law,  under  the  guidance  of  intellect.  The  will 
that  binds  a  subject  independently  of  intellect  is  a  prin- 
ciple not  of  law  but  of  confusion  and  destruction  {magis 
iniquitas  quan}  lex).     Hence,   inasmuch  as   the  guidint; 


ON  LAW  635 

power  is  always  principal,  and  of  more  consequence 
than  that  which  is  guided,  we  regard  law  as  primarily 
and  essentially  a  function  of  Reason — not  of  will. 

Note  on  "  Natural  Selection  "  as  a  Substitute  for 
"  Aws  OF  Reason." — Some  try  to  explain  the  order  of 
the  living  Universe,  not  as  a  result  of  laws  of  Reason,  but 
as  a  result  of  natural  selection,  of  "  Struggle  for  Existence," 
of  the  "  Survival  of  the  fittest."  Now,  it  is  not  within  the 
scope  of  the  present  work  to  discuss  this  question  of  "  natural 
selection  "  on  its  own  merits.  But  we  may  be  permitted  to 
point  out  that  "  natural  selection  "  and  "  struggle,"  even  if 
we  accord  them  a  large  place  among  the  existing  world- 
forces,  are  not  to  be  regarded  as  incompatible  with  the  ex- 
istence in  the  world  of  laws  of  Reason.  Nay,  they  may 
themselves  be  laws  of  Reason.  For  even  an  all- wise  Reason 
might  impart  a  "  law  of  struggle  "  to  living  things  in  order 
to  secure  the  development  and  continuance  of  the  best  types 
amongst  the  species,  and  in  that  case  we  should  speak  of 
the  "  struggle  for  existence  "  as  a  law  or  function  of  Reason. 

Yet,  even  though  we  admit  the  possibihty  of  such  a  law, 
we  could  not  regard  the  "  struggle  for  existence  "  as  an 
ultimate  explanation  of  the  natural  order  of  things,  for 
"  struggle "  amongst  living  beings  is  itself  based  on  the 
existence  in  plants  and  animals  of  natural  appetites,  and  of 
a  natural  law  depending  on  these  appetites.  Thus,  animals 
struggle  for  sustenance  because  they  have  a  natural  appetite 
for  food.  Hence  the  "  struggle  for  existence  "  could  not  be 
the  ultimate  principle  of  the  order  of  the  Universe,  but  the 
natural  laws  of  the  appetites  ;  and  as  we  shall  show  later, 
it  is  from  these  natural  laws  that  we  come  to  the  knowledge 
of  the  Eternal  Law  of  the  Supreme  Reason  from  which  all 
order  proceeds. 

It  may  be  well  to  add  here  that  to  our  mind  the  existence 
of  a  supreme  directing  Reason  is  even  more  evident  from  the 
study  of  the  natural  appetites  of  plants  and  animals  than 
from  their  structure.  It  is  evident  that  the  animal  is  driven 
to  seek  for  food  and  other  objects  in  order  that  thereby  it 
may  secure  its  own  life  and  that  of  the  race.  But  of  these 
ends  the  animal  itself  has  no  consciousness  and  no  care  when 
following  its  natural  appetites  ;  and  hence  its  direction  to 
these  ends  depends  on  some  other  power  besides  its  own 
appetites. 

To  the  foregoing  argument  some  philosophers  might  raise 
the  objection  that  it  is  built  on  the  assumption  that  the 


636  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

appetites  of  the  various  animals  are  natural — that  is,  that 
they  were  present  in  animals  from  the  beginning.  Now, 
though  it  is  quite  true  that  our  argument  assumes  the  natural 
and  original  character  of  some  appetites,  still  we  claim  to 
have  shown  that  the  existence  of  natural  appetites  in  living 
things  is  more  than  an  assumption.  It  is  an  established  fact 
(see  chapter  on  The  Good).  As  Leslie  Stephen  points  out, 
unless  certain  natural  appetites  were  present  from  the 
beginning,  the  animal  world  could  not  have  survived  a 
generation.  These  appetites,  therefore,  are  part  of  the 
natural  constitution  of  the  animal  races,  and  they  are,  as  we 
have  said,  evidence  of  the  existence,  somewhere,  of  a 
designing  mind. 

(2)  We  have  revt  tn  rlp|P|-p-iinp  thp  pnd  nf  law.  Law, 
we  claim,  is  always  ordained  to  the  xommon  £;ood.  We 
saw  that  law  is  a  rule  of  action.  Now,  the  good  or  wel- 
fare at  which  action  aims  may  be  either  the  good  of  an 
individual  merely  or  of  a  whole  community.  But  law 
evident!}^  aims  at  realising  a  certain  unity  of  action, 
which  without  law,  it  would  be  difficult  if  not  impossible 
to  secure ;  and,  therefore,  we  claim  that  law  apper- 
tains principally  to  the  good  of  the  community  only, 
since  the  conduct  of  an  individual  does  not  need  to  be 
unified  by  any  rule  of  guidance.  For  another  reason, 
also,  we  claim  that  law  has  reference  principally  to  the 
common  good  and  not  to  the  individual  good — namely, 
that  everything  in  nature  which  is  defined  by  its  effects 
is  defined  or  denominated  b}^  its  highest  effect,  not  by 
its  lowest.  Thus,  we  speak  of  man  not  as  a  vegetative 
or  sensitive,  but  as  a  rational,  being.  And,  therefore, 
it  is  right  that  we  should  regard  law  as  a  rule  of  action 
given  to  a  community  ;  for  the  good  of  the  community 
is  .higher  than  that  of  the  individual,  being  related  to 
the  individual  good  as  the  whole  is  related  to  the  part. 
Just,  therefore,  as  the  plan  of  an  architect  regards 
j)rimarily  not  the  parts  of  the  house,  but  the  whole 
house  to  which  the  parts  are  subordinate,  and,  in  a 
secondary  way  only,  the  perfection  of  the  parts,  so  law 
has  reference  primarily  to  the  order  which  is  to  be 
followed    in    the   securing    of    the    con-.nion    good,    aruJ 


ON  LAW  637 

• 
/secondarily  to  the  I'nrlivirlna]  g77pH  Rules  of  action, 
we  admit,  are  often  formulated  for  the  guidance  of 
individual  conduct  only.  But  we  should  no  more  re- 
gard rules  of  this  kind  as  laws  than  we  should  speak  of 
a  couple  of  individuals  as  composing  the  State  or  of  a 
mere  well-ordered  sitting-room  as  an  Art  Gallery.  The 
individual  good  is  neither  wide  enough  nor  great  enough 
to  be  the  sole  end  of  law. 

From  what  we  have  said,  it  will  be  evident  that  the 
law  of  the  Prime  Ruler  appertains  directly  and  princi- 
pally to  the  common  good  of  all  creatures — the  law  of 
any  other  subordinate  ruler  to  the  common  good  of 
some  lesser  perfect  community.  We  say  "  a  perfect  ^ 
community,"  because  law  belongs  only  to  a  community 
which  is  capable  of  attaining  its  own  ends — that  is,  it 
belongs  to  a  community  which  is  self-sufficing.  The 
rules  of  a  particular  house  or  of  a  family  are  called,  not 
laws,  but  precepts,  for  a  house  or  family  is  not  a  self- 
sufficing  community. 

We  should,  however,  remark  in  explanation  of  our 
doctrine  that  the  end  of  law  is  the  good  of  the  com- 
munity, that  not  all  laws  are  meant  to  bitid  the  whole 
community  or  are  meant  to  lead  directly  and  tmme^itely 
to  the  good  ot  the  whole  community.  For,  man\^  laws 
bind  a  part  only  of  the  community,  and  directly  betiefii^ 
no  more  than  a  part.  But  persons  that  come  under 
laws  of  this  kind  come  under  it  as  parts  of  the  com- 
munity, and  the  law  which  guides  them  is  to  be  regarded 
as  part  of  the  general  scheme  for  the  securing  of  the 
common  good.  In  this  sense  we  describe  law  as  directed 
always  to  the  general  good. 

(3)  A  law  requires  to  be  promulgated.  ^  By  promulga- 
tion is  meant  the  bringing  of  a  law  under  the  notice  of 
those  whom  it  binds,  and  giving  it  to  them  as  binding. 
Now,  a  law  is  a  rule  of  action,  and  since  nothing  can  be 
a  rule  of  action  to  men  unless  it  comes  to  the  knowledge 
of  those  whom  it  binds  (human  action  being  always 
directed  by  knowledge),  it  follows  that  promulgation  is 


638 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


necessary  for  law.  Promulgation  must  also  be  certain, 
for  true  knowledge  implies  certainty  ;  so  that  if  the  pro- 
mulgation of  any  law  be  doubtful  such  a  law  is  not 
sufficiently  promulgated,  and  it  is  not  to  be  regarded 
as  binding. 

Promulgation,  ^if^wmror^  jip^d  not  succeed  in  bringing 
a^law  under  the  notice  of  every  subject.  A  law  which 
is  published  may  bind  its  subjects,  even  though  it  fails 
to  reach  the  notice  of  some  individuals.  But,  though 
this  is  true  as  regards  many  of  the  effects  of  law,  still, 
in  order  that  a  law  may  bind  the  individual  conscience 
formally — in  other  words,  in  order  that  its  violation  may 
be  regarded  as,  properly  speaking,  a  transgression — it 
must  be  known  with  certitude  *  even  by  the  individual, 
since  for  formal  sin  it  is  necessary  that  a  man  sins 
knowingly  and  willingly. 

The  foregoing  considerations  will  suffice  to  give  us 
the  full  definition  of  a  law — it  is  a  "  dictate  (ordinatio) 
of  Reason  given  and  promulgated  Jar  ^^^^  r.or""^""  good 
by  one  who  ^^^q  f^hprp;p  nf  the  commurtjtv." 

(4)  A  supplementary  question  remains  as  regards  the 
subject  of  laws,  or  what  and  whom  it  binds.  A  law  may 
bind  any  creature,  for  there  is  no  creature  that  may  not 
be  directed  to  some  end.  But,  as  we  shall  see  later,  law 
in  its  strict  sense  extends  onl}^  to  rational  creatures,  and 
the  only  rational  creatures  that  concern  us  here  are 
human  beings.  The  question  then  arises — Are  all  men 
subject  to  law  ?  Our  answer  is — Everv  human  being 
is  subject  to  the  natural  law,  for  every  hnmpn  Iwm^  is 
possessed  of  human  nature.  Rijj^Qply  such  people,  as 
are  hahitually^lk^^^bis^ud  pf  thff  ii^<^  nf  Rp^^9]r^  :irc  subject 
tomiman  laws — that  is,  to  laws  that  emanate  from  men. 
Infants  and  mad  people,  therefore,  could  not  be  bound 
by  human  law,  but  those  who  are  habitually  sane,  even 
though  they  suffer  from  a  temporary  mental  aberration. 


•  The  subject  of  Probabilism  is  intimately  connected  with  this 
qucHlion  of  promulgation.  A  brief  reference  to  it  is  found  at  the  end 
of  our  ciuipter  on  Conscience. 


ON  LAW  639 

are  subject  to  human  law.  But  though  all  men  are 
subject  to  the  natural  law,  and  those  who  are  habitually 
sane  are  subject  to  human  laws,  still  the  formal — that 
is,  the  criminal — violation  of  any  law,  whether  natural 
or  human,  is  possible  only  in  the  case  of  one  who  is  in 
actual  possession  of  the  use  of  Reason. 

A  practical  consequence  of  the  doctrine  we  have  just 
laid  down — the  doctrine  that  all  men  are  subject  to  the 
natural  law — may  be  mentioned  here,  namely,  that  it  is 
not  lawful  to  incite  infants  or  mad  people  to  acts  that 
oppose  the  natural  law.  To  do  so  is  to  incur  all  the  guilt 
of  their  act.* 

(b)  Of  the  Various  Kinds  of  Laws 

Men  are  governed  by  four  principal  kinds  of  law — 
namely,  the  Eternal,  the  Natural,  the  Human,  and  the 
(positive)  Divme'Tavvs.  The  last  of  these  belongs  to 
revealed  science,  and  need  not  be  considered  here.  The 
other  three  will  now  be  considered  at  some  length. 

THE   ETERNAL   LAW 

(i)  "  As  with  every  artificer,"  writes  Aquinas, f  "  there 
pre-exists  the  plan  of  the  things  that  are  set  up  by  art, 
so  in  every  governor  there  must  pre-exist  a  plan  of  the 
order  of  the  things  that  are  to  be  done  by  those  who  are 
subject  to  his  government.  And  as  the  plan  of  things  to 
be  done  by  art  is  called  a  pattern  or  exemplar,  so  the 

•  Apropos  of  the  doctrine  that  the  aim  of  law  is  the  good  of  a 
community,  Aquinas  points  out  that  whereas  a  subject  may  be  a  bad 
man  in  his  private  life  without  injury  to  the  State,  he  cannot  be  a  bad 
citizen — that  is,  he  cannot  set  the  public  legislation  at  nought  without 
injury  to  the  State.  A  ruler,  on  the  other  hand,  will  harm  the  State 
if  he  is  bad,  either  in  his  private  or  his  public  life — eadem  est  virtus 
principis  et  boni  viri — for  even  the  inner  dispositions  of  a  ruler  tend 
to  make  themselves  felt  in  the  laws  he  enacts.  This  latter  portion 
of  Aquinas'  teaching,  however — that,  namely,  which  concerns  the 
requirements  of  rulers — holds  more  for  the  case  of  absolute  monarchies 
than  for  constitutional  monarchies  or  republics. 

t  "  Aquinas  Ethicus  "  (Rickaby),  Vol.  I.,  page  274.  We  begin 
with  the  consideration  ot  the  eternal  law,  because  ontologically  it  is 
prior  to  the  natural  law.  But  it  should  be  remembered  that  the 
natural  law  is  known  to  every  man  in  some  measure,  before  the  eternal, 
and  that  through  it  we  come  to  the  knowledge  of  the  eternal  law. 


640  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

plan  of  him  who  governs  subjects  has  the  character  of  a 
law,  if  the  other  conditions  are  observed,  which  we  have 
said  to  be  essential  to  a  law.  .  .  ,  And  as  the  plan  of 
Divine  Wisdom  has  the  character  of  an  exemplar,  pattern, 
or  idea,  inasmuch  as  by  it  all  things  are  created,  so  the 
plan  of  Divine  Wisdom  moving  all  things  to  their  due 
end  has  the  character  of  a  law.  And  thus  the  eternal 
law  is  nothing  else  than,  the  plan  ofDivine  Wisdom  as 
director  of,al]  ar.t.s  and  movements." 

From  this  passage  of  Aquinas  we  shall  have  no  diffi- 
l/culty  in  understanding  the  nature  of  the  eternal  law. 
The  eternal  law  is  the  law  of  God  as  directing  the  whole 
universe  to  its  end.  By  it  God  rules  all  His  creatures, 
and  directs  them  to  their  final  end,  which  is  Himself. 
There  is  nothing  which  does  not  come  under  this  law — 
neither  plant,  nor  animal,  nor  man,  nor  angel ;  for 
Divine  Providence  extends  to  all.  Later  in  this  chapter 
we  shall  show  what  is  the  origin  of  our  knowledge  of 
the  eternal  law  :  we  shall  show  that  it  is  known  to  us 
through  the  natural  law.  At  present  our  claim  is  that 
the  eternal  law  itself  is  prior  to  every  other  law — to 
natural  and  to  human  law — and  that  it  is  the  ground 
and  principle  of  every  other  law. 

(2)  Now,  the  planning  and  the  guiding  of  the  created 
universe  by  the  Supreme  Reason  are  acts  of  God,  and 
like  all  other  acts  of  God  they  nrg  indpppt](l«^nt  of  timp 
(that  is,  His  acts  do  not  succeed  one  another  in  time), 
since  God  Himself  is  independent  of  time.  God's 
actions  have  no  beginning  and  no  ending.  The  outer 
effects  that  attend  upon  His  wishes  and  commands  are, 
indeed,  subject  to  the  time-conditions  of  the  finite 
universe — they  begin  and  end  at  definite  moments  of 
the  world's  history — but  the  act  from  which  these  effects 
spring  is  not  subject  to  time-conditions.     It  is  eternal.* 

•  There  is  no  reason  why  causes  should  always  be  subject  to  the 
same  conditions  of  existence  that  govorn  the  ellects.  God's  directing 
act  is,  like  God  Himself,  eternal  and  out  of  the  time-series  altogether. 
The  effects  of  His  action  are  subject  to  the  time-conditions  of  the  finite 
universe 


ON  LAW  641 

^God's  law  is,  therefore,  eternal.  It  existed  in  God 
before  *  the  created  world  existed,  just  as  the  plan  pre- 
cedes the  building  of  a  house.  It  was  even  promulgated 
before  the  world  appeared  (though  its  promulgation  was 
not  received  until  creatures  existed),  for  promulgation 
consists  in  the  expression  of  the  law  ;  and  the  Divine 
Word,  which  is  God's  mind,  expresses  itself  eternall}; 
in  the  fullest  way. 

But,  it  will  be  objected,  any  law  is  meaningless  and 
foolish  which  is  enacted  and  promulgated  before  those 
subjects  for  whom  it  is  destined  exist  ;  and  as  the 
eternal  law,  which  is  destined  for  the  created  world, 
existed  before  the  creation,  it  was  a  meaningless  and  a 
foolish  law.  We  answer — If  the  law  which  is  promul- 
gated is  only  a  means  to  creatures,  then  it  is  a  foolish 
thing  to  promulgate  a  law  before  they  to  whom  it  is 
directed  exist  and  are  able  to  receive  it.  But  the 
eternal  law  is  not  a  means  to  anything  beyond  itself. 
Even  the  natural  law  existing  in  created  things  is  not  a 
means  to — that  is,  is  not  directed  to — the  good  of 
created  things.  Rather  it  is  that  which  directs  created 
things  to  their  end.  It  guides,  for  instance,  and  directs 
animals  to  their  ends.  But  human  laws,  existing  in 
the  mind  of  human  legislators,  are  directed  to  the  attain- 
ment of  the  prosperity  of  others.  They  are,  therefore, 
means  to  something  beyond  themselves.  Now,  the 
eternal  law,  like  the  natural  law,  is  of  the  nature  of  a 
directing  principle.  It  directs.  ttiingQ  ir.  \\^f^\x  eq^.  It 
produces,  no  doubt,  effects  outside  of  God  ;  but  yet  it 
is  not  directed  to  created  things.  For  the  'eternnl 
law  is  not  distin(;'t  from  God.  It  is  the  will  of  God 
Qmself,  who  is  the  Primp.  TViTTvp]-  r^f^^nUfi^ynnrc  •  ^^^ 
hence,  if  w"e  might  be  permitted  soto  spea"k,  it  is 
its  own  end.  Even,  therefore,  before  created  things 
came  into  Being,  the  eternal  law  had  reached  its  end, 
though  it   did   not   produce  its   effects  until  the  world 

♦  This  word  "  before  "  means  simply  that  God's  act  did  not  begin 
with  the  created  world.     It  is  the  cause  of  the  created  world. 

Vol.  t— 41 


642  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

existed  and  until  the  conditions  of  its  fulfilment  were 
realised. 

(3)  We  must  now  consider  the  scope  of  the  eternal 
law  or  its  breadth  of  application.  All  things,  necessary 
as  well  as  contingent,  are  subject  to  the  eternal  law. 
Necessary  and  eternal  things  are  subject  to  the  eternal 
law  because  they  are  subject  to  the  Divine  government. 
And  they  are  subject  to  the  eternal  law  exclusively 
because  they  are  subject  to  Divine  government  ex- 
clusively. Necessary  things  are  not  subject  to  the 
government  of  man.  A  man  can,  no  doubt,  make  a  law 
concerning  other  people's  contingent  acts ;  but  no 
earthly  ruler  could  make  a  law  that  men  are  to  ha^'e  or 
not  to  have  hands  or  feet.  But  God  could  make,  and 
has  made,  such  a  law,  because  nature  and  natural  neces- 
sities are  subject  to  the  Divine  power. 

Natural  contingent  things  are  also  subject  to  the 
eternal  law,  because  they  also  are  subject  to  Divine 
government.  But  of  these  one  class  comes  under  human 
law  as  well  as  under  the  eternal  law — namely,  human 
actions.  Other  contingent  things  come  under  the 
eternal  law  07ily.  The  reason  of  this  is  interesting. 
Man,  as  we  have  said,  can  make  a  law  to  guide  the 
conduct  of  human  beings,  but  he  could  not  issue  a  law 
to  irrational  creatures.  For  man  cannot,  as  God  does, 
give  to  things  natural  inclinations  towards  those  ends 
which  he  wishes  them  to  attain.  Hence,  nnythinp^hrjj- 
is  directed  by  hjimfut^governm^t  musr]|be]^apabl£  of 
receivmg  directJQp -by  lygiyof  command,  and  of  directing 
its  own  acts  accordingly^  Btlt — tmrmals  can  neither 
receive  a  command  nor  direct  themselves.  They  cannot 
receive  a  command,  for  a  command  can  influence  to 
action  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  understood,  and  animals 
cannot  understand  human  commands.*  Neither  can 
they  direct  themselves  to  action,   because  they  are  not 

•  Tlic  obvious  objection  to  the  above,  that  some  animals  "  under- 
stand "  their  master's  command  to  "  come  "  or  to  "  depart,"  is  not 
worlii  discussing  here. 


ON  LAW  643 

free.  Therefore^  being  unable  to  receive  a  command 
and  unable  to  direct  themselves,  they  are  not  subject 
to  human  government.  Any  eiTect,  therefore,  that  a 
man  may  wish  to  bring  about  in  animals  he  must  him- 
self produce  in  them,  without  their  co-operation.  But 
man  can  issue  a  law  to  other  men  by  conveying  to  their 
minds  the  knowledge  of  what  they  are  to  do.  And  in 
this  the  human  law  is,  even  as  a  directive  force,  like  the 
eternal.  For,  just  as  a  man  guides  others  by  imprinting 
a  principle  of  action  in  the  minds  of  others,  so  God 
directs  by  imprinting  an  inner  directive  principle  in  all 
things — namely,  the  natural  law — by  which  internal 
principle  they  are  moved  to  obey  Him. 

THE   NATURAL   LAW 

(i)  As  we  have  already  pointed  out,  law  being  a 
measure  and  rule  of  action,  it  exists  in  two  wa^•s — in 
that  which  rules  and  in  that  which  is  ruled  ("  in  men- 
surante  et  tn  mensurato ").  As  existing  in  God  the 
supreme  law  is  eternal ;  ^^  frr^nrg  '''"  fhfi  m.hjr.rt  ri^^l^d 
it  is  Known  as  tfie^natural  Jaw.  And  since  the  ruler 
comes  before  that  which  is  ruled,  the  eternal. Jaw^  is 
prior  to  the  natural  law  and  is  its  cause.  ^^~" 

But  though  ontologically  the  eternal  law  is  prior  to 
and  is  the  ground  of  the  natural  law,  yet  we  are  to  con- 
ceive the  natural  law  as  logically  prior  in  regard  to  us — 
that  is,  as  coming  first  in  the  order  of  our  knowledge.  For 
just  as  it  is  from  the  existence  of  the  finite  world  that 
we  come  to  know  of  God's  existence  who  is  first  cause 
of  all,  so  also  *  it  is  from  the  existence  of  the  natural 

*  In  his  article  on  "  Divine  Providence  "  ("  S.  Theol."  I.,  Q.  XXII., 
Art.  1.)  Aquinas  follows  this  a  posteriori  method — that  is,  his  argunacnt 
for  Providence  proceeds  from  effect  to  cause,  from  the  existence  of  law 
in  the  Universe  to  the  existence  of  a  Divine  Providence.  Later,  in 
establishing  the  Divine  government  of  the  Universe  (Q.  ClII.,  Art.  I.), 
he  argues  in  a  two-fold  way — first,  a  priori  from  the  idea  of  a  most 
perfect  being,  saying  that  it  is  most  congruent  that  such  a  Being  should 
rule  the  world  according  to  law  ;  and,  secondly,  a  posteriori  from  the 
manifest  existence  of  natural  "  law  "  in  the  Universe.  In  the  text 
above  we  follow  the  a  posteriori  proof,  as  Aquinas  himself  seems  to 
do  when  treating  of  the  relation  of  the  Natural  to  the  Eternal  law. 


644  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

law  of  the  universe  that  we  establish  Divine  Providence 
and  the  existence  of  the  eternal  law.  The  natural  law, 
since  it  exists  in  creatures,  is  an  effect  ;  and,  therefore, 
it  presupposes  another  law  above  itself  from  which  it 
springs. 

(2)  Existence  and  purpose  of  natural  law.  We  know 
that  a  natural  law  exists  and  what  its  function  is  from 
the  fact  that  everj^thing  in  the  world  is  guided  and 
directed  to  its  end  by  certain  natural  appetites  (habent 
inclinationes  in  proprios  actus  et  fines).*  Law^is„any 
rule  of  action  which  guides  and  directs  things  to  the 
attainment  of  their  proper  perfection.  Now  the  ap- 
petites are  certain  natural  tendencies  which  guide  and 
impel  to,  by  creating  a  need  for,  certain  objects.  These 
objects  constitute  the  natural  '  good  '  of  things  (object 
of  appetite  being  our  definition  of  '  good  ')  and  natural 
perfection  consists  in  their  attainment.  Hence  the 
natural  appetites  are  a  source  of  law,  the  law,  viz.  by 
which  the  world,  and  all  that  is  in  it,  are  guided  to  their 
proper  natural  perfection. 

(3)  Scope  of  the  natural  law.  The  tiatur^^ii^aw  is 
wider  in  its  scope  than  the  ends  of  the  appetites.  It 
extends  -also.to  the.ja£ajis  necessary  f^r  .ntta-ining  thpsc 
ends.  For,  if  we  must  attain  the  end,  then  we  must 
iHso^  adopt  the  means.  For  instance,  the  animal  must 
live — it  has  a  natural  appetite  for  life.  Therefore  it 
must  have  food.  Man  must  develop  (development  being 
a  natural  end)  and  therefore  man  must  have  Society, 
which  is  necessary  for  development.  "Fhcp  me.ms,  then, 
as  well  as  the  end^  ^re  qf-q^tural  law.  Often^  indeed, 
flTe  means  are  necessary  by  a  double  title,  for  when 
tlic  ends  to  which  they  lead  are  of  fundamental  im- 
portance,   nature    often    supplies    special    appetites    for 

•  St-e  pages  104-11.3,  129-134  ;  also  paRcs  300  392.  Hegelians, 
and  pantheists  generally,  speak  of  these  appetites  as  phages  in  the 
Divine  Consciousness.  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  iiescril)es  them  as  ordinary 
finite  fotces,  physical  and  j)sychical.  Tlie  lirst  view  is  tlie  '  world- 
view  'of  ni\slii.ism,  the  second  that  of  Piiilosophy  and  sound  common- 
■cnse. 


ON  LAW  645 

the  means,  e.g.,  food  and  the  care  of  offspring  which  are 
both  of  natural  law,  first  as  being  necessar}^  means 
to  the  life  of  the  individual  and  the  race,  and  secondly, 
as  objects  of  special  appetites.  The  natural  law  then 
extends  both  to  means  and  ends. 

(4)  Kinds  of  natural  law.  The  natural  appetites 
differ  not  only  in  their  ends  but  also  in  the  manner  in 
which  they  guide  to  these  ends.  In  plants,  appetites 
take  the  form  of  irresistible  vital  forces,  which  physically 
impel  the  plant  to  develop  in  a  certain  way.  The  animal 
appetites  are  felt  as  sensuous  impulses  or  psychical 
desires^  depending  on  sf^rit;nnn';  kri^wipdg^  In  man 
besides  the^R^TH^  kinds  there  are  also  appetites  which 
depend  on  Reason,  like  the  appetite  for  social  inter- 
course,  lor  knowledge  of  causes,  and  for  the  good-in- 
general.  As  Aquinas  says  some  appetites  belong  to 
man  as  substance,  some  as  animal,  some  as  rational, 
the  manner  in  which  the  appetites  affect  the  agent 
depending  in  each  case  on  the  ixiture  to  which  they  are 
attached.  Like  the  appetites,  therefore,  the  laws  built 
on  those  appetites  differ  widely  in  the  way  in  which 
they  ^uide  things  to  their  ends.  Since,  however,  in 
man  most  of  the  appetites  are  under  the  control  of 
Reason,  and  since  as  a  consequence,  it  is  by  Reason 
rather  than  by  the  appetites  directly  that  men  are 
guided  to  their  ends,  it  becomes  necessary  to  speak  of 
the  natural  law  in  man,  so  far  as  it  concerns  deliberate 
acts,  as  a  law  of  Reason.* 

t  (5)  The  precepts  of  the  natural  law.  The  precepts  of 
the  natural  law  or  the  4u^;pa-which  it  imposes  are  many, 
and  varied,  because  the  natural  appetites  are  many 
and  varied.     There  are  as  we  saw  a  number  of  appetites 

*  Not  in  the  sense  that  Reason  creates  the  law  (as  Kant  claimed), 
but  in  the  sense  that  Reason  promulgates  and  enforces  it.  This. law, 
however,  is  deduced  by  Reason  from  the  requirements  of  the  natural 
appetites.  We  sometimes  speak  of  "  right  Reason  "  as  the  criterion 
and  law  of  good  conduct.  But  it  is  to  be  remembered  that  by  "  right 
Reason  "  is  meant  Reason  as  according  with  the  claims  of  the  natural 
appetites  (see  page  174).  The  natural  law,  therefore,  is  founded  on 
the  natural  appetites  or  needs  of  man. 


646  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

which  belong  to  man  in  his  various  capacities  as  sub- 
stance, as  animal,  as  rational,  and  these  appetites  create 
necessities  for  their  several  objects,  and  the  means  to 
them,  which  necessities  we  speak  of  as  precepts  of 
nature.  From  this,  however,  we  are  not  to  conclude 
that  each  man  is  under  an  obligation  to  secure  the  ends 
of  all  the  appetites.  For,  first,  no  man  could  possibly 
attain  them  all  ;  and,  secondly,  the  interests  arising 
out  of  one  appetite  are  often  at  variance  with  those  of 
another,  and,  therefore,  both  cannot  be  attained.  Thus 
marii.ige  and  a  soldier's  duty  are  in  some  circumstances 
quite  incompatible.  It  is  for  Reason  to  determine  in 
each  case  what  is  best  for  each  one  to  do,  the  general 
principle  of  Reason  being  that  each  man  should  attain 
some  of  the  ends  which  belong  to  the  life  and  perfection 
of  the  individual  whilst  the  duty  of  attaining  what 
appertains  to  the  life  and  perfection  of  the  race  devolves, 
not  on  each  individual  but  on  the  race,  such  and  so 
man}'  individual?  only  being  required  to  share  the 
burden  who  are  necessary  for  the  attainment  of  the 
required  end. 

(6)  Relation  of  natural  to  the  eternal  law.  Froin 
within,  the  universe  is  guided  to  it-^  pndii  ^''y  TlfjillKP^ 
jaw^  But  above  and  outside  the  world  stands  the 
eternal  law  of  the  Prime  Mover,  and  in  this  law  the 
natural  law  has  its  ground  and  cause.  Now  as  the 
lio.se  is  only  a  repetition  and  a  reflection  of  tlie  idea 
of  the  architect  received  into  the  material  building,  and 
as  the  movement  of  the  arrow  is  only  an  impression  of 
the  directive  act  of  the  archer,  so,  natural_Jaw_isJo  be 
rpgniV^r:.!  as^a  reflection  :<rid  pprtj^'ipation  of  thc^etc^ial 
law.  By  this  we  do  not  mean  that  the  natural  law 
is  unreal,  that  it  is  a  mere  image,  like  the  rcllection 
of  the  sun  in  the  waters.  The  natural  law  is  a 
reflection  in  the  sense  in  which  the  house  reflects 
the  idea  of  the  architect—  it  is  a  icflection  but  real  and 
substantive. 

(7)  Universality  and  invariabilHy  of  natural  law.     In 


ON  LAW  647 

its  primary  principles  the  natural  law  is  universal,  i.e. 
it  holds  for  all,  because  the  natural  appetites  are  uni- 
versal. But  the  conclusions  from  these  principles  are 
not  all  universal  since  they  depend  on  the  circumstances 
as  well  as  the  principles. 

The  natural  law  is  also  in  some  respects  invariable. 
But  in  order  to  bring  put  its  invariability  it  is  necessary 
to  bring  out  the  different  senses  in  which  a  law  is  said 
to  vary.  Variation  may  be  either  objective  or  subjective, 
i.e.  it  may  occur  in  things  themselves  or  in  our  opinions 
about  things.  Again  it  may  occur  by  addition  [i.e. 
there  may  be  increase  in  the  number  of  laws)  or  by 
subtraction  {i.e.  a  thing  which  is  prescribed  by  law  at 
one  period  may  cease  to  hold  for  another). 

Now  subjectively,  or  in  regard  to  our  knowledge  of 
the  law,  the  natural  law  may  vary,  not  indeed  in  regard 
to  first  principles  (these,  as  we  saw,*  cannot  remain 
unknown)  but  in  regarcf  to  the  conclusions,  particularly 
the  remote  conclusions.  Objective  variation  is  possible 
in  regard  to  the  applications  of  the  first  principles  | 
since  the  applications  depend  on  the  varying  circum- 
stances of  human  action.  What  a  man  should  ea^  at 
one  period  may  not  be  necessary  at  another.  The 
question  of  objective  variation  in  the  primary  principles 
thcn:selves  has  already  been  treated.  We  saw  %  that 
the  principles  are  grounded  on  the  existence  in  us  of 
natural  needs,  which  are  themselves  based  upon  natural 
appetites.  We  saw  also  that  though  variation  in  these 
appetites,  in  the  sense  of  the  disappearance  of  some  of 
them  from  our  constitution,  or  the  appearance  of  a  new 
■appetite,  is  conceivable,  such  alteration  is  hardly  ion- 
sonant  with  the  physical  conditions  of  our  constitution. 
Also  that  if  any  appetite  were  to  disappear  it  would  not 
necessarily  involve  the  cessation  of  the  corresponding 
natural    precept.     The    conclusion    to    which    we    were 

*  page  387. 

■f  and  in  the  two  ways  m?ntioncd,  i.e.  by  addition  and  by  subtraction. 

X  page-o  3^9-393. 


648  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

led  was  that  variation  is  hardly  to  be  regarded  as 
possible  in  the  primary  natural  principles  themselves, 
though  the  widest  divergence  is  to  be  expected  in  their 
applications.  And  this  conclusion  is  in  accordance  with 
what  is  known  of  the  laws  of  development  in  the  world 
generally,  even  in  spheres  inferior  to  that  of  human 
life — viz.  permanence  in  the  great  underlying  laws  and 
forces  with  wide  variation  in  their  effects  through 
variation  in  the  circumstances  in  which  these  laws  and 
forces  are  operative. 


The  jus  gentium* 

We  shall  here  say  a  brief  word  about  a  kind  of  law  which 
is  generally  said  to  stand  midway  between  the  natural  and 
positive  law,  viz.,  the  jus  gentium.  It  mav  be  c^efincd  as 
that  porHnn  of  tVip  pncifiv^^  n^  {^nmar.  Iqm;  \{\]\ch  \?.  mmmon 
to  all  nations.  In  "  S.  TheoL,"  -I.  II.,  XCV.,  4,  we  find  an 
answer  to  the  difficulty  how  can  any  law  which  is  merely 
human  be  common  to  all  nations  since  in  things  that  depend 
on  the  will  of  the  legislator  divergence  is  always  to  be  expected. 
St.  Thomas  explains  that  there  are  some  conclusions  of  the 
natural  law  which  are  remote  and  difficult  and  about  these 
all  will  not  be  in  agreement ;  but  there  are  some  that  are 
proximate  and  easy,  and  which,  moreover,  do  not  depend 
on  variation  in  circumstance,  and  about  these  all  nations 
will  agree.  These  latter  precepts  constitute  between  them 
what  is  known  as  the  jus  gentium.^  ]w  rp:i1ifT,Y  hoinfi  mp- 
clusions  from  natural  princ[ple^  thpy^fp  n  pf^^-t-oi-Uaij  nntijr.nl 
law  strictly  so  called  ;  but  they  are  accounted  as  positive 
law,  because  tiiey  are  re-enacted  and  enforced  by  positive 
authority.  An  example  would  be  the  ordinary  natural  laws 
of  buying  and  selling,  and  the  law  forbidding  murder.  These 
are*  natural  laws.    But  they  are  re-enacted  and  enforced  by 


*  We  earnestly  recommend  the  study  of  Fr.  Cathrein's  chapter  on 
jus  gentium  in  Moralphilosophic. 

•f  It  will  be  seen,,  tliercforo,  that  the  jus  gentium  corresponds 
exactly  with  tlic  first  set  of  positive  laws  mentioiu'd  later,  page  ()50, 
viz.,  tiiose  which  are  derived  from  the  natural  principles  by  way  of 
conclusion  (as  opptxsed  to  those  derived  hy  way  of  determination)  and 
whicli  ure  of  such  importance  to  the  community  that  they  are  made  a 
part  of  the  State  code. 


ON  LAW  649 

tlie  civil  governments  for  two  reasons,  first,  because  of  their 
im}Jortance  to  the  community — men  must  be  compelled  by 
positive  sanctions  to  obey  them  ;  secondly,  because  though 
thinking  men  must  all  know  of  them  some  individuals  may 
not,  and  from  their  importance  they  must  be  brought  to  the 
knowledge  of  every  person. 

From  what  we  have  sa'id  \t  is  easy  to  account  for  the 
apparently  very  varied  views  which  have  been  taken  of  the 
meaning  of  jus  gentium.  These  views  are  not  wholly  opposed 
but  may  be  regarded  as  variants  of  the  original  definition 
considered  from  different  points  of  view.  St.  Thomas,  for 
instance,  in  addition  to  the  definition  given  above,  defines  it 
also  as  that  part  of  the  natural  law  which  is  proper  to  man, 
excluding  what  is  common  to  men  and  animals.*  But  it  is 
evident  that  the  part  of  the  natural  law  which  is  common 
to  men  and  animals,  e.g.,  the  necessity  of  food,  does  not 
require  to  be  enacted  by  positive  law  since  first  it  is  known 
to  everybody,  and  second  there  are  sufficient  inducements 
in  our  nature  to  fulfil  such  laws  without  the  intervention 
of  the  civil  legislator.  But  the  jtis  gentium  is  a  part  of  the 
positive  law.  Indeed  it  will  be  found  tliat  the  iz/.s  gentium 
applies  exclusively  to  law^  nt  pmtirp  and  justice  obtams 
amongst  men  only. 

'Other  variants  of  the  original  definition  are  to  be  found 
in  Salmond's  Jurisprudence  and  the  Moral  Philosophy  of 
Schiffini.  e.g.,  in  Roman  law  it  was  that  part  of  the  law 
which  was  common  to  Romans  and  outsiders.  Suarez 
defines  it  a<;  thnt  p--^^^  ^f  ^hp  ^^'^mon  positive  law  \^'hiVli  i-^ 
founded  on  universal  custom,  t 


*  Commentary  on  Nich.  Ethics,  V.  7.  In  S.  Theol.  I.  II.,  Q.  XCV., 
Art.  4,  St.  Thomas  speaks  more  carefully  than  in  the  Commentaries. 
He  says  that  the  jus  gentium  represents  those  conclusions  of  the  natural 
law  which  are  proximate  and  easy  and  therefore  about  which  men 
readily  agree  (and  which,  of  course,  through  their  social  importance 
are  made  also  a  part  of  the  positive  law).  He  adds  that  they  are  thus 
distinguished  from  the  pure  natural  law,  particularly  that  part  of  the 
latter  which  is  common  to  men  and  animals.  These  latter  precepts 
are  not  made  a  part  of  the  positive  law  for  the  reasons  given  in  the 
text  above. 

t  The  confusion  which  has  arisen  amongst  jurists  and  even  amongst 
some  theologians  can  easily  be  avoided  by  adhering  closely  to  the 
definition  given  by  St.  Thomas  which  clearly  corresponds  to  the 
original  conception  of  jus  gentium  amongst  the  Roman  lawyers. 

The  definition  of  jus  gentium  given  by  some  theologians  that  it 
is  that  part  of  the  law  which  depends  on  a  universal  natural  principle 
and  a  contingent  fact  is  clearly  wrong.  There  is  no  contingent  element 
in  the  law  forbidding  murder. 


650  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

ON    HUMAN    LAW 

(i)  All  human  State  laws  are  derived  fro^  ^^irl  rest 
on  the  "natural  iaw.*_  ^ome  are  derived  from  natural 
la\\^6y  way  of  conclusion,  i.e.  they  enforce  some  necessary 


conclusion  ot  the  natural  law.  Others  are  ceri\eT_^ 
way  of  determination,  i.e.  natural  law  prescribes  some 
en3^  but  it  leaves' the  means  to  that  end  undeter- 
mined. Natural  law,  e.g.,  requires  that  the  State  be 
supported,  but  it  does  not  decide  in  what  wa}^  whether 
by  voluntary  subscriptions  or  by  taxes  ;  whether  by 
direct  or  indirect  taxation.  This  is  the  work  of  the 
positive  law — to  "  determine."  as  Aquinjas  says.  "  in 
eTTcIT  case  what  nature  leaves  undetermined . ' '  These 
latter  laws  are  more  positive  than  those  which  are 
derived  by  way  of  conclusion,  since  they  depend  more 
on  human  choice.  But  it  is  important  to  remember 
that  both  kinds  ultimately  depend  on  nature,  i.e.,  on 
natural  requirements,  and,  therefore,  on  natural  law. 

(2)  Some  have  thought  that  human  laws  do  not  bind 
in  conscience.  This  is  a  very  grave  error,  and  one 
fraught  with  grave  consequences  to  the  community. f 
Human  laws  are  either  jvst  or  unjust.  If  they  are  just 
they  bind  in  conscience  by  virtue  of  the  natural  and 
eternal  law  from  which  they  arc  derived.  If  they  are 
unjust  they  do  not  bind,  and  are  not,  properly  speak- 
ing,   laws.     The    only    question,    then,    that    arises    in 

*  An  examination  of  the  ordinary  law  of  the  land  will  reveal  this 
connection.  Every  law  presupposes  some  good  to  he  attained  which 
is  not  dependent  for  its  value  upon  the  law  in  question.  Laws  arc 
enacted,  e.g.,  that  the  people  may  be  fed,  that  order  may  be  main- 
tained, that  property  may  be  safeguarded  and  so  the  common  good 
secured.  It  is  these  natural  ends  that  constitute  the  reasonableness 
of  the  law.  No  legislator  would  dream  of  introducing  a  law  which 
did  not  lend  to  the  promolit)n  of  some  natural  end. 

I  Some  ethicians,  particularly  lawyers — e.g.,  Blackstone  ((pioted  in 
Si<lgwick's  "  Methods,"  page  302) — seem  to  think  it  an  indignity  to 
human  law  to  regard  it  as  bimling  in  conscience,  so  strongly  ilo  they 
in.sist  on  its  non-moral  character.  This  attitude  we  cannot  under- 
stand. Surely  a  law  must  gain  in  dignity  and  influence  by  the  fact 
tl>at  over  ami  alxjve  the  authority  conferred  on  it  by  the  State  it  has 
ulso  authority  from  Conscience.  To  hold  with  lilackstone  is  to  bo 
uulnie  to  the  State  laws. 


ON  LAW  631 

regard  to  the  binding  power  of  a  law  is  the  question 
of  its  justice  or  its  injustice.  Nmv  to  ho.  juFft  n  ]:i\v 
should  be  just  in  respect  of  (a)  its  ends — that  is,  it 
should  be  ordained  to  the  common  good  ;  {b)  its  author 
— the  law  should  not  exceed  the  legislative  powers  of 
the  Ruler  ;  (c)  in  respect  of  jqrm — the  burden  imposed 
by  the  law  should  be  properly  distributed.  A  law  that 
is  just  in  all  these  respects  is  binding  in  conscience. 
If  it  fails  in  regard  to  any  one  of  these  it  does  not  bind, 
and  is  not  a  valid  law.* 

(3)  Human  law  possesses  neither  the  universality  nor 
the  invariability'  that  belong  to  natural  law,  for  human 
law  depends  on  the  contingent  and  varying  conditions 
of  the  State.  And  for  this  reason  it  is  sometimes  right 
and  necessary  to  change  or  abrogate  a  human  law — 
namely,  when  it  becomes  unsuitable  to  the  altered  con- 
ditions of  a  nation  and  when  its  observance  would  co 
harm.  But  a  law  should  not  be  ch-ini'T^'^  ivif^nnf  ^-ii-» 
reason,  for  change  of  law  weakens  the  very  principle  of 
law,  there  being  no  better  bulwark  for  the  protection 
of  law  against  the  tidal  wave  of  revolution  than  the 
custom  which  arises  from  long-continued  observance 
of  it.  Custom  makes  the  observance  of  a  law  seem 
easy,  whereas  a  new  law  tends  to  offend  our  sense  of 
freedom,  and  the  observance  of  it  is  always  attended 
with  some  difficultJ^ 

A  law,  we  said,  should  change  when  the  general  good 
requires  its  abolition,  but  this  change  can  only  be 
effected  by  the  law-giver.     He  can,  however,  effect  this 

*  Ethicians  generally  mention  six  qualities  of  a  true  valid  law — it 

must  be  possible,  good,  useful,  just,  permanent  and  promulgated.  All 
six  are  contained  in  the  three  given  above. 

In  regard  to  the  distinction  drawn  above  between  validity  in  respect 
of  end,  author,  and  form,  and  our  doctrine  that  to  be  valid  at  all  a  law 
should  be  valid  in  respect  of  all  three,  we  should  notice  that  in  the 
writings  of  Hegel,  Stahl  and  other  modern  jurists,  mention  is  also 
made  of  formal  validity,  not  in  our  sense,  given  above,  but  in  the  sense 
of  validity  in  respect  of  author  ;  and  the  view  is  defended  that  when  a 
law  is  formally  valid — that  is,  when  it  is  enacted  by  a  genuine  Ruler — 
tl  en,  even  though  the  (material)  contents  of  the  law  are  evil,  the  law 
is  a  genuinely  valid  law.  Tiiis  view  is  quite  opposed  to  the  teaching 
Kivcn  in  the  text  above. 


652  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

change  in  cither  of  two  wa^s — either  directly,  by  posi- 
tive personal  interference,  or  indirecth%  by  allowing  a 
contrary  custom  to  obtain.  This  second  mode  of  legis- 
lation requires  to  be  explained.  Every  law  emanates 
from  the  Reason  and  will  of  the  lawgiver.  But  a  law- 
giver may  manifest  his  wishes  by  deeds  as  well  as  by 
words  ;  and,  by  allowing  a  custom  to  obtain  against  a 
law,  a  lawgiver  may  be  regarded  as  indicating,  in  deed, 
if  not  in  word,  his  desire  for  its  abolition.  For  when 
the  violation  of  a  law  is  frequently  allowed  to  pass  un- 
noticed by  the  legislator,  his  attitude  seems  to  spring, 
not  from  sloth  or  inactivity  or  from  some  momentary 
desire,  but  from  a  deliberate  judgment  of  his  Reason  as 
to  what  should  be  done.  Hence,  custom  can  expound, 
abolish,  or  even  make  a  law. 

We  should  remark,  however,  in  regard  to  custom  that 
the  legal  value  of  custom  is  very  different  in  different 
States.  Where  the  people  are  the  rulers  (a  form  of 
government  for  which  Aquinas  makes  express  pro- 
vision), a  custom  may  more  easily  become  law  than 
under  an  absolute  monarchy,  since,  in  the  former  case, 
it  is  the  lawgivers  themselves  that  institute  the  custom. 
Wq_  should  also  remark  that  custom  of  itself  can  never 
^'nm^  ''-"^"•'^nrt  2.""  in  other  words^  custom  is  a 
material  source  of  law,  not  a  formal  source,  i.e.  it  does 
not  become  law  by  its  own  authority  as  custom,  rather 
it  becomes  law  because  it  is  regarded  as  reflecting  the 
will  of  the  legislator — it  becomes  law  by  his  authority. 

(c)  Theory  of  the  Autonomy  of  Reason 

STATEMENT   OF  THE   THEORY 

Having  distinguished  the  various  kinds  of  law,  and 
the  sources  of  each,  we  are  now  in  a  position  to  criticise 
Kant's  celebrated  theory  of  the  "  Autonomy  of  the 
Reason  " — that  is,  the  theory  that  ever}-  man  is  a  law 
to  himself,  that  each  man's  Reason  originates  the 
moral   laws   by   which   he   is   individually   bor.nd,   that 


ON  LAW  653 

actions  could  not  be  moral  if  law  proceeded  from  any 
other  source  than  a  man's  own  Reason.*  By  this 
theory  Kant  attempted  to  effect  the  same  revolution 
in  Ethical  doctrine,  which,  by  means  of  the  theory  of 
the  Categories,  he  had  already  tried  to  effect  in  the 
sphere  of  the  speculative  understanding.  For,  just  as 
in  his  doctrine  of  the  Categories,  he  made  mind,  not 
objects,  the  source  of  knowledge,  and  in  a  certain  way 
regarded  even  objects  themselves  as  the  effect  of  under- 
standing, so,  by  his  theory  of  Autonomy,  Kant  at- 
tempted to  reverse  the  traditional  Ethics,  to  show  that 
it  is  in  mind,  and  not  in  an  objective  moral  world,  that 
law  originates,  that  Reason  is  a  law  to  itself,  that  Reason 
creates  the  moral  law  to  which,  in  the  traditional  Ethics, 
it  was  supposed  to  be  merely  subject.  The  theory  that 
man  receives  the  moral  law  from  another  or  from 
anything  outside  himself  Kant  calls  the  theory  of 
"  hcteronomy."  This  theory,  he  declares,  is  the  source 
of  all  spurious  Ethics,  as  the  theory  of  Autonomy  is 
the  source  of  all  pure  and  genuine  Ethics. 

Kant's  arguments  for  Autonomy  are  the  same  as  those 
for  his  doctrine  of  Stoicism  already  explained.  Morality,  he 
insists,  must  be  categorical  f  and  universal.  From  this  he 
argues  that  it  cannot  be  grounded  in  objects  outside  the  will 
(for  objects,  in  the  first  place,  are  sought  only  as  means  to 
inner  pleasure,  and,  secondly,  are  not  universally  good, 
what  is  good  for  one  man  being  often  bad  for  another  J), 

*  The  expression  sibi  ipsi  est  lex,  which  is  sometimes  used  by  Aquinas 
in  reference  to  law,  means  not  that  each  man  is  his  own  law  but,  first, 
that  law  exists  in  the  subject  ruled  as  well  as  in  the  directing  Reason 
[in  mensnrato  as  well  as  in  mensurante),  and,  secondly,  that  it  is  only 
in  so  far  as  our  own  personal  Reason  promulgates  any  law  to  us  that 
we  are  bound  in  conscience  to  obey  it.  Aquinas'  expression,  therefore, 
sibi  ipsi  est  lex,  is  not  to  be  confounded  with  the  Kantian  conception 
of  the  Autonomy  of  Reason  referred  to  above. 

t  This  argument  has  already  been  fully  explained  and  examined 
(page  266).     It  is  repeated  here  only  for  convenience. 

X  Kant  argues,  in  addition,  that  common  opinion  refuses  to  place 
the  morality  of  an  action  in  the  effect  it  produces,  or  in  anythm» 
except  the  inner  intention.  Our  point  against  this  argument  is  that 
it  docs  not  disprove  tlie  possibility  of  morality  being  founded  on  objects, 
for  inner  intention  may  be  the  intention  to  gain  some  outer  end  or 
object. 


654  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

nor  in  sense  pleasure  (which,  being  a  feehng,  differs  in  each 
individual).  Hence  law  must  be  grounded  in  the  will  itself. 
But  it  cannot  be  grounded  in  any  inclination  of  the  will,  for 
inclination  differs  in  different  men.  Therefore,  it  is  grounded 
in  a  command  or  imperative  of  the  Will  or  Practical  Reason. 
These  arguments  we  answer  briefly  as  follows  :  (i)  Objects 
are  not  always  a  means  to  pleasure,  as  was  proved  in  our 
chapter  on  Hedonism.  (2)  Not  all  objects  are  indifferent, 
some  good  objects  could  not  be  evil  for  anybody,  some  evil 
objects  could  not  be  good  ;  also,  if  good  objects  can  be  used 
for  an  evil  purpose,  the  fault  of  this  misuse  lies  not  with  the 
object  but  with  the  will  or  intention,  and  hence  the  theory 
of  Kant,  that  Will  or  Practical  Reason  is  good  in  itself,  and  is, 
therefore,  the  proper  ground  of  morality,  cannot  be  true. 
(3)  Pleasures  do  not  differ  in  all  people  ;  at  least  the  attain- 
ment of  the  last  end  must  giv?  pleasure  to  all.  Also  the 
natural  appetites  and  their  pleasures  are  common  to  all. 

CRITICISM   OF  THE   THEORY   OF   AUTONOMY 

(i)  Law  is  a  command  laid  by  a  superior  (and,  there- 
fore, by  a  distinct  Reason)  on  an  inferior,  as  Kant  him- 
self implicitly  admits  when  he  asserts  that  "  man  always 
fincis  himself  compelled  by  his  Reason  to  transact  it 
(law)  as  if  at  the  command  of  another."  But  no  man 
can  either  he  superior  to  himself  or  can  look  upon  him- 
self as  his  own  superior.  Therefore,  no  man  can  impose 
a  law  on  himself.* 

(2)  Some  ethicians  have  tried  to  show  that  the  giving 
of  a  law  or  the  issuing  of  a  command  to  one's  self  is  a 
psychological  impossihility.  This  view  we  do  not  ac- 
cept ;  and  it  is  expressly  denied  by  Aquinas  ("  S. 
Thcol.."  I.,  II.,  Q.  XVIL,  Art.  6).  But  though  it  is 
possible  to  command  one's  self,  we  still  claim  that  if 
law  ordinarily  consisted  in  commanding  ourselves,  the 
end  of  law  would  be  in  most  cases  frustrated  ;  for  the 
end  of  law  is  to  induce  or  constrain  individuals  to  do 
certain   acts,   and   hence  it   usually   supposes   that   the 

•  Even  Kant's  claim  tlial  law  proceeds  from  Keason  as  noumeiuil, 
and  is  laid  iiiK)n  the  Reason  or  will  .is  plienonuniil,  will  not  explain 
away  this  dilhculty.  If  the  will  is  really  bouml  by  law  it  is  bound 
noumenally,  and  ntnimenal  will  is  not  superior  to  itself.  It  therefore 
cann(jt  impose  a  law  upon  itsrlf. 


ON  LAW  655 

wills  of  those  whom  it  binds  are  not  already  determined 
to  those  acts.  But  the  man  who  issues  a  command  to 
himself  to  do  a  certain  act  has  already  willed  that  act, 
else  he  could  not  have  issued  the  command.  Hence, 
autonomy  is  opposed  to  the  ordinary  end  of  law  or  to 
what  is  ordinarily  regarded  as  its  essential  effect. 

(3)  Punishment  is  a  necessary  accompaniment  of  law. 
But  on  the  theory  of  Autonomy  there  could  be  no  mean- 
ing in  punishment.  For  if  a  man's  own  Practical 
Reason  commands  him  to  do  something,  and  if  the 
same  Practical  Reason  or  will  of  the  individual  refuses 
to  do  that  something,  then  it  would  be  impossible  to 
punish  the  refractory  subject  without  punishing  also 
the  legislator,  which  is  absurd.  In  this  theory  the 
same  individual  Reason  is  both  governor  and  governed, 
the  same  man  is  both  good  and  bad — that  is,  both 
urges  to  the  doing  of  the  good  act  and  refrains  from 
doing  it.  If,  therefore,  under  this  theory  you  punish 
at  all,  you  necessarily  punish  the  good  with  the  bad, 
the  legislator  with  the  subject,  and  thereby  frustrate 
the  essential  effect  of  punishment,  which  is,  as  we  have 
already  seen,  to  neutralise  the  ill-gotten  pleasure  of  the 
evil  act  and  to  make  of  the  delincjuent  a  good  man. 
This  end  cannot  be  achieved  if  good  and  bad,  legislator 
and  subject,  are  punished  indiscriminately.* 

(4)  To  look  upon  each  man  as  his  own  legislator  is 
to  deprive  all  earthly  rulers,  and  God  Himself,  of  all 
authority  over  the  individual — a  consequence,  we  think, 
which  no  man  should  be  prepared  to  disregard.  Of 
course,  it  maj^  be  said  in  reply  that,  even  though  law 
sprang  from  our  own  Reason,  still  it  is  possible  that 
Reason  will  always  bid  us  obey  the  Divine  commands 
and  those  of  the  State,  and  that,  therefore,  Autonomy 
only    emphasises    and    confirms    the    Divine    authority. 

*  Again,  we  fail  to  sec  how  Kant's  distinction  of  noumenal  and 
phenomenal  will  affects  our  argument.  Even  if  the  noumenal  will 
issues  the  law  an'd  the  phenomenal  will  receives  and  disobeys  it,  how 
are  we,  in  inflicting  punishment,  to  secure  that  the  punislijnent  we 
inflict  will  reach  the  phenomenal  will  alone  ? 


656  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Still,  the  fact  remains  that,  even  if  our  Practical  Reason 
were  to  re-affirm  the  Divine  authority,  the  authority 
of  God  and  the  State  to  command  us  is  represented, 
in  this  theory,  as  derived  from  our  own  Reason,  a 
doctrine  which  we  cannot  but  regard  as  full  of  danger 
both  to  religion  and  to  the  State. 

(5)  If  the  logical  outcome  of  the  Critique  of  Spcat- 
lative  Reason,  in  which  Unity,  Plurality,  Causality, 
Substance,  etc.,  are  represented  as  categories  of  the 
Understanding,  is  subjectivism  (or  the  theory  that  the 
real  world  is  not  what  it  seems  to  be,  that  what  seems 
to  be  objective  fact  is  only  a  form  of  the  mind),  then 
the  logical  effect  of  deriving  the  moral  law  from  the 
individual  Reason,  as  is  done  in  the  Critique  of  Practical 
Reason,  must  be  to  substitute  for  objective  fact  a  theory 
of  subjectivism  in  Morals,  or  the  theory  that  the  Moral 
world  and  its  authorit}'  are  not  what  they  seem  to  be, 
that,  whereas  they  seem  to  hold  objectively  and  inde- 
pendently of  our  wills,  they  really  spring  from  ourselves. 
Both  theories  lead  directly  to  scepticism.* 

These  last  two  arguments,  drawn  from  the  considera- 
tion of  consequences,  should  lead  us,  if  not  to  reject 
this  theory  of  Autonomy  altogether,  at  least  to  examine 
it  closely,  and  to  require  a  full  and  adequate  statement 
of  its  grounds,  before  giving  it  any  credence.     We  have 

*  The  points  of  analogy  between  the  subjective  Categories  of  the 
Understanding  and  the  law  of  the  practical  Reason  are  very  many  in 
Kant's  theory,  and  they  serve  to  confirm  the  force  of  the  argument 
given  above — that  what  is  regarded  as  true  of  the  categories  should  be 
regarded  as  true  also  of  autonomous  law.  Some  of  these  points  of 
analogy  arc  the  following  :  (a)  Both,  it  is  assorted,  spring  not  from 
objects  but  from  subjective  faculties ;  {h)  both  are  empty  forms 
without  content  ;  (c)  both  are  applied  to  the  things  that  they  govern 
not  immediately  but  through  certain  mediating  conceptions.  The 
mediating  conceptions  in  the  case  of  the  Categories  arc  the  Schemata 
of  the  Imagination.  In  the  case  of  law  the  mediating  conception  is 
the  "  typic  of  the  Understanding  " — that  is,  a  universal  case  of  tlie 
realisation  of  law  in  concrete  nature.  This  typic,  Kant  tells  us,  is 
none  other  than  the  Categorical  Imperative.  The  distinction  between 
the  schemata  and  the  typic  in  Kant's  theory  is  that  whereas  the 
schemata  are  applied  to  objects  which  the  Understanding  does  not 
create,  the  typic  is  applied  to  acts  which  the  Practical  Keason  creates 
—namely,  moral  acts. 


ON  LAW  657 

shown,  in  the  present  section,  that  the  grounds  on 
which  this  theor}'  rests  are  neither  adequate  nor  con- 
vincing. 

THEORY   OF   WILL   AUTONOMY 

The  Kantian  doctrine  of  the  Autonomy  of  Reason  has 
of  late  been  superseded  by  other  theories  of  Autonomy, 
two  of  which  we  shall  notice  very  briefly  here — namely, 
that  of  Will- Autonomy  and  that  of  Immanent  Heter- 
onomy  (the  latter  tlieory  being  radically  a  theory  of 
Autonomy,  though  opposed  to  Autonomy  in  name). 

The  cardinal  principle  of  the  theory  of  Will-Autonomy, 
as  expounded,  e.g.,  by  Dr.  Lipps,*  is  that  man  is  a  law 
to  himself,  not  because  Reason  commands  him  to  do 
certain  acts,  but  because  he  has  from  nature  an  appetite 
for  these  acts.  The  man  who  does  anything  from  inclina- 
tion, Dr.  Lipps  tells  us,  acts  from  himself,  and  he  who 
acts  from  himself  is  rightly  regarded  as  autonomous. 

Our  criticism  of  this  theory  is  that  to  have  an  inclina- 
tion to  do  something  and  to  impose  on  ourselves  a 
moral  law  (which  latter  is  the  assumption  contained  in 
every  theor}^  of  Autonomy)  are  very  different  concep- 
tions. There  are  thousands  of  things  to  which  a  man 
is  inclined  by  virtue  of  the  appetites  within  him,  which, 
yet,  a  man  is  free  to  resist,  and  hence,  even  though  our 
appetites  may  be  the  basis  of  a  law,  still  the  full  necessity 
of  moral  law  could  not  consist  in  them  alone.  They 
could  not  give  rise  to  the  categorical  necessity  of  attain- 
ing their  objects  which  is  essential  to  moral  law.  The 
theory  of  Will-Autonomy,  therefore,  cannot  be  regarded 
as  a  sufficient  account  of  law  or  obligation.! 

*  "  Die  Ethischen  Grundfragcn,"  Lectures  4  and  5.  This  theory 
of  Dr.  Lipps  we  regard  as  a  natural  and  necessary  reaction  against 
the  extreme  intellectual  formalism  of  Kant's  doctrine. 

t  Dr.  Lipps  regards  blind  obedience  to  the  will  of  another  as  sinful, 
since  blind  obedience  does  not  distinguish  prudent  and  rightful  from 
imprudent  and  wrong  obedience.  The  same  theory  is  taught  by 
Fichte.  Our  answer  is  that  Religion  (Dr.  Lipps'  attack  is  mainly  on 
the  obedience  of  religion)  never  inculcates  blind  obedience  in  thifs 
sense.  Religion  and  the  natural  law  forbid  us  to  obey  any  command 
of  any  superior  which  is  evidently  wrong  or  unjust. 
Vol.  1—42 


658  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

THEORY   OF   IMMANENT  HETERONOMY 

The  theory  of  Immanent  Heteronomy  is  explained 
and  defended  by  Ed.  von  Hartmann  in  the  chapter 
"  Heteronomie  and  Autonomie "  of  the  "  Ethische 
Stiidien."  The  supreme  lawgiver,  he  tells  us,  lives 
not  without,  but  within,  the  world,  and  is  not  distinct 
from  ourselves.  The  theory  that  places  Him  in  in- 
visible light  beyond  the  world — the  pseudo-moral  theory, 
as  he  calls  it,  of  transcendent  heteronomy — is  a  result 
of  a  certain  illusory  process  of  "  projection,"  by  which 
what  is  really  within  us  is  represented  by  our  imagina- 
tion as  without. 

On  the  other  hand,  we  must  not  identify  the  supreme 
lawgiver,  as  Kant  did,  with  our  individual  Reason,  since 
individual  Reason  could  only  give  rise  to  contingent 
precepts  without  either  the  binding  power  or  the  per- 
manence of  genuine  laws. 

The  true  lawgiving  Reason  is  the  Reason  or  mind  of 
society,  and  this  Reason  Ed.  von  Hartmann  (following 
the  doctrine  of  the  Solidarists  already  noticed)  explains 
as  the  true  being  and  substance  of  all  individual  minds. 
This  Universal  Reason  being  one  with  humanity,  the 
source  of  human  law  is  immanent  in  the  world  ;  being, 
however,  wider  than  individuals  it  is  to  be  regarded  as 
a  heteronomous  principle  in  so  far  as  it  legislates  for 
individuals. 

"  Immanent  Heteronomy,"  he  writes,*  "  is  heter- 
onomy only  for  the  individual  as  such,  but,  for  the 
whole  people,  as  individual  of  a  higher  order,  it  is 
autonomy.  .  .  .  The  lawgiver  in  the  case  of  this  heter- 
onomy is  not  an  external  ego  but  the  people  themselves 
— the  higher  (social)  organism,  of  which  each  indi- 
gental  feels  and  knows  that  he  is  a  member  and  an 
uiif  al  part.  The  individual  is  a  part  and  member  of 
vsd  lawgiver,  and  (therefore)  participates  in  the  law- 
giving of  the  State  .  .  .  according  to  the  degree  in  which 

•  "  Ethibchc  Studicn,"  page  114. 


ON  LAW  659 

his  (share  of)  membership  allows  him  to  participate  (in 
the  making  of  its  laws).  ...  In  this  sense  heteronomy 
may  to  some  extent  be  looked  on  as  a  system  of  laws 
left  us  by  past  generations,  as  a  kind  of  inherited  social 
autonomy,  in  so  far  as  the  living  generation  is  originally 
one  with  its  direct  predecessors,  and  cannot  be  thought 
of  out  of  that  relation." 

Criticism. — The  chief  points  in  this  theory  of  "  Im- 
manent Heteronomy  "  that  arise  for  criticism  have 
already  been  noticed  in  various  parts  of  this  work. 
Thus,  the  doctrine  that  the  individual  is  not  distinct 
from  society,  but  is  related  to  it  as  a  mere  part  is  related 
to  the  whole,  is  fully  examined  in  connection  with  the 
theory  of  the  Solidarists  in  our  chapter  on  Utilitarianism. 

As  regards  the  main  contention  of  Ed.  von  Hart- 
mann — the  contention,  namely,  that  law  is  imposed  on 
the  individual  by  the  Universal  Consciousness — our 
criticism  is  that,  if  this  Universal  Consciousness  is 
really  one  with  the  individual  consciousness,  then  the 
theory  of  Immanent  Heteronomy  is  open  to  all  the 
arguments  that  we  have  brought  against  the  general 
theory  of  Autonomy  as  formulated  by  Kant.  If  it  is 
not  one  with  the  individual,  then,  in  so  far  as  it  is  not 
one  with  him,  it  is  not  a  theory  of  Autonomy  but  of 
Heteronom}^  of  Transcendent  (not  immanent)  Heter- 
onomy, and  the  supposed  difficulties  of  Heteronomy 
hold,  therefore,  against  it  as  against  any  other  heter- 
onomous  theory  of  Morals.* 

*  On  account  of  its  importance  we  have  reserved  the  following 
note  until  the  end  of  our  criticism  of  the  "  autonomous  "  theories. 
It  seems  to  us  that  the  ruling  idea  in  all  these  theories  is  that  since 
man  is  a  person,  self-contained  and  self-directed,  it  would  be  an  in- 
dignity to  his  nature  to  regard  him  as  deix;ndent  on  laws  laid  upon 
lum  from  outside  himself.  The  perfection  of  a  self-directed  being 
must  consist  in  accordance  with  laws  laid  on  him  by  himself.  To 
regard  Reason  as  subject  to  laws  imposed  from  outside  itself  is  to  rank 
Reason  as  on  a  par  with  the  mere  animal  world  which  is  in  no  way 
self -direc  live. 

Now  with  this  reasoning  we  agree  so  far  as  to  admit  that  Reason 
cannot  be  expected  blindly  to  submit  to  laws  laid  upjn  it  from  outside. 
It  would  be  an  indignity  to  Reason  to  ask  it  to  submit  to  law.,  that  it 
did  not  itself  approve  as  good  and  right,  and  as  imposed  by  a  ngatful 


CHAPTER  XX 
ON  RIGHTS 

NOTION   OF   RIGHT 

Law,  as  we  have  seen,  is  a  binding  rule,  of  action.  It 
is  the  expression  of  the  will  of  a  Lawgiver  binding  us 
to  do  or  to  avoid  certain  things.  Now,  sometimes  that 
to  which  the  Law  obliges  one  is  the  doing  of  some 
good  to  another  person  or  the  refraining  from  doing 
him  an  evil.  The  effect  of  such  a  law  is  to  establish 
in  one  person  the  duty  to  do  or  not  to  do  something, 
and  in  the  other  person  the  right  to  its  being  done  or 
avoided. 

Right,  then,  is  a  result  of  law.  It  springs  from  law 
simultaneously  with  duty.  Right  and  duty  are  the  two 
termini  of  the  one  relation  created  by  law.  Thus,  the 
law  that  binds  a  man  to  pay  for  what  he  buys,  estab- 
lishes a  relation  between  the  seller  and  the  buyer,  which 
relation  is,  on  the  side  of  the  seller,  a  right  to  payment, 
and,  on  the  side  of  the  buyer,  a  duty  of  payment.  So, 
also,  the  law  that  binds  parents  to  support  their  children 
establishes  in  the  parent  the  duty,  and  in  the  child  the 
right  of  support. 

Now,  it  is  evident  from  the  examples  we  have  just 
given — that  of  the  seller  of  goods  and  that  of  the  child — 

authority.  Under  no  circumstances  could  Reason  be  asked  to  submit 
to  laws  that  it  regarded  as  wrong  or  unjust.  Now,  by  giving  to  laws 
laid  upon  it  from  without  the  sanction  of  its  own  approval  before  it 
proceeds  to  obey,  Reason  in  a  sense  may  be  said  to  lay  these  laws  on 
itself — in  which  sense  Aquinas  uses  the  phrase  "  sibi  ipsi  est  lex." 
But  from  this  it  does  not  follow  that  Reason  creates  the  laws  by  which 
it  is  governed.  Law  bears  the  same  relation  to  Reason  in  the  practical 
that  it  does  in  the  speculative  sphere.  It  is  not  considered  an  indignity 
to  Reason  that  it  should  have  to  submit  in  its  reasonings  to  laws  or 
principles  of  Mathematics.  Now  the  laws  of  MatluMuatics  are  dis- 
covered and  proved  (and  ajiprovi-d)  by  the  Reason — but  tiiey  are  not 
created  by  tlie  Riisnn.  So  millM^r  are  the  moral  laws  created  by  our 
Reason. 

660 


ON  RIGHTS  66i 

that  right  is  always  a  power  of  some  kind,  something 
which  enables  one  to  have  or  to  do  something.  But 
right  is  a  power  of  a  very  particular  kind,  as  will  be 
seen  from  the  following  example.  Every  man  has  a 
right  to  the  exercise  of  his  faculties.  He  has  a  right 
to  walk,  to  speak,  to  work,  to  eat,  without  interference 
from  other  people.  Now,  a  man's  power  to  keep  off 
unjust  interference  from  others  is  two-fold.  First,  he 
can  ward  off  interference  by  means  of  physical  power — 
the  physical  power  of  hands,  and  feet,  and  firearms. 
But  this  is  evidently  not  the  kind  of  power  referred  to 
when  men  speak  of  right.  For,  even  when  physical 
force  avails  us  nothing,  when,  for  instance,  others  so 
overpower  us  that  we  are  unable  to  resist  them 
physically,  or  even  when  the  State  is  unwilling  or  un- 
able to  help  us,  there  still  remains  to  us  in  many  cases 
another  power  in  virtue  of  which  we  are  justified  in 
claiming  something  as  ours,  of  calling  something  our 
own,  even  though  we  know  we  may  never  succeed  in 
keeping  or  obtaining  that  thing.  This  power  we  speak 
of  as  a  moral  power.  It  is  the  power  conferred  on  us 
by  the  moral  law,  a  law  which  forbids  undue  interference 
with  our  liberty,  a  law  which  creates  in  others,  if  not 
the  desire,  at  least  the  duty  to  respect  our  liberty.  And 
to  this  moral  power  we  give  the  name  of  right,  which, 
therefore,  we  define  as  the  "  moral  power  (facultas)  of 
doing  or  possessing  something."  The  existence  of  such 
a  power  in  us  depends  on  the  existence  of  a  moral  law, 
from  which  law  right  follows  as  necessarily  as  an}'  effect 
follows  from  its  cause.  If  there  be,  for  instance,  in 
existence  a  moral  law  that  parents  should  support  and 
educate  their  children,  then  children  have  a  right  to 
support  and  education.  Right,  as  we  said,  is  a  relation 
established  by  law,  and,  we  repeat,  it  is  a  necessary 
consequence  of  law. 

The  question  how  far  this  kind  of  power  is  cficacious 
— that  is,  how  far  it  is  able  to  influence  men  to  avoid 
injustice — is  outside  the  scope  of  our  present  enquiry. 


662  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

which  concerns  the  meaning  of  right  only.  But  it  may 
not  be  out  of  place  at  this  point  to  quote  our  view  that, 
though  bad  men  may  respect  only  ph3sical  power,  with 
good  men  the  moral  power  would  seem  to  be  the  more 
efficacious,  for  most  good  men  avoid  injustice,  not 
because  of  the  terrors  of  punishment,  but  from  an 
inner  sense  of  their  duty  to  others,  and  of  respect  for 
others'  rights. 

THE   PROPERTIES   OF   RIGHT 

Right  has  three  principal  properties — namely,  {a)  in- 
violability, {b)  limitation,  (c)  coaction.* 

Inviolahility.  The  first  and  fundamental  property  of 
right  is  its  inviolability,  or  the  fact  that  a  man  must 
not  be  interfered  with  in  the  exercise  of  his  right.  By 
inviolability  we  mean  that  if  a  man  has  a  right  to  sing, 
to  walk,  to  hunt,  then  no  one  can  lawfully  prevent 
him  from  doing  these  things.  Every  right  involves  this 
property  of  inviolability — that  is,  every  right  involves 
necessarily  and  essentially,  besides  the  conception  of 
lawfulness  to  do  a  thing,  the  conception  of  a  duty  in 
some  other  person  not  to  hinder  the  doing  of  it.f  In 
no  intelligible  sense  could  I  be  said  to  have  a  right  to 
walk  the  street  if  every  man  could  lawfully  prevent  me 
from  doing  so.  J 

Limitation  means  that  one  right  can  limit  the  exer- 

•  Our  meaning  for  these  expressions  is  not  quite  the  same  as  that 
given  by  some  Scholastics. 

I  Germap  writers  give  to  the  conception  of  "  lawfulness  to  do  " 
or  "  not  to  do  "  the  name  Erlaubtheit,  whilst  inviolability  they  call 
Unversetzlich  keit. 

The  existence  of  defeasible  rights,  or  rights  that  can  be  withdrawn, 
does  not  affect  the  view  stated  above  that  all  rights  are  inviolable. 
For  even  defeasible  rights  are  inviolable  as  long  as  they  remain 

X  Writers  on  Jurisprudence  give  prominence  to  the  division  of 
rights  into  real  and  personal.  The  former  avail  against  every  man, 
e.g.,  one's  right  peaceably  to  occupy  one's  house,  a  patimtee's  riglit  to 
his  invention.  The  second  is  a  rif;ht  aj^uinst  six'citic  persons,  e.g.,  a 
servant's  right  to  receive  wages.  Now,  manifestly,  what  is  here  called 
real  right  is  nothing  more  tlian  the  proi)erty  of  inviolability,  and  since 
it  attaches  to  every  right,  the  division  of  rights  into  real  and  personal, 
though  convenient,  is  not  properly  speaking  a  division  of  rights. 


ON  RIGHTS  663 

cise  of  another,  that  in  the  exercise  of  a  right  we  are 
not  free  to  disregard  the  counter-claims  of  others.  We 
must  conceive  the  moral  laws  from  which  rights  spring 
as  making  up  one  organic  system,  just  as  the  parts  of 
the  body  make  up  one  organic  bodily  system.  And  just 
as  the  functions  of  one  part  of  an  organism  limit  the 
functions  of  others — that  is,  as  no  part  should  be  exer- 
cised prejudicially  to  the  others — so  due  regard  must 
be  had  in  exercising  any  right,  or  in  following  any  law, 
to  the  whole  system  of  rights  and  laws  that  regulate 
human  conduct.  Thus,  the  law  which  gives  a  man 
power  to  keep  for  himself  what  he  produces  is  limited 
and  conditioned  by  other  laws,  such  as  the  law  of 
charit}',  which  binds  a  man  to  help  his  neighbour.  Also, 
the  right  of  one  man  to  liberty  in  the  use  of  his  faculties 
is  limited  by  the  right  of  another  man  to  the  same. 
The  extent  of  a  man's  rights  depends  largely  upon  this 
property  of  limitation. 

Coaction.  The  third  property  of  right  is  that  of 
coaction  [Erzwingbarkcit).  The  power  or  right  of  co- 
action  is  the  moral  power  that  attaches  to  each  right 
of  using  such  violence  as  is  necessary  for  its  defence. 
Naturally  the  necessity  for  violent  defence  appertains 
to  external  rights  only.  Thus,  a  father  could  not  com- 
pel the  love  of  his  children  by  violence,  though  he  has 
a  right  to  their  love.  But  external  rights,  like  that 
of  property,  carry  with  them  this  right  of  defence  or 
of  coaction — a  power  which  arises  from  the  fact  that  he 
who  has  a  right  to  the  end  has  a  right  to  such  means 
as  are  necessary  for  obtaining  the  end.  Hence,  if  a  man 
has  a  right  to  possess  a  house,  he  has  a  right  to  the 
use  of  violence,  either  personally  or  through  the  State, 
in  its  defence,  provided,  as  we  have  said  in  the  last 
paragraph, -that  in  defending  his  house  he  offend  against 
no  law  and  no  other  person's  right. 

We  may  here  call  attention  to  two  erroneous  theories 
on  the  relation  of  right  to  coactive  power,  which  are  to 
be  found  in  the  wprks  of  Ihering,   Hegel,  Thomasius, 


664  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

and  other  modern  ethicians.  The  first  is  the  view  that 
the  power  of  coaction  which  attaches  to  right  is  to  be 
regarded,  not  as  a  property  of  right,  but  as  its  essence, 
that  right  is  coactive  power.  Thus,  Ihering  *  defines 
right  in  one  place  as  the  "  conception  of  all  the  coactive 
laws  obtaining  in  a  State,"  and,  in  another  place,  as 
"  the  securing  of  the  conditions  of  social  life  in  the  form 
of  coercive  power."  And  Hegel  t  defines  abstract  right 
as  the  "  right  to  use  force."        -—    (-'—  "^i-^^^^-r- 

Now,  we  maintain  that  right  cannot  be  the  same 
thing  as  power  of  coaction,  since  the  power  of  coaction 
presupposes  right,  and  follows  from  it  as  a  consequence. 
It  would  be  an  absurd  thing,  for  instance,  for  the  State 
to  defend  a  man's  property  unless  it  knew  that  the  man 
had  a  right  to  his  property.  Defence,  therefore,  pre- 
supposes the  right  of  ownership,  and,  hence,  it  is  pro- 
perly regarded  as  a  consequence  of  right — not  as  its 
essence. 

The  second  error  referred  to  concerns  the  nature  of 
this  power  of  coaction.  The  reader  will  remember  that 
when  we  spoke  of  coactive  power  as  a  property  of  right 
we  defined  coactive  power  as  the  right  to  coaction,  not 
as  actual  coaction  or  the  physical  power  of  coaction. 
By  coaction  here  we  mean  that  a  man  who  owns  a 
hoi.se  has  a  right  to  defend  his  house  against  aggressors. 
But  many  of  those  ethicians  to  wliom  we  have  just 
referred  identify  right,  not  with  the  right  of  coaction, 
but  with  actual  physical  power  of  coaction,  so  that, 
according  to  these  philosophers,  a  right  to  anything  is 
nothing  more  than  the  actual  phjsical  power  that  we 
possess  to  defend  or  liold  that  thing.  Now,  this  theory 
we  cannot  allow.  In  the  first  place,  right  is  not  the 
same  thing  as  coaction ;  and,  in  the  second  place,  right 
docs  not  involve  a  physical  power  of  actual  coaction, 
but  only  the  right  to  coaction  in  its  defence.  A  man 
has  still  a  right  to  his  house  even  though  he  is  not 

•  In  his  work,  "  Der  Zwcck  im  Rccht." 
•f  "  IMiilosophy  of  Uight  "  (Dydo),  page  92, 


ON  RIGHTS  665 

able  to  defend  it,  and  even  though  the  State  will  not 
defend  it  for  him.  Might  and  right  are  very  different 
things.  Right  appertains  to  the  moral,  might  to  the 
physical  world.  Right  is  a  moral  power,  might  is  only 
brute  force.  We  may  have  a  right,  therefore,  to  a  thing 
which  still  we  are  unable  to  defend.  But  what,  it  may 
be  asked,  is  the  good  of  a  right  that  cannot  be  defended 
by  actual  violence — what  good,  for  instance,  is  the  right 
to  a  house  that  we  cannot  defend,  and  which  the  State 
refuses  to  defend  ?  "  What  is  right  without  power," 
asks  Ihering,*  "  but  a  fire  that  burns  not — a  light  that 
does  not  illumine  ?  "  We  answer — right  without  might 
is  like  the  fire  that  is  smothered  and  will  not  be  allowed 
to  burn,  the  light  that  is  shut  in,  so  that  it  cannot 
illumine.  Right  without  might  is,  therefore,  a  real 
thing,  just  as  the  moral  law  is  a  real  thing.  And  it 
has  this  effectiveness,  that  he  who  violates  it  sins  against 
the  moral  law — a  consideration,  as  we  have  already 
said,  that  may  not  weigh  with  evil  men  who  care  nothing 
for  justice,  but  which  will  weigh  with  the  just  who  hate 
evil  of  every  kind,  and  will  respect  a  man's  liberty  and 
property  even  though  the  State  fail  in  its  duty  to  defend 
them.  But  we  must  remember,  also,  that,  even  though 
a  right  of  nature  be  undefended  by  the  State,  it  will 
not  remain  undefended  by  nature  herself,  and  that 
every  right  will  in  the  end  be  vindicated  by  nature's 
Chief  Legislator.  Right,  even  though  it  may  not  alwa3's 
be  vindicated  here,  must  necessarily  be  vindicated  at 
some  time  and  in  some  place. 

But  the  point  on  which  we  wish  now  to  insist  is  that 
every  right  involves  a  right  of  its  defence,  and  that 
the  right  to  defend  may  still  remain,  even  though  w^e 
be  not  physically  able  to  use  our  right.  It  is  to  this 
right  of  defence  that  we  allude  when  we  say  that  co- 
action  is  a  property  of  right. 

*  We  should  explain  that  even  though  Ihering  regards  right  as 
meaningless  without  power  of  actual  coaction,  he  also  regards  it  as 
meaningless  without  a  moral  law. 


656  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

DIVISION    OF   RIGHTS 

Rights  are  divided  in  respect  of — 

meaning  into  objective  and  subjective. 
ground  into  natural  and  positive  (or  human), 
origin  into  connatural  and  acquired. 
yi^subject  into  public  and  private. 
object  into   (a)  affirmative  and  negative,  and  into   {b)  in- 
alienable and  alienable  rights.* 
binding  power  into  perfect  and  imperfect,  or  juridical  and 
non-juridical, 
(i)  Objective  Right  means  that  thing  to  which  we  have  a 
right — the  act  which  we  have  a  riglit  to  do, 
the  object  which  we  have  a  right  to  possess. 
Subjective  right  is  our  moral  power  or  claim  to  do  or 
have  that  thing. 

(2)  Natural  right  is  a  right  conferred  by  and  grounded  upon 

natural  law. 
Positive  right  is  a  right  conferred  by  and  grounded  upon 
positive  law. 

(3)  Connatural  right  is  a  right  which  one  possesses  from 

birth  independently  of  any  human  conditions 
— for  instance,  the  right  to  life.  Even  from 
birth  a  child  may  have  a  right  to  certain 
lands  willed  to  him  by  his  father,  yet,  since 
such  a  right  depends  on  a  human  condition, 
we  do  not  speak  of  it  as  connatural. 
Acquired  right  is  a  right  which  we  come  to  possess  in  time 
on  the  fulfilment  of  some  condition — for 
instance,  a  man's  right  to  payment  for  goods 
sold.f 

(4)  Public  right  is  the  right  of  a  perfect  community  to  have 

or  do  something. 
^Private  right  is  the  right  of  a  particular  individual,  or  a 
family,  or  of  an  institution  which  is  not  a 
perfect  community. 

■ r ___ 

*  Divisions  in  respect  of  object  are  innumerable  Most  of  these 
mentioned  in  Salmond's  Jurisprudence  (page  222)  are  in  respect  of 
object. 

t  It  should  be  noticed  that  acquired  rights,  though  opposed  to  con- 
natural rights,  arc  not  opposed  to  natural.  Tlius,  a  man's  riglit  to 
payment  for  goods  sold  is  an  acquired  right,  but  natural.  Another 
distinction  depending  on  origin  is  that  of  primary  and  sanctioning 
rights.  IVimary  right  is  one  that  arises  from  law  directly  :  sanction- 
ing rights  arise  directly  from  a  wrong  and  only  remotely  from  law, 
e.g.,  riglit  to  damages  for  breach  of  contract.  The  distinction,  however, 
is  not  fundamental. 


ON  RIGHTS  667 

(5)  Affirmative  right  is  a  right  to  do  or  have  something  done. 
Negative  right  is  a  right  to  abstain  from  doing,  or  a  right 

that  something  should  not  be  done. 
Inalienable  rights  are  rights  to  things  which  are  also  our 

duty,   and  to  which,   therefore,   we   cannot 

renounce  our  right,  e.g.,  the  right  to  life. 
Alienable  rights  are  rights  that  we  can  renounce — for 

instance,  the  right  to  drink  alcohol. 

(6)  Perfect,  or  juridical,  or  legal  right  is  a  right  which  is 

strictly  enjoined  by  law  (whether  by  the 
natural  law  or  the  law  of  the  State),  It  is 
therefore  a  right  the  fulfilment  of  which  is 
absolutely  necessary  to  morality  as  long  as 
the  law  which  establishes  the  right  stands. 
Examples  are  the  right  of  a  seller  to  pay- 
ment, of  a  child  to  support,  of  a  parent  to 
respect  from  his  children. 
/,  Imperfect,  or  non-juridical,  or  non-legal  rights  *  are  rights 
which,  though  not  strictly  enjoined  by  law, 
and  consequently  not  strictly  necessary  for 
morality,  yet  are  necessary  to  the  seemliness 
of  morality  and  of  virtue.  Now,  of  these 
latter  rights  some  are  more  necessary  than 
others,  for  some  are  necessary  to  the  decencies 
of  ordinary  virtue  [ad  honestafem  maris),  whilst 
others  are  necessary  only  for  the  more  per- 
fect life,  or  for  the*  fulness  of  morality  and 
virtue  {ad  majorem  honestatem).  Thus,  to  tell 
a  lie,  apart  altogether  from  its  being  a  viola- 
tion of  God's  law  or  of  the  natural  law,  is 
also  an  offence  against  him  to  whom  we  lie. 
It  is,  therefore,  not  in  accordance  with  the 
decencies  of  ordinary  social  life,  which  forbid 
our  being  offensive  to  other  people.  Conse- 
quently, even  if  a  lie  were  not  a  wrong  to  my 
own  nature,  it  would  be  wrong  as  offending 
against  an  imperfect  right  of  him  to  whom 
we  tell  the  lie.  Again,  to  be  ungrateful  to  a 
benefactor,  though  not  strictly  forbidden  by 
any  definite  law,  is  still  an  offence  against 
the  ordinary  decencies  of  social  life.  A  bene- 
factor, therefore,  has  an  imperfect  right  to 
gratitude. 
But  there  is,  as  we  said,  a  second  class  of 

♦  Or,  as  they  are  soinetinacs  called,  claims. 


668  .      THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

imperfect  right.  There  are  many  things 
which  are  not  due  to  others,  which  they 
cannot  claim  from  us,  to  omit  which  is  no 
offence  against  others,  but  whicli  yet  are 
necessary  jf  we  would  be  perfect  men  per- 
sonally and  socially — for  instance,  we  must 
be  both  affable  and  liberal  with  others. 
These  rights  arc  necessary  only  for  the 
fulness  of  morality. 

Now,  these  three  examples  of  rights — that 
others  should  not  tell  us  lies,  that  those  whom 
we  benefit  should  be  grateful  to  us,  that  men 
should  treat  us  affably  and  with  some 
liberality — are  all  cases  of  imperfect  rights 
or  claims,  and  the  duties  that  correspond  to 
these  rights  are  imperfect  duties.* 

The  meaning  here  given  to  the  expression 
"  imperfect  right  "  is  that  which  generally 
attaches  to  it  in  Scholastic  works.  And,  as 
this  meaning  is  frequently  distorted  by 
recent  writers  on  Ethics,  it  may  be  well  to 
repeat  that  a  perfect  right  is  one  that  is 
bestowed  in  strictness  by  law  whether  that 
law  be  a  law  of  nature  or  of  the  State,  and 
that,  therefore,  a  right  can  be  perfect  even 
though  it  is  not  conferred  by  the  State,  or 
even  though  the  State  could  not  or  would 
not  vindicate  it  in  the  sense  of  enforcing  its 
observance.  Kant  and  his  followers  (includ- 
ing, indeed,  most  modern  writers  on  Juris- 
prudence, e.g.,  Salmond)  have  no  ground,  it 
seems  to  us,  for  the  narrow  view  they  take 
of  perfect  right.  A  man's  right  to  get  back 
money  that  has  been  stolen,  but  which  he 

*  It  is  possible  that  the  same  thing  might  be  a  perfect  duty  from  or  e 
point  of  view  and  imperfect  from  another.  Thus,  we  are  bound  to 
refrain  from  lies  by  a  two-fold  duty — a  perfect  duty  not  to  violate  rur 
own  nature  and  an  imperfect  duly  to  refrain  from  the  offence  which 
the  lie  offers  to  another  person.  Kant  draws  a  different  distinction 
from  that  given  above  between  juridical  and  non-juridical  or  f'Hhic;'! 
duties.  Juridical  duties,  he  says,  are  those  that  can  be  enforced  both 
by  our  inner  conscience  and  by  external  legislation.  Ethical  duties 
are  those  that  cannot  be  enforced  by  external  legislation.  Juridical 
duties  he  also  calls  perfect  or  determinate  duties,  or  officia  juris. 
Kthical  duties  he  calls  imperfect,  or  indeterminate  duties,  or  officia 
virtiitis.  Kant  is,  however,  not  always  consistent  in  his  use  o|  these 
terms. 


ON  RIGHTS  669 

cannot  prove  was  stolen,  and  which,  as  a 
consequence,  the  State  will  not  help  him  to 
recover,  is  a  perfect  right  even  though  the 
State  will  not  enforce  it. 

& 

THAT   SOME   RIGHTS   ARE   NATURAL 

We  distinguished  above  between  natural  and  positive 
(or  human)  rights — that  is,  betw^een  rights  conferred 
by  natural  law  and  rights  conferred  by  human  law. 
Now,  many  ethicians  deny  that  any  rights  are  natural, 
and  insist  that  all  rights  are  conferred  by  positive 
human  law  or  by  the  State.  This  theory  it  will  not  be 
necessary  to  disprove  here.  For  we  have  already 
shown  that  the  natural  law  is  a  reality,  and  since  right 
is  a  consequence  of  law,  it  follows  that  any  particular 
right  must  necessarily  take  on  the  character  of  the 
law  in  which  it  originates.  The  natural  law,  therefore, 
will  give  rise  to  natural  rights,  as  the  positive  law  con- 
fers positive  rights.  Thus,  the  right  which  every  man 
has  to  his  own  life,  and  to  such  means  as  are  necessary 
for  sustaining  it,  is  a  natural  right.  Also,  the  right  of 
men  to  the  fullilment  of  contract,  to  their  good  name, 
to  the  fruits  of  their  labour,  the  right  of  a  husband  to 
fidelity  on  the  part  of  his  wife,  the  right  of  parents  to 
respect  on  the  part  of  their  children,  and  of  children  to 
support  on  the  part  of  parents,  the  right  of  the  State  to 
:o-operation  and  obedience  on  the  part  of  its  subjects, 
and  of  subjects  to  protection  by  the  State,  the  right  of 
individual  liberty  (within  certain  well-defined  limits),  or 
of  immunity  from  interference  from  others,  the  right  of 
personal  development,  the  right  of  the  State  to  main- 
tain itself  and  to  oppose  aggression  from  other  States — 
all  these  rights  are  from  nature,  since  the  laws  on  which 
they  are  grounded  are  natural  laws,  these  laws  being 
again  grounded  on  natural  appetites,  as  we  saw  in  our 
chapters  on  The  Good  and  on  Law. 

Taking  it  for  granted,  then,  that  by  making  good  our 
doctrine  that  some  appetites  and  laws  are  natural,  we 


670  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

have  also  shown  that  some  rights  are  natural,  we  now 
go  on  to  prove  our  thesis  negatively — that  is,  we  go  on 
to  meet  the  principal  objections  which  modern  Ethicians 
have  raised  against  our  doctrine  of  Natural  rights. 

Objections, 

(i)  It  has  been  contended  by  Neukamp  *  that  rights 
concern  the  public  welfare,  as  "  Medicine "  concerns 
the  individual  welfare.  But  medical  laws  are  deter- 
mined empiricall}^  from  the  known  requirements  of 
bodies.  Therefore,  rights  also  should  be  determined 
empirically.  But,  if  rights  be  natural,  they  are  deter- 
mined not  empirically,  but  a  priori — that  is,  from  some 
a  priori  view  of  what  man  ought  to  be  rather  than  from 
what  he  is.     Therefore,  rights  are  not  natural. 

Reply. — If  Rights  follow  the  analogy  of  medicine 
they  must  be  natural.  For,  though  medical  laws  are 
discovered  by  the  investigation  of  our  human  constitu- 
tion, still  the  aim  of  such  empirical  investigation  is, 
first  and  before  all,  to  determine  the  natural  require- 
ments of  the  body — that  is,  to  determine  what  the 
human  body  requires  in  order  that  it  may  come  up  to 
nature's  standard.  For  this  purpose  we  determine  the 
natural  position  and  structure  of  the  organs,  their  func- 
tions and  natural  needs,  and  on  the  consideration  of 
these  natural  requirements  we  build  our  science  of 
medicine.  Now,  upholders  of  the  theory  of  natural 
rights  determine  rights  after  the  very  same  fashion  as 
this.  They  determine  rights  not  a  priori,  as  our  op- 
ponents claim,  but  by  an  empirical  investigation  of  our 
constitution  and  needs  and  the  laws  to  which  these 
needs  give  rise  ;  and  having  thus  determined  nature's 
standard  they  deduce  from  it  the  table  of  our  natural 
duties  and  natural  rights.  The  analogy  with  medicine, 
therefore,  strengthens  rather  than  disproves  our  theory 
of  the  existence  of  natural  rights. 

(2)  The  second  objection  against  the  theory  of  natural 

•  "  Einlcitung  in  cine  Entwicklungsgcschichte  des  Kcchls,"  page  49. 


ON  RIGHTS  671 

rights,  and  the  objection  which  weighs  perhaps  more 
than  any  other  with  the  modern  ethician,  is  that  it 
seems  not  to  fit  in  with  the  laws  of  evolution.  De- 
velopment, it  is  argued,  involves  change — constant  and 
wide-extending.  Development  recognises,  as  Savigny 
writes,  no  point  of  rest.  Everything  is  movement  from 
one  stage  to  another.  Natural  right,  on  the  other 
hand,  write  our  opponents,  connotes  unchanging  law, 
absolute  rest.  Between  these  two  conceptions  there 
can  be  no  harmony.  "  We  have,"  writes  Neukamp,* 
"  to  thank  the  evolution  theory  in  its  application  to 
the  Sphere  of  right  for  the  fact  that  the  doctrine  of 
right  has  finally  set  itself  free  from  the  conception  of  a 
natural  ground  of  rights."  And  again,  "  the  concep- 
tion of  evolution  and  of  natural  right  are  absolutely 
irreconcilable." 

Reply. — First,  Evolutionists  make  the  false  assump- 
tion that  everything  in  man  is  subject  to  development. 
This  assumption  we  cannot  allow.  A  limb  may,  no 
doubt,  alter  its  shape  and  may  even  atrophy  from  dis- 
use ;  but  without  head,  stomach,  lungs,  and  heart  it 
would  be  impossible  to  support  human  life.  Part, 
therefore,  at  least,  of  our  human  constitution  is  un- 
changeable. So  also  many  of  our  appetites  are  per- 
manent and  unchangeable,  and  on  these  are  founded 
0".r  natural  rights. 

Secondly,  unless  there  were  in  things  an  element  of 
stability  it  is  impossible  that  the}^  could  develop.  It  is 
because  the  plant  has  permanent  needs  that  it  is  able 
to  alter  its  shape  and  colour  according  as  environment 
acts  upon  these  needs.  So  also,  unless  some  laws  were 
permanent  and  natural,  it  is  impossible  that  morality 
should  develop.f 

*  "  Einleitung,"  page  41. 

f  A  permanent  element  is  necessary  for  the  very  conception  of 
continuity,  which  is  a  necessary  part  of  the  idea  of  development. 
Change  without  continuity  is  not  development.  German  jurists  dis- 
tinguish between  change  and  development  in  right  by  the  words 
"  Rechtsvcrandcrung  "  and  "  Rechtsentwicklung."  The  second  im- 
plies some  stable  element  in  right. 


672  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Thirdh',  our  opponents  declare  that  if  rights  are 
natural  they  could  not  develop.  On  the  contrary,  we 
say,  because  there  is  in  right  a  natural  and  unchange- 
able foundation,  therefore  development  is  a  necessity. 
The  satisfaction  of  an  unchangeable  need  in  changeable 
circumstances  involves,  necessarily,  change  of  one's  way 
of  satisfying  that  need.  But  natural  rights  are  built 
on  natural  law,  which  is,  in  turn,  built  on  natural  un- 
changeable needs.  Natural  right,  therefore,  admits  of, 
and  implies,  development. 

(3)  A  third  objection  is  that  the  State  can  only  annul 
:a  right  which  it  creates.  But  the  State  can  annul 
many  rights  of  justice,  as  is  evident  from  the  exist- 
ence of  Statutes  of  Limitations.  Therefore,  rights  of 
justice  are  a  creation  of  the  State  and  not  of  nature. 
And  if  rights  of  justice  are  not  natural,  no  rights  are 
natural. 

Reply. — We  deny  the  major  proposition  of  this  argu- 
ment. The  State  has  a  natural  right  to  do  anything 
that  is  necessary  for  the  common  good,  and,  therefore, 
it  may  annul  any  rights,  even  rights  which  it  docs  not 
itself  create,  provided  that  insistence  on  these  rights 
would  be  harmful  to  the  community.  It  may  also 
determine  the  conditions  of  natural  rights,  e.g.,  it  has 
power  to  place  conditions  to  contracts,  and  to  annul 
a  seller's  right  to  payment,  when  these  conditions  are 
not  fulfilled.* 

(4)  Jurists  raise  the  difficulty  that  to  admit  that 
some  rights  are  natural   would   be   most   awkward   for 

*  This  power  the  State  very  rarely  uses.  It  "  bars  the  remedy  " 
mucli  ofteuer  than  it  "  extinguishes  the  title." 

Modern  jurists,  like  Savigny  and  Neukanip,  lay  great  stress  on  the 
analogy  between  "  Speech  "  and  "  right,"  and  argue  that  if  speech 
may  wholly  change,  right  also  may  change,  and  therefore  that  riglit 
cannot  be  natural.  We  find  it  hard  to  see  any  point  in  this  dillicully, 
anri  therefore  shall  not  discuss  it  at  length.  Language  bears  no 
analogy  to  right.  Languages  arc  not  distinguislicd  into  valid  and 
invalid  as  rights  arc.  Language  is  nothing  more  than  practice.  Also, 
if  men  agreed  to  alter  all  existing  languages  the  world  could  still  go 
on.  it  we  agreiil  to  disregard  the  rights  of  parents,  children,  husbands, 
etc.,  nature  would  at  once  rebel. 


ON  RIGHTS  673 

the  State,  since  the  State  expects  that  its  judges  will 
rule  according  to  the  law  of  the  land  only. 

Reply, — The  fact  that  judges  are  expected  to  rule 
according  to  the  law  of  the  land  only  is  proof,  not  that 
no  natural  law  or  right  exists,  but  only  that  the  con- 
sideration of  the  natural  law  and  of  natural  right  is  to 
a  very  large  extent  outside  the  province  of  judges. 
The  natural  law,  it  is  supposed,  is  fully  consulted  for 
by  the  legislator  when  the  laws  of  the  land  are  being 
introduced,  and  it  is  right  that  the  judge  should  trust 
these  laws  and  rule  according  to  them  only,  whenever 
they  are  found  to  cover  the  case  in  point.  We  insist, 
however,  that  a  judge  has  often  to  give  his  decision  on 
points  of  natural  law,  when  the  positive  law  fails  him,* 
and,  also,  that  it  would  be  unlawful  for  him  to  ad- 
minister any  law  that  was  clearly  antagonistic  to  nature. 
As  regards  the  awkward  effects  referred  to,  we  may 
make  the  admission  that  for  judges  the  existence  of  a 
natural  law  might  often  be  an  embarrassing  and  a 
distressing  thing,  but  we  contend  also  that  the  natural 
law  is  the  one  great  safeguard  of  the  community  at  large 
against  oppressive  and  evil  legislation,  and  also  against 
maladministration  of  even  good  laws. 

These  difficulties,  then,  do  not  disprove  our  theory 
that  some  rights  are  natural. 

ON   THE   RELATION   OF   RIGHT   TO   MORALITY 

From  what  precedes  it  will  be  plain  that  we  must 
regard  right  as  founded  on  law,  and  since  the  laws  by 
which  human  acts  are  directed  appertain  to  the  moral 
order,  it  follows  that  we  must  regard  rights  as  also 
appertaining  to  the  moral  order — as  a  branch  of  morality 
— as  dependent  on  morality. 

Against  this  view  some  ethicians,  such  as  Kant  and 

*  Some  jurists  claim  that  the  positive  law,  since  it  creates  all  right, 
must  necessarily  cover  all  disputed  questions  in  right ;  in  other  words' 
that  there  are  no  lacuncs  in  the  positive  law.     This  claim,  we  think  is 
not  borne  out  by  the  experience  of  lawj^ers. 
Vol.  1—43 


674  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

Thomasius,  maintain  that  right  does  not  depend  on 
morahty,  that  they  have  different  objects  and  a  different 
origin,  the  one  (right)  originating  in  the  law  of  the 
State,  the  other  (morals)  in  the  moral  law  ;  the  one 
appertaining  to  external  action,  the  other  to  internal 
motive  ;  that,  consequently,  there  is  a  well-marked  and 
an  absolute  line  of  cleavage  between  right  and  morals.* 

The  following  two  arguments  will,  we  believe,  make 
it  evident  that  right  cannot  be  divorced  from  morals — 
that  apart  from  morals  right  would  have  absolutely  no 
meaning. 

First,  right,  as  already  stated,  depends  on  natural 
law.  But,  regarded  as  a  rule  of  human  action,  the 
natural  law  is  the  moral  law.  Therefore,  right  depends 
on  moral  law. 

Secondly,  in  no  sense  can  I  be  said  to  have  a  right 
to  keep  money  except  it  be  understood  that  other  men 
are  under  an  obligation  not  to  take  it  from  me.  But 
obligation  belongs  to  morality.  Consequently,  right, 
if  it  be  independent  of  moral  law,  can  have  no  meaning. 

The  following  argument  is  sometimes  brought  to  show 
that  right  is  independent  of  morality.  Right  and 
morals  belong  to  two  totally  distinct  spheres  of  human 
life.f  The  one  (right)  has  to  do  with  external  action — 
the  other  (morality)  has  to  do  with  inner  motive. 
Legality  (or  right)  and  morality  thus  stand  apart  from, 
and  are  independent  of,  one  another. 

Reply. — We  cannot  admit  this  distinction  of  inner 
or  subjective  morality,  and  outer  or  objective  right.     Rights 

*  A  similar,  though  not  quite  identical,  view  of  right  is  taken  by 
Stahl  in  his  "  Philosophy  of  Right."  This  philosopher  insists  that 
alxjve  right  there  is  a  moral  order,  or  what  he  calls  a  Gottes  Weltordnung, 
to  which  all  right  should  conform.  Yet  right,  he  declares,  is  not 
intrinsically  dependent  on  this  order,  and  even  when  it  does  not  con- 
form to  the  moral  order  it  may  still  be  a  valid  right.  A  similar  view 
to  this  is  criticised  by  us  in  our  chapter  on  Law,  page  ()5i,  note. 

t  Thomasius  completely  separated  the  objects  of  right  and  morality. 
Morals,  he  said,  arc  meant  to  secure  inner,  rights  to  sccui-e  outer ,  jjoace. 
Kant,  however,  (at  least  when  treating  of  right  in  the  abstract),  allowed 
to  morals  the  control  both  of  the  inner  and  the  outer  man  (see  "  Mcta- 
physic  of  Morals,"  Abbot,  page  269)  ;  but  to  Juridical  Science — i.e., 
to  the  Sci'tucc  of  Right — he  allowed  tlic  control  of  outer  action  only. 


ON  RIGHTS  675 

have  not  to  do  merely  with  the  outer  act,  for,  besides 
rights  that  concern  the  outer  act,  there  are  also  rights 
that  concern  the  inner  wih,  A  father  has  a  right  to  the 
love  of  his  children,  just  as  children  are  obliged  to  love 
their  father.  And  the  love  that  is  due  to  a  father  is 
something  more  than  mere  external  reverence.  It  is 
an  inner  act  of  the  wih.  Inner  love,  therefore,  can  be 
the  object  of  right.  Also,  men  have  a  right  not  merely 
to  freedom  from  attack  on  the  part  of  others,  but  also 
to  freedom  from  evil  judgment.  I  can  be  quite  as 
unjust  to  a  man  by  judging  him  wrongly,  or  getting 
others  to  judge  him  wrongly,  as  I  can  by  stealing  money 
out  of  his  pocket.  Hence,  right  does  not  concern  outer 
acts  merely. 

Again,  outer  act  cannot  be  completely  separated  from 
inner  motive,  for  they  both  make  up  one  complete 
human  action,  and  hence,  even  if  right  had  to  do  with 
the  external  act  only,  it  would  not  on  that  account 
be  disassociated  from  morals.  Just  as  an  outer  act 
can  be  free,  but  not  independently  of  inner  act  (since 
it  is  free  because  it  makes  one  object  with  inner  act), 
so  even  though  right  referred  to  outer  act,  it  would 
still  depend  on  inner  moral  law^ 

We  cannot,  therefore,  admit  any  such  complete 
cleavage  as  that  insisted  on  by  the  positivists  between 
inner  morality  and  outer  right. 

Corollaries. — (i)  A  right  which  opposes  the  moral 
law  is  no  right.  Some  jurists  admit  that  any  right 
has  formal  validity  which,  though  opposed  in  its  con- 
tent to  moral  law,  has  still  been  conferred  by  a  com- 
petent authority.  We  claim  that  if  rights  are  essen- 
tially dependent  on  morality,  then  any  right  which 
opposes  morality  is  null  and  void,  both  formally  and  in 
every  other  way. 

(2)  Only  a  moral  Being  can  be  the  subject  of  or 
possess  rights.  Animals,  therefore,  have  no  rights. 
A  man  may,  indeed,  have  duties  about  animals,  but  he 


676  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

cannot  have  duties  towards  them,  for  they  have  no 
rights.  But  of  this  we  shall  have  to  speak  more  fully 
in  our  second  volume. 


ERRONEOUS  THEORIES  OF  THE  ORIGIN  AND  NATURE  OF 
RIGHT 

We  must  now  take  up  for  consideration  some  of  the 
more  important  of  recent  erroneous  theories  on  the 
origin  of  right. 

(i)  Theory  that  all  rights  originate  with  the  State* 

The  most  important,  because  the  most  widespread,  of 
all  modern  errors  on  the  origin  of  right  is  the  theory 
that  all  rights  originate  with  the  State.  It  would  be 
difficult  to  say  how  far  back  this  theory  dates  in  the 
history  of  Philosophy,  It  certainly  was  taught  by 
many  very  ancient  philosophers,  since  it  forms  part  of 
the  very  ancient  theory  that  morality  originates  with 
the  State.  But  many  modern  philosophers  have  dis- 
cussed this  question  of  the  origin  of  right  on  its  own 
account — that  is,  apart  altogether  from  any  question 
of  the  origin  of  the  moral  law,  and  have  decided  that, 
though  the  7noral  law  is  independent  of  State  law,  a 
right  originates  with  the  State,  and  is,  therefore,  de- 
pendent on  the  will  of  the  ruler. 

Criticism. — We  admit  that  the  State  can  confer  some 
rights,  but  our  present  contention  is  that  not  all  rights 
originate  with  the  State.f 

(a)  It  cannot  be  that  all  rights  originate  with  the 
State,  since  we  have  conclusively  shown  that  there  are 

•  Taught  by  Hobbes,  Spinoza,  Kant,  and  others.  A  very  good 
account  of  modem  theories  of  right  is  to  be  found  in  Walter's  "  Natur- 
reclit  und  Politik." 

t  The  theory  that  all  rights  originate  with  the  State  by  no  means 
excludes  other  theories  of  right,  such  as  the  theory  that  right  originates 
in  contract  or  in  custom.  For  contract  may  be  State  contract  and  lustom 
may  be  State  custom.  Most  modern  lithicians  of  tlie  Historical  School 
hold  the  two  theories  siniuUanoously— that  all  rigiits  derive  from  the 
State  and  that  all  rights  derive  from  custom. 


ON  RIGHTS  677 

such  things  as  natural  rights.  There  must  be  natural 
rights  because  there  are  natural  laws,  right  being  simply 
a  result  of  law.  Thus,  children  have  a  natural  right  to 
support  from  their  parents,  and  every  man  has  a  natural 
right  to  his  life,  and  to  the  means  of  supporting  it  ; 
husbands  have  a  natural  right  to  fidelity  on  the  part 
of  their  wives,  etc.  None  of  these  originate  with  the 
State. 

(b)  The  State  cannot  be  the  source  of  all  right  for  it 
cannot  be  the  source  of  its  own  right  to  existence.  And, 
if  it  cannot  originate  its  own  right  to  existence,  then, 
unless  its  right  to  existence  be  from  nature,  from  what 
can  it  be  derived  ? 

(c)  Again,  if  the  State  has  no  natural  right  to  its  own 
existence,  it  could  not  create  or  confer  rights  on  others, 
and  if  it  attempted  to  do  so,  nobody  would  be  bound 
to  heed  its  action. 

{d)  The  individual  has  rights  as  against  the  State. 
For  instance,  the  individual  has  a  right  to  his  life,  which 
the  State  cannot  take  away  except  the  individual  be 
guilty  of  some  crime.  But,  if  there  be  rights  against 
the  State,  the  State  cannot  be  the  source  of  all  rights. 
■  (e)  If  the  State  be  the  source  of  all  rights,  then  how 
could  one  State  have  rights  as  against  another  State  ? 
The  State  can  rule  its  own  subject,  but  it  cannot  rule 
other  States,  and  consequently  it  could  not  originate 
rights  against  other  States.  Yet  each  State  has  rights 
against  other  States,  which  rights  must,  therefore,  be 
from  nature.* 

•  (/)  If  the  State  originated  all  rights,  it  could  confer 
upon  itself  a  right  to  do  anything  that  it  wished  to  do, 
and,  in  that  case,  the  State  could  never  do  wrong.  But 
the  State  can  do,  and  has  done,  wrong  ;   therefore,  rights 

*  Hegel  contends  that  all  rights  originate  with  the  absolute  State, 
not  this  or  that  State  ;  and  many  Hegelians  would,  therefore,  answer 
the  above  difficulty  by  saying  that  particular  States  derive  their  rights 
against  other  particular  States  from  the  Absolute  or  Universal  State. 
We  contend,  however,  that  there  is  no  such  thing  in  existence  as  a 
Universal  State,  and,  if  it  does  exist,  it  is  not  known. 


678  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

cannot  all  originate  with  the  State.  Hegel,  indeed,  con- 
tends that  a  true  State  could  not  do  wrong — that  if 
WTong  is  done  it  is  done  by  a  false  State — that  a  State 
which  does  wrong  is  no  more  a  true  State  than  the  hand 
that  is  cut  off  from  the  body  is  a  true  human  hand. 
We  rejoin — how  shall  we  know,  unless  we  presuppose 
rights  of  7iature  with  which  to  compare  the  cnacimetiis  of 
the  State,  whether  the  actions  of  a  State  be  wrong  or 
right,  and,  therefore,  which  is  the  false  and  which  the 
true  State  ?  Unless  there  be  a  law  of  nature  by  which 
to  determine  the  false  and  the  true,  all  States  should 
be  equally  true,  and  all  acts  of  the  State  equally  just. 
But  laws  of  nature  involve  rights  of  nature.  Therefore, 
there  are  rights  that  are  not  from  the  State. 

(g)  The  argument  from  consequences  we  need  not 
labour.  The  theory  of  the  "  State — the  origin  of  all 
Right  "  has  many  evil  consequences,  some  for  the  State 
itself,  some  for  the  individual.  One  consequence  that 
concerns  the  State  itself  is  that,  if  this  theory  be  true, 
then,  the  State  has  no  authority  from  nature  to  rule  or 
to  confer  rights  ;  and  if  the  State  has  no  natural  autho- 
rity its  ruling  need  not  be  respected.  A  consequence 
for  the  subject  is  that,  if  the  State  be  the  source  of  all 
right,  the  individual  can  have  no  right  against  the 
State.  This  latter  consequence,  we  claim,  mankind 
could  never  recognise  or  accept.  ^  Hence,  it  is  not  true 
that  all  right  originates  with  the  State. 

(2)  Theory  that  all  right  is  based  upon  contract. 

Practically  all  that  we  have  wTittcn  on  the  theory  of 
the  "  State — the  source  of  Right  "  applies  equally  to 
the  theory  defended  by  Hobbes,  Fichte,  and  many 
others,  that  all  right  originates  in  vohmtary  contract. 
We  add,  however,  one  or  two  arguments  which  are 
proper  to  the  contract  theory,  and  which  the  reader 
can  himself  further  expand  and  illustrate.  Admitting 
that  some  rights  are  base.d  on  contract,  we  claim  still 


ON  RIGHTS  679 

that  there  are  some  rights  that  are  not  based  on  con- 
tract, and  that,  in  fact,  no  right  can  be  based  on  con- 
tract alo7ie.  For,  first,  if  all  rights  were  based  on  con- 
tract there  could  be  no  such  thing  as  inalienable  rights. 
Inalienable  rights  are  rights  which  we  cannot  of  our 
own  accord  renounce — e.g.,  the  right  of  a  father  to 
respect  from  his  children,  of  a  child  to  support,  of  the 
State  to  maintenance.  Were  these  rights  the  result  of  • 
voluntary  contract  the  parties  who  made  the  contract 
could  break  it  by  mutual  agreement,  and  so  remove 
the  right.  But,  since  certain  rights  are  inalienable, 
this  is  impossible.  A  father,  for  instance,  cannot  re- 
nounce his  right  to  respect,  nor  a  child  his  right  to  sup- 
port and  education.  Secondly,  'since  there  is  nothing  » 
that  a  man  may  not  contract  to  do,  so  there  is  nothing 
to  which,  if  this  theory  be  logically  worked  out,  a  man 
may  not  acquire  a  right.  If  all  right  originates  in 
contract,  then  by  a  simple  process  of  common  agree- 
ment men  might  acquire  a  right  to  the  most  iniquitous 
conduct.  But  since  all  admit  that  some  acts  could 
never  become  our  right,  it  follows  that  rights  cannot 
be  all  based  on  contract.  Thirdly,  the  right  of  the 
contracting  parties  to  keep  each  other  to  the  contract 
could  not  be  itself  the  result  of  contract,  since  it  is  prior 
to,  and  necessary  to,  the  very  conception  of  a  contract. 
Lastly;  we  asserted  that  no  right  can  depend  on  volun- 
tary contract  alone.  This  follows  from  what  is  said 
above — that  all  contract  of  its  nature  presupposes 
certain  natural  rights  of  contract. 

(3)   Theory  of  the  historical  school  that  custom  is  the 
ultimate  ground  of  right. 

Note  on  the  Historical  School. — This  school  may  be 
described  as  a  reaction  against  the  ultra  a  priori  theory  of 
Kant  to  be  described  in  the  next  section.  For,  Kant  had,  in 
deducing  all  right  from  the  mere  conception  of  a  conflict  of 
all  men's  liberties,  not  taken  sufficient  account  of  the  State 
and  of  custom,  which  all  must  recognise  as  having  a  great 
deal  to  do  with  the  creation  of  existing  rights.    As  a  natural 


68o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

reaction  against  this  over-subjectivism  in  regard  to  right 
came  the  over-objective  theory  of  ScheUing,  Hegel,  and  the 
Historical  school,  that  right  originates  in  ancient  customs — 
those  customs,  namely,  which  have  ruled  the  world  from  the 
baginning,  and  developed  with  the  world. 

Amongst  the  older  defenders  and  founders  of  this  school 
are,  as  we  said,  Schelling  and  Hegel  and,  also,  Savigny  and 
Puchta.  Amongst  recent  writers,  its  best  known  adherents 
are  Bergbohm  and  Neukamp.  Needless  to  say,  the  Historical 
School,  just  as  it  opposes  the  theory  of  the  Positivists  that 
anything  is  our  right  which  we  may  wish  to  make  our  right, 
opposes  also  the  theory  of  Natural  Right- — that  is,  the  theory 
that  rights  are  grounded  not  in  custom  but  in  human  nature. 
Neukamp,*  however,  calls  attention  to  the  fact,  that  even 
within  the  historical  school  itself  opposition  to  the  theory  of 
rights  of  nature  was  not  so  strongly  marked  formerly  as  it  is 
now.  Thus  he  declares  that  some,  like  Savigny,  in  spite  of 
their  opposition  to  natural  right,  were  not  able  to  shake 
themselves  wholly  free  from  that  theory,  since,  in  the  first 
place,  they  admitted  a  certain  unchangeable  character  in 
right,  and,  in  the  second  place,  they  regarded  not  custom 
itself  but  the  will  of  the  people  (the  Volksgeist),  of  which 
national  custom  is  only  the  outward  expression,  as  the 
ultimate  source  of  right.  This  want  of  thoroughness,  Neu- 
kamp tells  us,  is  found  to  characterise  all  the  followers  of 
Savigny  until  the  most  recent  times.  Neukamp  is  himself 
amongst  the  most  uncompromising  defenders  of  the  pure 
historical  theory  of  right,  for  he  will  admit  nothing  into  his 
theory  that  might  even  remotely  be  connected  with  the 
conception  of  a  natural  or  an  unchangeable  system  of  rights, 
or  of  rights  which  depend  on  any  a  priori  ground.  "  We 
cannot,"  he  writes,  "  come  by  the  principles  of  rights  by  pure 
speculation  or  logical  reasoning.  .  .  .  We  can  only  arrive  at 
an  answer  to  questions  on  rights  by  empirical  examination 
of  the  positive  rights  of  each  people  and  each  age." 

The  more  metaphysical  form  of  this  theory— that,  namely, 
which  is  grounded  in  the  conception  of  a  race-consciousness, 
or  Volksgeist — is  thus  described  by  Prof.  Cathrcin  in  his 
"  Moralphilosophie  " — "  Right  is  an  unconscious  product  of 
the  spirit  of  the  People.  It  dwells  in  the  common  thought  of 
tiic  people.  It  resides  there,  not  as  an  abstract  rule,  but  as 
a  living  intuition,  wliich  in  practical  life  is  transformed  into 
the  institutions  known  as  riglits.  Just  as  speech,  public 
manners,  and  art  arise  unconsciously  with  the  people,  and 

♦  "  Einlcitun{^'  in  cine  Entwicklun^s^cschichtc  dcg  Rechts,"  pige  28, 


ON  RIGHTS  68i 

then  gradually  develop,  so  is  it  also  with  right.  Of  this 
gradual  upward  process  through  which  rights  are  formed, 
the  highest  aim  and  purpose  is  the  formation  of  the  State. 
The  State  is  not  prior  to  right— \t  is  only  a  step  in  the  develop- 
ment of  right.  Originally  and  essentially  all  right  is  grounded 
on  custom— the  customs  of  the  race.  The  function  of  the 
State  is  not  so  much  the  creation  of  right  as  the  formation  of 
it  in  accordance  with  the  degree  of  development  reached. 
The  conscious  activity  of  the  State  (legal  right)  is,  in  this 
matter,  subordinated  to  the  unconscious  activity  of. the  Will 
of  the  people  "  (which  reveals  itself  in  national  customs). 

Criticism. — ^The  central  point  in  this  theory,  and  the 
point  which  we  now  proceed  to  criticise,  is  that  all 
rights  originate  in  the  customs  of  the  people. 

[a]  It  must  be  granted  that  some  rights  originate  in 
custom,  for  some  laws  originate  in  custom  (as  we 
showed  in  the  last  chapter),  and  right  is  the  result  of 
law.  But  we  also  pointed  out  that  when  custom 
originates  a  law,  it  does  so,  not  as  custom,  not  as  mere 
practice,  but  only  in  so  far  as  custom  is  an  expression 
of  the  will  of  the  lawgiver.  Hence,  laws  of  custom 
originate  like  other  laws  in  the  will  of  the  lawgiver. 
If  the  will  of  the  lawgiver  be  not  presupposed,  custom 
would  have  no  power  to  originate  a  law.  And,  as  all 
right  originates  in  law,  so  rights  which  come  from 
custom  are  always  grounded  on  something  deeper  than 
mere  custom — namely,  on  the  will  of  the  lawgiver,  of 
which  custom  is  merely  the  outward  expression.  We 
cannot,  therefore,  sustain  the  theory  that  all  rights 
originate  in  custom. 

This  argument,  as  will  be  seen  from  what  precedes, 
some  defenders  of  the  historical  school  would  meet  by 
asserting  that  the  customs  of  the  people  in  which  rights 
are  grounded  are  not  to  be  regarded  as  a  set  of  mere 
practices,  but  rather  as  the  expression  in  act  of  the  will 
of  the  people;  and,  consequentl}',  when  it  is  asserted 
that  rights  are  grounded  on  custom,  what  is  meant  is 
that  they  are  grounded  on  the  will  of  the  people,  of 
which  custom  is  the  expression. 


682  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

To  this  we  rejoin. — Either  the  will  of  the  people,  of 
which  the  historical  school  makes  mention,  is  to  be 
regarded  as  a  universal  will  distinct  from  individuals, 
or  it  is  simply  the  sum  of  the  individual  wills.  Now, 
the  theory  of  a  distinct  racial  will  is  a  mere  hypothesis, 
which,  in  the  first  place,  could  never  be  verified  (and, 
therefore,  we  could  only  regard  rights  that  are  grounded 
on  it  as  imaginary  and  unreal),  and,  in  the  second  place, 
is  impossible,  as  can  be  proved  in  Metaphysics  (and, 
therefore,  rights  grounded  on  it  are  an  impossibility). 
On  the  other  hand,  if  the  racial  will  of  which  our  op- 
ponents speak  is  merely  the  sum  of  individual  wills  in 
prehistoric  times,  then,  since  our  present-day  wills  are 
quite  as  authoritative  as  those  of  our  predecessors,  it 
would  follow  from  this  theory  that  mankind  could 
to-day  cancel  every  existing  right  just  as  mankind 
created  them.  But  this  we  cannot  allow.  There  are 
some  rights  that  cannot  be  abrogated.  However, 
whether  the  racial  will  is  to  be  regarded  as  distinct  or 
as  the  sum  merely  of  individual  wills,  it  is  quite  wrong 
to  speak  of  a  theory  that  grounds  right  on  an  expression 
of  will  as  an  historical  theory  of  rights.  An  historical 
theory  of  rights  is  a  theory  which  grounds  rights 
ultimately  on  outward  custom  or  practice,  and  not  on  the 
autJwrity  of  a  legislator.  The  theory  which  grounds 
rights  on  the  will  of  the  legislator,  even  though  the 
people  were  themselves  the  legislators,  is  a  distinct 
theory  from  the  present,  and  it  has  already  been  criti- 
cised by  us  in  the  present  chapter.* 

(b)  There  have  been  bad  customs  and  good  customs, 
just  customs  and  unjust  customs.  Hence,  custom  re- 
garded in  itself  is  neither  reasonable  nor  unreasonable, 
just  nor  unjust.  But,  right  being  the  principle  of 
Justice,  that  in  which  all  rights  originate  must  be 
essentially  just.  Hence,  rights  cannot  originate  ulti- 
mately in  custom. 

(c)  Right  springs,  as  "we  saw,  from  law.     Now,  in  no 

•  Sec  Theory  that  all  rights  originate  with  the  State. 


ON  RIGHTS  683 

department  of  nature  is  law  grounded  on  mere  practice 
or  customary  action.  A  stone  does  not  fall  to  the  earth 
simply  because  it  fell  in  former  ages.  A  plant  does  not 
grow  to-day  because  plants  grew  yesterday.  So,  if  there 
is  any  analogy  between  the  various  parts  of  nature, 
it  would  follow  that  human  laws  cannot  be  based 
merely  on  the  fact  that  men  in  former  times  uniformly 
did  certain  actions.  Rather  both  former  actions  and 
present  law  are  based  upon  necessities  of  nature,  just 
as  the  falling  of  the  stone  in  former  times  and  its  falling 
to-day  are  based  upon  the  same  necessity  of  nature — 
namely,  the  force  of  gravitation.  Hence,  law  does  not 
originate  in  custom,  and  rights,  therefore,  which  are 
grounded  on  law  cannot  be  based  on  mere  past  customs. 
{(i)  Mankind  is  superior  to  his  own  outward  practices, 
as  the  cause  is  superior  to  the  effect.  Hence,  mankind 
cannot  be  bound  by,  or  subject  to,  its  own  outward 
practices.  But  if  all  rights  originated  with  human 
customs  or  practices,  the  customs  of  the  race  must  have 
had  power  to  make  laws  for  the  race,  and  hence  they 
must  be  superior  to  the  race — which  is  absurd. 

(4)  The  "  Mechanical  "  theory  of  Right. 

According  to  Kant  the  individual  person  is  absolutely 
free.  But  freedom  is  two-fold — freedom  from  inner  com- 
pulsion and  freedom  from  outer  compulsion,  or  from  the 
compulsion  of  our  outer  acts  by  other  men.  Now,  in 
Kant's  theory,  right  is  regarded  as  nothing  more  than 
freedom  in  the  second  sense — that  is,  freedom  from 
outer  compulsion.  And  since,  according  to  Kant,  all 
men  have  equal  rights,  in  the  sense  of  equal  freedom 
from  outer  compulsion,  he  defines  right  as  "  the  con- 
ception of  the  conditions  under  which  the  wishes  of  one 
man  can  be  reconciled  with  the  wishes  of  every  other 
man  according  to  a  general  law  of  freedom."  Every 
man,  according  to  Kant,  is  a  person — that  is,  he  is  free. 
Now,  a. person,  like  every  other  living  thing,  has  need 


684  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  exercise  his  faculties  in  the  external  world.  Hence, 
each  man  has  a  right  to  external  freedom — that  is,  a 
right  to  use  the  external  world  without  interference 
from  others.  But  since  the  world  of  material  goods  is 
limited,  there  is  only  one  way  of  reconciling  the  powers 
of  different  men  with  one  another — that  is,  by  each  man 
using  just  so  much  of  the  world  as  is  consonant  with  the 
equal  freedom  of  every  other  man — in  other  words,  by  all 
having  originally  equal  shares  in  the  goods  of  the  world. 
This  system  of  the  equal  division  of  the  field  of  external 
liberty  is,  according  to  Kant,  the  system  of  rights. 

Criticism. — In  Kant's  theory  we  find  several  un- 
justifiable assumptions.*  For  instance,  {a)  that  rights 
appertain  to  external  goods  only  ;  (6)  that  all  rights 
can  be  deduced  from  the  conception  of  a  conflict  be- 
tween the  liberties  of  each  man  and  those  of  the  rest 
of  humanity  ;  (c)  that  the  goods  of  the  world  are  a 
definite  quantity,  that  they  are  not  7nade  by  individuals, 
but  are  supplied  ready-made  by  nature,  f  so  that  all 
men  have  an  equal  claim  to  them  ;  {d)  that  men  have  a 
right  to  any  line  of  action  which  does  not  injure  others 
or  limit  their  liberty. 

These  assumptions  we  can  consider  only  very  briefly. 

[a]  Not  all  rights  are  rights  to  material  things.  A 
man  has  a  right  to  his  good  name,  and  a  father  has  a 
right  to  the  respect  of  his  children.  But  neither  of 
these  is  a  material  good. 

(6)  If,  in  determining  rights,  it  is  asserted  that  we 
must  begin  with  the  conception  of  the  reconciliation  of 
all  men's  liberties,  then  it  is  assumed  that  every  right 
is  deducible  from  this  conception  of  the  freedom  of  all 
men.  Now,  this  assumption  we  cannot  allow.  For, 
first,  there  are  rights  which  are  deduced  from  the  con- 
ception either  of  the  work  we  do,  or  of  some  natural 
relation  depending  on  some  personal  act  of  ours — for 

*  If  thcsi!  things  are  not  assumed  Kant's  theory  is  meaningless. 
\  It  is  obvious  that  Kant  does  not  give  expression  to  this  assump 
lion.     But  apart  from  it  we  cannot  understand  his  theory. 


ON  RIGHTS  685 

instance,  the  right  of  a  man  to  the  table  he  makes,  the 
right  of  a  parent  to  the  love  of  his  child.  These  rights 
could  not  be  deduced  from  the  conception  of  freedom, 
much  less  from  the  conception  of  the  equal  freedom  of 
all.  Secondly,  there  are  such  things  as  inalienable 
rights — for.  instance,  the  right  of  a  child  to  support — 
which  it  would  be  difficult  to  deduce  from  the  concep- 
tion of  a  conflict  of  liberties.  If  right  and  freedom  be 
one,  as  Kant  supposes,  then  surely  there  is  no  right 
that  we  may  not  freely  surrender.  Liberty  in  right 
means  the  freely  retaining  or  freely  surrendering  of  that 
to  which  we  have  the  right.  But  there  are  rights  that 
we  cannot  surrender,  and,  therefore,  there  must  be 
something  in  right  other  than  the  conception  of  mere 
liberty.  Thirdly,  men  have  rights  to  coerce  other  men 
in  certain  cases — for  instance,  the  right  to  restrain  a 
man  forcibly  from  committing  suicide.  Such  a  right 
as  that  could  not  be  deduced  from  the  conception  of 
other  men's  liberties.  Fourthly,  the  only  kind  of  right 
which  Kant  considers  is  the  right  to  non-interference 
from  others,  which  is  merely  negative  right.  But  men 
have  positive  rights  as  well  as  negative — for  instance, 
the  right  of  the  State  to  support,  and  of  starving  men  to 
obtain  food.  Therefore,  there  are  Rights  that  cannot 
be  deduced  from  the  conceptions  of  liberty. 

(c)  It  seems  to  us  that,  in  defining  right  as  the  sum  of 
the  conditions  under  which  all  men  can  exercise  their 
liberty,  Kant  supposes  that  the  goods  of  the  world  are 
fixed  in  amount,  that  they  are  not  to  a  large  extent  made 
by  certain  individuals,  that  Nature  supplies  us  with 
everything.  On  no  other  understanding  could  he  defend 
the  view  that  all  men  have  equal  rights  to  external 
liberty  in  regard  to  the  goods  of  the  world.  But  the 
world  of  goods  is  not  fixed  in  amount — it  is  built  up  to 
a  large  extent  by  individuals.  Were  it  not  for  human 
endeavour  much  of  what  is  most  valuable  on  the  earth 
would  not  exist.  We  must,  then,  in  considering  our 
rights  to  the  goods  of  the  world,  remember  that  man 


686  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

to  a  large  extent  produces  these  goods.  But  surely  it 
cannot  be  that  in  determ.ining  a  man's  rights  to  these 
things  which  he  himself  produces,  we  must  start  by 
allowing  for  the  liberties  of  other  people  with  regard  to 
them.  On  the  contrary,  it  is  both  natural  and  just  that 
ill  estimating  a  man's  right  in  regard  to  things  produced 
by  him,  we  should  base  our  calculation  on  the  fact  that  he 
produced  them,  and  then,  having  made  full  allowance 
for  that  fact,  we  might  proceed  to  take  account  of  the 
claims  of  other  people,  and  of  all  opposing  liberties. 
The  starting  point,  therefore,  in  the  determination  of 
any  individual's  rights  is  not  necessarily  that  of  the 
"  general  law  of  freedom,"  as  Kant's  theory  supposes. 

[d)  We  have  seen  already  that  besides  inviolability 
there  is  always  in  right  the  element  of  lawfulness,  or 
Frlaublheit — that  is,  a  man  has  a  right  to  do  only  that 
which  is  lawful  for  him  to  do.  I  can  have  no  right  to 
that  which  is  unlawful  or  immoral.  Even,  therefore,' 
before  we  start  to  determine  what  liberty  remains  to 
each  man  after  the  conflict  of  all  men's  liberties  is 
allowed  for,  we  must  recognise  that  there  are  certain 
actions,  certain  liberties,  which  are  absolutely  forbidden 
to  us  from  the  beginning  as  wrong  in  themselves,  and 
independently  of  the  liberties  or  wishes  of  others.  To 
these  we  are  antecedently  debarred  from  ever  acquiring 
a  right.  Thus,  a  man  could  not  possibly  acquire  a  right 
of  sweating  falsely,  of  hating  God,  of  hating  his  fellow- 
men,  a  right  to  private  sins  of  immorality,  or  to  take 
away  his  own  life.  .  He  could  not  acquire  a  right  to 
these  things  even  if  all  men  agreed  to  give  him  the 
right.  Hence,  right  cannot  be  in  all  cases  the  resultant 
of  conflicting  liberties,  for  there  are  some  objects  to 
which  we  can  never  acquire  a  right.  The  principle, 
then,  of  the  conflict  of  human  liberties  can  never  be 
the  principle  on  which  we  base  right  in  general,  and, 
therefore,  it  is  not  the  starting  point  in  our  calculus  of 
rights.  It  is  just  one  amongst  the  mcuiy  factors  of  the 
calculus. 


APPENDIX  TO  VOL.   I 

Kant's  Criterion  of  Goodness. — The  Categorical 
Imperative 

An  act,  according  to  Kant,  if  it  is  to  be  morally  good,  must 
be  done  for  the  sake  of  law.  Now,  not  every  act  can  be 
done  for  the  sake  of  law,  and  therefore  it  is  of  the  utmost 
importance  that  we  should  know  what  acts  can  be  brought 
under  this  motive  and  what  can  not.  An  act,  according  to 
Kant,  can  be  brought  under  this  motive  when  it  is  possible 
for  us,  without  contradicting  ourselves,  to  will  that  such  an 
act  should  become  a  law  for  all  men.  It  cannot  be  brought 
under  this  motive  and  so  cannot  be  morally  good  when  to 
will  it  'to  become  a  law  for  all  is  self-contradictory  and  im- 
possy^^^The  law — act  so  that  the  maxim  of  thy  will  may 
be  <^^^^  of  becoming  a  universal  law  for  all  men — is 
knot^BlFthe  Categorical  Imperative.  Now,  the  impossi- 
bility of  willing  that  a  certain  line  of  action  should  become 
a  universal  law  may  arise  from  either  of  two  reasons — either 
because  we  cannot  even  conceive  its  being  a  universal  law, 
the  very  notion  of  such  an  act  becoming  a  law  being  incon- 
sistent with  itself ;  or  because,  whilst  the  conception  of  such 
a  law  is  possible,  still  the  willing  of  it  is  impossible,  inasmuch 
as  the  willing  of  such  a  law  conflicts  with  some  other  per- 
manent appetite  or  wish  within  us.  Examples  of  the  first 
class  of  acts  are  suicide  and  false  promises.  Of  a  law  of 
suicide  Kant  says — "  A  system  of  nature  of  which  it  should 
be  a  law  to  destroy  life  by  means  of  the  very  feeling  whose 
special  nature  it  is  to  impel  to  the  improvement  of  life  " 
(that  is,  the  will,  desiring  its  own  good,  which  object  is,  on 
Kant's  own  confession,  present  in  every  act  of  will)  "  would 
contradict  itself,  and  therefore  could  not  possibly  exist  as  a 
universal  law  of  nature."  Examples  of  the  second  class  of 
acts  are  idleness  and  want  of  kindness.  Of  the  impossibility 
of  willing  idleness  as  a  universal  law  he  says  :  "  As  a  rational 
being  he  (man)  necessarily  wills  that  his  faculties  be  developed 
since  they  serve  him  and  have  been  given  him  for  all  sorts  of 
possible  purposes."  These  kinds  of  acts,  therefore,  are  bad. 
Criticism. — The  reader  should  refer  to  our  chapter  on  the 
Criterion  of  Morals  in  order  to  see  how  far  Kant's  criterion 

687 


688  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 

could  possibly  be  brought  into  harmony  with  ours.  We 
shall  just  call  his  attention  here  to  one  or  two  points  that 
may*be  of  use  to  him  in  making  contrast  of  the  two  theories 
— (a)  It  is  quite  possible  to  wish  that  all  men  should  commit 
suicide  or  make  deceitful  promises.  The  wish  for  these 
things  is  not  self-contradictory.  We  acknowledge,  however, 
that  in  both  these  acts  there  is  a  contradiction  which  is  not 
without  its  ethical  significance,  for  both  acts  contradict  the 
natural  objects  of  the  faculty  employed,  as  we  pointed  out 
concerning  suicide  and  lying  in  our  chapter  on  the  Criterion. 
In  a  sense,  therefore,  unnatural  or  bad  acts  are  self-contra- 
dictory ;  and  from  the  examples  cited  we  may  judge  how 
close  Kant  was  to  the  Scholastic  system  in  some  parts  of  his 
theory,  (b)  There  are  many  morally  good  acts  that,  yet, 
could  not  possibly  become  a  law  for  all.  A  healthy  man 
has  duties  that  could  not  bind  a  sick  man.  Our  duties 
depend  often  on  circumstances  of  person,  time,  and  place. 
For  these  Kant  makes  no  allowance,  (c)  Some  courses  that 
are  morally  good  and  lawful  are  good  only  as  long  as  they 
do  not  become  a  universal  law.  It  is  lawful,  for  instance, 
for  a  man  to  remain  a  bachelor.     But  all  could  not  do  so. 

Thus,  the  Categorical  Imperative — act  so  that  the  maxim 
of  thy  will  may  be  capable  of  becoming  a  universal  law — is 
not  the  ultimate  criterion  of  good  and  evil  in  human  conduct. 

An  interesting  discussion  on  Kant's  criterion  is  given  in 
Prof.  Rashdall's  "  Theory  of  Good  and  Evil "  and  in  Prof. 
Simmel's  "  Kant — Sechzehn  Vorlesungen." 


INDEX 


Absolute,  3. 

Act,  acts,  not  states,  the  subject 

matter   of   Ethics,    3  ;     human 

acts,  28-45. 
Adjustment  to  environment.  See 

Environment. 
Aesthetic  Morals,  525. 
^•Altruism,  see  Benevolence. 
Anthropocentrism,  167. 
Appetite,  good  as  object  of,  89  ; 

existence  of  natural  app.,  104- 

113  ;    App.  and  law,  113,  643. 
♦  AssociATiONiST   theory  of   duty, 

240  ;   of  moral  judgments,  427. 
Autonomy   of    reason,    652  ;     of 

will,  657. 

Beauty  and  goodness  compared, 

520,  525- 
Being  and  goodness,  89-95. 
Benevolence,  impulse  of,   331- 

339. 

^  Categorical  character  of  duty, 
219;  cat.  imperative  of  Kant. 
See  appendix  to  Vol  I. 

Circumstances,  morality  of,  99. 

Character,  place  in  Ethics,  3. 

Conduct,  as  subject-matter  of 
Ethics,  3. 

Conscience,  nature  of,  472-475  ; 
erroneous  theories  on,  475-504  ; 
as  God's  voice,  497  ;  can  it  de- 
velop and  decay,  547  ;  con- 
science of  child,  see  synderests. 
See  also  Judgments  fmoral). 

Consequences,  morality  of,  36 ; 
of  morality,  573. 

Criteria  of  morality,  meaning, 
124  ;  division  of,  125  ;  need  of, 
126  ;  primary,  127-139  ;  second- 
ary, 140-157  ;  general  remarks 
on,  157. 

Culture,  not  our  final  end,  68. 


Custom,  and  moral  distinctions, 

US- 
Determinants  of  morality,  97. 
.  Determinism.     See  freedom. 
Drunkenness,  139. 
Duty,  freedom  and,  198  ;   mean- 
ing  of,    211  ;     proof   of,    214  ; 
absolute  character  of,  219  ;  duty 
dependent  on. God,   212,   229; 
erroneous  theories  of,  230-254  ; 
Kant's     deduction     of    liberty 
from,  254. 
•Duty    for     duty's    sake.     See 
Formalism. 

Elicited  and  commanded  acts, 

28. 
Elpistic  theory,  85. 

•^ND,  in  general,  46  ;  all  that  is 
desired  is  directed  to  final  end, 
49  ;  cannot  be  many  ultimate 
ends,  51  ;  ultimate  end  same 
for  all  men,  52  ;  objective  final 
end,  54 ;  can  objective  final 
end  be  determined,  54  ;  the 
things  that  do  not  constitute 
final  obj.  end,  56;  objective 
end  an  external  thing,  58-66  ; 
the  true  obj.  end,  69  ;  final  obj. 
end  a  reality,  71  and  85  ;  sub- 
jective final  end,  79-85. 

^Environment,  adjustment  to,  as 

end,  69  ;   as  criterion,  414. 
Ethics,  definition  and  scope  of, 
1-7  ;   relation  to  other  sciences, 
7;    method  of,   14-21;    possi- 
bility of  as  a  science,  21-27. 

^Evolution,  and  end  of  man,  63  ; 
evol.  theory  of  duty,  240  ;  Bio- 
logical, 372-424  ;  Psychological 
425-441  ;  Transcendental,  442- 

471- 
Extrinsic  morality,  120. 


Vol.  I — 44 


689 


690 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


Faculty,  moial.     See  Conscience. 
Fear,  44. 

Feelings,  moral,  as  criteria,  155  ; 
moral  faculty,  a  group  of,  480. 
•^  Formalism  (Kantian),  256-274. 

vX-FoRTITUDE,  618. 

Freedom,  relation  to  human  act, 
31  ;  nature  of,  175-181  ;  ground 
of,  181-184  ;  extent  of,  185  ; 
freedom  and  conservation  of 
energy,  187  ;  Kant  on  meaning 
of,  190  ;  Hegel  on  meaning  of, 
192  ;   and  morality,  196-210.     , 

Friendsi^ip.     See  Benevolence. 

Fulness  of  Being,  and  goodness. 
See  Being. 

•^  God,  the  end  of  man,  69-79  ;  God 
the  ground  of  duty,  229  ;  proof 
of  God's  existence  from  Ethics, 
73  and  501  ;  theory  of  con- 
science the  voice  of  God,  497. 

•  Goodness,    meaning   of,    89-97  5 

identical  with  Being,  89-95  5 
determinants  of,  97  ;  natural 
distinction  from  evil,  104 ; 
theory  that  goodness  implies 
struggle,  581. 

^Habits,  593, 

\Happiness,  distinguished  from 
pleasure,  53  ;  our  subjective 
final  end,  79  ;  perfect  happiness 
attainable,  85  ;  relation  to  vir- 
tue, see  Virtue. 
Health,  as  criterion,  417. 

♦  Hedonism,     58 ;      statement    of 

theory,  275  ;  disproved,  279- 
288  ;  arguments  of,  examined, 
289-302  ;  Psychological,  289  ; 
Ethical,  299  ;  criterion  of,  302  ; 
empirical  and  scientific,  306  ; 
paradox  of,  291  ;  usteron  pro- 
teron  of,  297  ;  and  Utilitarian- 
ism, 339  and  369. 

Historical  method,  17;  school 
of  Rights,  679. 

Holiness,  not  our  final  end,  66. 

Human  acts,  meaning  of,  3-4  ; 
division  of,  28 ;  principles  of 
and  their  opposites,  31. 

«/Ignorance,  40 ;  and  freedom, 
186;  ignorance  an  clement  in 
evil-doing,  224, 


Imitation,  as  formative  of  mind 

364. 
Immanent  Heteronomy,  658. 
Impulses  (moral)  theory  of,  530. 
oImputability,  574  ;  freedom  and, 

201. 
Independent  morality,  122. 
Indifferent  acts,  100-104. 
Individual  acts,  morality  of,  and 

Simmel  on,  170. 
Infinite  Good,  our  final  objective 

end,  69-97. 
Intention,  33  ;   various  kinds  of, 

34- 
^  Intuitionist  method,  15  ;  theory 

of  duty,  234  ;    theory  of  moral 

judgments,  how  far  true,  307  ; 

Perceptional  Intuitionism,  516  ; 

Common  Sense  Int.,  522. 

Judgments,  moral,  nature  of, 
472  ;  some  self-evident,  507  ; 
origin  of  in  child's  mind,  539  ; 
origin  of  according  to  positivists, 
427  ;  differences  in,  explained 
by  St.  Thomas,  513  ;  by  Fichte, 
493  ;  by  Hegel,  494  ;  by 
Martineau,  431  ;  by  Elsenhans, 

^    571. 

'Justice,  621. 
Jus  gentium,  648. 

Knowledge,  relation  to  human 
act,  33  and  37  ;  not  our  final 
end,  67 ;  Can  we  do  evil 
knowingly  ?  224. 

^Law,  and  fact  in  Ethics,  5; 
appetite  and,  113;  conception 
of,  633  ;  eternal,  639  ;  natural, 
643  ;  human,  650  ;  theory  of 
autonomy,  652. 

Lie,  134. 

Life,  as  end  of  man,  Spencer's 
theory,  411. 

Logic,  relation  to  Ethics,  9. 

Mean,  golden,  as  criterion,  159 ; 

virtue  a  mean,  606. 
Merit,  574. 
Method  of  Ethics,  14. 
^loDERNisTS,  73. 
Moral  beliefs.     See  Judgments. 
Moral  Sense,  486. 
Moral     Theology,     relation     to 
Ethics,  13. 


INDEX 


601 


Natural,  distinctions  of  good  and 
evil,  104-113;  objections  to 
theory  of  natural  morals,  160- 
174;  'natural  selection'  ap- 
plied to  moral  ideas,  434  ;  same 
applied  to  Law,  63"-,;  natural 
la-.v  and  its  ground,  643. 

Nature  does  not  act  in  vain,  72. 

Nirvana,  83,  151. 

Normative  Science,  Ethics  a,  5, 
10. 

Obligation.  See  Duty. 
Optimism  Ethical,  148.. 
Origin  of  moral  judgments.     See 

Judgments. 
Ought  and  is,  5,  10,  26. 


Romanticists,  171. 


«  Passion,  relation  to  voluntariness 
42. 

Pity,  analysed,  337. 
•^Pleasure,  and  happiness,  53 ; 
pleasure  not  our  final  end,  57. 
see  also  Hedonism  ;  Kant's  atti- 
tude towards  pleasure,  see 
Formalism ;  qualitative  dis- 
tinctions in,  311;  pleasure 
associations  as  ground  of  moral 
judgments,  427. 

Political  Philosophy  and  Ethics, 
10. 

PosiTivisT  theories  of  good  and 
evil,  114-120  ;  theory  of  duty, 
240;  origin  of  moral  judgments, 
427  ;  view  of  moral  beliefs  of 
savages,  551. 

Pragmatist  view  of  freedom,  255  • 
defence  of  Utilitarianism, '353.' 

Principles,  primary  and  second- 
ary, 23  ;   are  they  self-evident, 
^      507. 
\Probabilism,  504. 

Prudence,  598. 

Psychology  and  Ethics,  8. 

Punishment,  freedom  and  retri- 
butive punishment,  202  ;  kinds 
of,  584-592. 

Reason,  its  relation  to  conduct, 
2,  9  ;  the  moral  faculty,  472  ; 
right  reason  as  criterion,  174. 

Rectitude,  573. 
^Rights,  notion,  division,  and  pro- 
perties of,  660  ;  existence  of 
natural,  669 ;  Rights  and 
Morality,  673  ;  erroneous  views 
on,  676. 


Sanction.     See  punishment. 

Savages,  moral  beliefs  of,  21 
551-568. 

Selection,  natural.   See  natural. 

Self-determination,  178,  igi. 

Self-evident  truths.  See  Judg- 
ments. 

Self-realisation,  not  our  end, 
63  ;  Transcendental-evolution- 
ist view  of,  442  ;  scholastic  view 
of,  461. 

Society,  our  duty  towards,  319, 
356  ;  relation  of  society  to  indi- 
vidual, 356-364  ;  happiness  of 
Society  not  our  end,  see  fJtiii- 
tarianism. 

Solidarity,  theory  of,  356-365. 

Struggle  and  goodness,  581-584. 

Suicide,  134. 

Survival,  theory  of,  applied  to 
moral  judgments,   434  ;    '  Sur- 
vival of  fittest  '  and  our  duty 
to  others,  418. 
I?ynderesis,  537-572. 

Temperance,  616. 

Transcendentalists,  on  free- 
dom, 192  ;  Transc.  Evolution, 
442-471. 

^  UTiLitARiANiSM,  Criterion  of  com- 
pared with  Scholastic  criterion, 
147;  definition  of,  318;  how 
far  true,  319  ;  disproof  of,  32  r- 
330  ;  arguments  for  330  and 
foil. ;  and  Hedonism,  339,  369. 

Values,  theory  of,  367. 

Violence,  42. 

Virtue  not  our  end,  66  ;  relation 
to  happiness,  148  ;  virtues  aid 
vices  in  general,  595  ;  moral 
virtues,  604  ;  cardinal  virtu  fs, 
613. 

Vitality,  relation  to  pleasure 
308. 

Voluntariness,  relation  to 
•human  act,  33  ;  kinds  of,  34  ; 
indirect,  36. 

Will.  See  Voluntariness ;  Free- 
dom of;  1 75-1 8 1  ;  will-auto- 
nomy, theory  of,  657. 


LIST  OF   AUTHORS  REFERRED  TO 
IN  THIS  WORK 


Antisthenes,  277. 

Aquinas  (St.  Thomas),  on  scope 
of  Ethics,  1-4  ;  Eth.  and  Psy- 
chology, 8  ;  Eth.  and  Pol. 
Philosophy,  11  ;  on  passion  and 
voluntariness,  42  ;  the  ends  of 
human  action,  47-88  passim  ; 
good  and  evil,  80-100  passim  ; 
indifferent  acts,  100  ;  appetites, 
104-113  ;  criterion.  133  ;  moral- 
ity and  individual  act,  172  ; 
freedom,  178  ;  obligation,  214  ; 
relation  of  liberty  to  duty,  224  ; 
arguments  against  Hedonism, 
280  and  foil.;  Ethical  Hedon- 
ism, 301  ;  the  Utilitarian  prin- 
ciple, 320 ;  benevolent  im- 
pulses, 333  ;  life  as  final  end, 
423  ;  self-realisation,  463  ;  self- 
evident  moral  truths,  506-512  ; 
beauty  and  goodness,  528  ;  pun- 
ishment, 586  ;  the  moral  virtues 
610  ;  justice,  621  ;  the  eternal 
law,  639  ;  the  natural  law,  643  ; 
jus  gentium,  648. 

Aristippus,  276,  277. 

Aristotle,  object  of  Ethics,  8 ; 
certitude  in  morals,  23  ;  Ethics 
a  telcological  science,  46  ;  nature 
does  not  act  in  vain,  72  ;  man's 
final  end,  53,  70  ;  definition  of 
good,  90  ;  knowledge  and  evil- 
doing,  224  ;  pleasure  and  happi- 
ness, 275  ;  definition  of  virtue, 
597,  608  ;  otherwise  referred  to, 

34,  4<J>  148,  150,  154,  157,  460, 

580,  587,  599,  602. 
Augustine  (St.),  79,  148. 
AvEBURY  (Lord),  550-567  passim. 


Bain,  241,  33S,  350,  515. 


Baldwin,  364. 

Balfour  (A.),  25    157. 

Beneke,  238. 

Bentham,  29,  279,  319,  33S,  588. 

Bergbohm,  680. 

Bergson,  407. 

Blackstone,  650. 

Bradley,  62,  66,   89,   444,  452, 

458,  475,  587- 
Branco,  404. 
Brentano,  368. 

liROWN,   15,  480,  487. 

Browning,  70,  94. 
ISUNGE,  399. 
Burlamaqui,  480. 

BUSSEL,  24,  25,  27. 

Butler,  theory  of  punishment, 
203  ;  our  knowledge  of  duty, 
235  ;  Hedonism,  277  ;  self-love 
and  conscience,  278  ;  Hed. 
paradox,  292  ;  conscience,  476, 
498  ;  otherwise  referred  to,  371, 
479,  4S0,  588. 

Cairo  (E.),  498. 

Cairnes,  422. 

Cajetan,  71. 

Calderwood,  180,  208. 

Carneades,  115. 

Carneri,  357. 

Casalis,  563. 

Cathrein,  553,  680. 

Clarke,  15. 

Clifford,  491. 

Comte,  319. 

Cousin,  538. 

CuDwoRTH,  15,  278,  476. 

Cumberland,  157,  278,  319,  515. 

Damascene  (St.  John),  537. 
Darwin,  241,  399,  403. 


693 


694 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


De  Lage,  406. 
Denziger,  121. 
Dewey,  500. 
Driesch,  400. 
Du  Bois  Reymond,  397. 

Ehrenfels,  367. 
Elsenhans,  494,  553,  571- 
Epicurus,  278. 
Espenberger,  58. 

Fairbrother,  173. 

FiCHTE,  on  consciousness  of  duty, 
235  ;  proof  of  Formalism,  272  ; 
system  of  Ethics,  468  ;  differ- 
ences of  men's  moral  judgments, 
493  ;  otherwise  referred  to,  19, 
319,  443,  475,  480,  538,  571,  605. 

Flugel,  553,  568. 

FouiLLEE,  224,  239,  336,  356,  364, 
424,  533,  678. 

GizYCKi,  66,  350,  371. 

Goethe,  177. 

Grant,  (Sir  A.)  55,  225. 

Green,   55,   265,   293,   318,   445, 

461,  466. 
Grote  (John),  18. 
Grotius,  538. 
Guyau,  92, 235,  239, 247-252,  357. 

Halleux,  407. 

Hamilton,  180. 

Harms,  122. 

Hartmann  (Ed.  von),  60,  118, 
272,  282,  658. 

Hegel,  on  freedom,  192  ;  proof 
of  Formalism,  272  ;  system  of 
Ethics,  445-461  ;  on  conscience, 
491  ;  on  differences  of  men's 
moral  judgments,  494  ;  on  the 
formal  validity  of  laws,  651  ; 
on  coactivc  power  of  Right,  663; 
origin  of  Right,  677  ;  otherwise 
referred  to,  19,  29,  443. 

Herbart,  238,  446,  517,  525. 

Hertwig,  400. 

Hobbes,  theory  of  good  and  evil, 
114;  Hedonism,  276;  fust 
principles, 538  ;  origin  of  Right, 
O76  ;  otherwise  referred  to,  O78. 

Hume,  on  subject-matter  of 
Ethics,  3  ;  paradox  of  Formal- 
ism, 2()5  ;  selfishness,  279 ; 
moral  faculty,  475  and  foil.; 
rights  of  justice,  630. 


Hutcheson,  self-love,  279  ;  moral 
faculty,  475,  487  ;  intuitionism, 
517;  Aesthetic  Morals,  527; 
otherwise  referred  to,  16. 

Huxley,  398,  399,  4x9. 

Iiiering,  663. 

James,  255. 

JoDL,  446,  503,  517,  526. 

Jouffroy,  475. 

Kant,  nature  of  freedom,  190, 
204 ;  freedom  and  morality, 
201;  the  consciousness  of  duty, 
235  ;  deduction  of  liberty  from 
morality,  254  ;  formalism,  256 
and  foil.  ;  definition  of  beauty, 
528  ;  merit,  588,  590  ;  auton- 
omy of  Reason,  652  ;  perfect 
and  imperfect  duties,  668 ; 
rights  and  morality,  673  ;  origin 
of  Right,  676  and  foil.;  cate- 
gorical imperative,  see  '  auton- 
omy of  Reason,  and  appendix  to 
present  Vol.;  otherwise  men- 
tioned, 2,  II,  46,  66,  67,  72,  85, 
157,  171,  224,  538. 

KiTTEL,  571. 

Krause,  503. 

Laas,  493. 

Lamenais  (de),  153,  157. 

Lantsheere  (de),  23. 

Leibnitz,  538. 

Lessius,  121. 

Levy-Bruhl,  56,   115,   166,  353, 

424,  481,  549. 
Lewes,  404. 
Le  Roy,  556. 
Lipps,  231,  538,  657. 

LiTTRfe,   387. 

Livingstone,  553. 
Locke,  204,  278,  371,  517. 
Lombard  (Peter),  58. 

McCosH,  516. 
Macintosh,  338. 
Mackenzie,  29. 
Maher,  43,  181,  187,  479. 
Mali.ock,  54. 
Man,  554. 
Mandevili-e,  238. 
Mansell,  516. 


LIST  OF  AUTHORS 


695 


Martineau,  on  pity,  338  ;  evolu- 
tionist Ethics,  406  ;  intuition- 
ism,  517,  519  ;  aesthetic  Ethics, 
525  ;  his  system,  533  ;  merit, 
578  ;  otherwise  referred  to,  157. 

McDonald.     See  preface. 

Meinong,  367. 

Meyer,  77,  234. 

Mill  (James),  358. 

Mill  (J.  S.),  origin  of  idea  of  duty, 
241  ;  Hedonism,  276  ;  pleasure 
man's  end,  289 ;  qualitative 
distinctions  of  pleasure,  311; 
argument  foi  Utilitarianism, 
340;  Hed.  and  Util.,  370; 
origin  of  moral  judgments,  424  ; 
conscience,  480  ;  otherwise  re- 
ferred to,  29,  157,  538,  629. 

Milton,  583. 

MivART,  403. 

More  (Sir  T.),  19,  475. 

MuiRHEAD,  294. 

MULLER,  404. 

Neukamp,  670  and  foil. 
Newman,  502. 
Nietzsche,  117, 

Occam,  120. 

Paley,  279,  371,  515. 
Paulsen,  81,  119,  228,  242. 
Plato,  19,  277. 
Prescott,  553,  557. 
Puchta,  680. 

PUFFENDORF,   I2C,  538, 

Quatrefages  (do),  399. 

Rashdall,  differences  between 
crime  and  disease,  206  ;  Psy- 
chological Hed.,  291,  295,  297  ; 
the  hedonistic  usteron-proteron, 
297  ;  Util.,  341  ;  intuitionis-m, 
515,  523  ;  otherwise  referred  to, 
370,  587,  appendix  to  Vol  I. 

Ratzel,  553,  560  passim. 

Rauber,  365,  569,  570. 

R6e,  238,  549,  553. 

Reid,  15,  180,  279,  475,  487,  515, 

517- 
Renouvier,  239. 

RiCKABY   (Joseph),   222,  463. 
ROBINET,   487. 

Rousseau,  114,  216. 
ROYCE,  364,  424,  481,  580. 


Salmond,  649. 
Savigny,  672,  680. 
schelling,  235,  463,  680 
schiffini,  222,  649. 
Schiller,  195,  198,  525. 
Schleiermacher,  171,  497. 
Schopenhauer,   3,    70,    81,    151, 

338,  446. 

ScoTUS,  100. 

Secretan,  239. 

Seth,  299,  313,  371,  462,  515. 

Shaftesbury,  selfish  impulses, 
278,  319,  331  ;  Hed.  and  Util., 
371  ;  aesthetic  morals,  527  ; 
merit  and  virtue,  578  ;  other- 
wise referred  to,  15,  157. 

SiDGWicK,  on  natural  morals,  1 58  ; 
obligation,  228  ;  Psych.  Hedon- 
ism, 295  ;  Eth.  Hed.,  300  ; 
Utilitar.,  324  ;  Benevolence, 
334  ;  Hed.  and  Util.,  341  ; 
origin  and  validity,  440  ;  Intui- 
tionism,  515,  523  ;  punishment, 
589  ;  justice,  630  ;  otherwise 
referred  to,  15,  311. 

Sigwart,  18. 

Simmel,  52,  81,  82,  151,  171,  223, 
241,  580,  appendix  to  Vol  I. 

Smith  (Adam),  157. 

Socrates,  224. 

Sorley,  5,  6,  436,  440,  458. 

Spencer,  altraism  and  pleasure, 
152  ;  duty,  240,  241  ;  hedon- 
istic paradox,  293  ;  scientific 
hedonism,  308 ;  Benevolence, 
371  ;  geneial  account  of  his 
theory,  373  ;  origin  of  moral 
judgments,  424  ;  otherwsie  re- 
ferred to,  57,  120,  404,  538,  629. 

Spencer  and  Gillen,  554. 

Spinoza,  466,  676. 

Stahl,  651. 

Stephen  (Leslie),  on  final  end,  52  ; 
originality  of  the  appetites,  76  ; 
happiness  and  virtue,  152  ; 
punishment,  203  ;  benevolence, 
336 ;  individual  and  society, 
357 ;  general  account  of  his 
theory,  383  ;  conscience,  480, 
491  ;  merit,  578  ;  otherwise  re- 
ferred to, 165, 414, 538, 580,  636. 

Stirner,  276. 

SuAREZ,  121,  649. 

Taparelli,  222. 

Taylor  (A.  E.),  59,  242,  414,  457, 
491. 


696 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS 


Thomasius,  538,  663, 
Tolstoi,  151. 
Trendelenburg,  357. 
Tylor,  552. 
Tyndall,  398,  399. 

ViRCHOW,   398,  399. 

Waitz,  554,  566. 
Wake,  553. 
Warburton,  480. 


Ward  (W.  G.),  122. 

Wallace,  403. 

Walter,  676. 

Wasmann,  399,  400,  406. 

Wells  (H.  G.),  211. 

Westermarck,  553,  566. 

Whewell,  266,  272,  613. 

Wilson,  400. 

Wissmann,  554. 

WuNDT,  22,  179,  180,  241,  538. 

ZiGLIARA,   77,   128. 


END  OF  VOLUME  I. 


Af.  U.  Gill  and  Son,  Ltd.,  Printers,  Dublin, 


\  f 


>- 


ra  I  «  I  ^  I  )  ^ 


niMr  'S'j  tyclo 


B^WDfNG,i-iST    Jinv   1    join 


EJ  Cronin,  Michael 

1011  The  science  of  ethics 

r2d  ed.,    rev  and  -en^.-, 


C7 


v.l 
cop. 4. 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 


UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO 
LIBRARY